Üzüntü Kitabı İngilizce Kopya
Üzüntü Kitabı: DSM ve Psikiyatrinin Bozulması
Gary Greenberg
Chapter 1
Shortly
after New Orleans physician Samuel Cartwright discovered a new disease in 1850,
he realized that like all medical pioneers he faced a special burden. “In noticing a disease1
not heretofore classed among the long list of maladies that man is subject to,”
he told a gathering of the Medical Association of Louisiana, “it was necessary
to have a new term to express it.” Cartwright could have followed the example
of many of his peers and named the malady for himself, but he decided instead
to exercise the ancient Greek he’d learned while being educated in
Philadelphia. He took two words—drapetes, meaning
“runaway slave,” and the more familiar mania—and
fashioned drapetomania, “the
disease causing Negroes2 to run away.”
The new disease, Cartwright reported in The New Orleans Medical and Surgical Journal, had one diagnostic symptom—“absconding from service”—and a
few secondary ones, including a sulkiness and dissatisfaction that appeared
just prior to the slaves’ flight. Through careful observations made when he
practiced in Maryland, he developed a crude epidemiology and concluded that
environmental factors could play a role in the onset of drapetomania.
Two classes of persons were apt to lose their Negroes: those who made
themselves too familiar with them, treating them as equals; and on the other
hand those who treated them cruelly, denied them the common necessaries of
life, neglected to protect them, or frightened them by a blustering manner of
approach.
But the most evenhanded
treatment would not prevent all cases, and for those whose illness was “without
cause,” Cartwright had a prescription: “whipping
the devil4 out of them.”
Lest anyone doubt that drapetomania was a
real disease—and, evidently, some Northern doctors did—Cartwright offered
proof. First of all, he said, we know that Negroes are descended from the
people of Canaan, a name that means “submissive
knee-bender5,” so it’s clear what God had in
mind for the race. And in case a reader subscribed to the notion, taught in the
“northern hornbooks in Medicine6,”
that “the Negro is only a lampblacked white man . . . requiring nothing but
liberty and equality—social and political—to wash him white,” Cartwright called
as witnesses the prominent European doctors who had “demonstrated, by dissection7,
so great a difference between the Negro and the white man as to induce the
majority of naturalists to refer him to a different species.” Africans’ blood
was darker, he said, and “the membranes,
tendons, and aponeuroses8, so brilliantly white in the
Caucasian race, have a livid cloudiness in the African.” This historical and
biological evidence, Cartwright concluded, proved that running away is neither
willfulness nor the normal human striving for freedom, but illness plain and
simple.
Drapetomania was never considered for the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, the American Psychiatric Association’s compendium of mental
illnesses, but that may be only because there was no such book in 1850.
(Indeed, the Association of Superintendents of American Institutions for the
Insane, the organization that eventually became the APA, was only six years old
at the time, and the word psychiatry had just come
into use.) Certainly it met many of the criteria for inclusion. It was a
condition that caused distress for a certain group of people. It had a known
and predictable onset, course, and outcome. Its diagnostic criteria could be
listed in clear language that a doctor could use, for instance, to distinguish
normal stubbornness from pathological dissatisfaction, or to determine whether
a slave was running away because he was sick or just evil. Many people besides
Cartwright had observed it. Its discovery was announced in a respected
professional journal. Its definition was precise enough to allow other doctors
to develop tests that distinguished normal (or, as the DSM puts it, expectable) from disordered dissatisfaction, and to conduct
research that confirmed (or didn’t) that most runaway slaves had been sulky
prior to absconding, or that slaves treated too familiarly or too cruelly were
more likely to contract drapetomania, or that whipping prevented the disease
from running its full course. Still other doctors might have recommended
potions that would relieve its symptoms. As the years wore on, some doctors
might have objected that the disease pathologized a normal response to
atrocious conditions, while others might have fought bitterly and publicly over
smaller issues: whether or not defiance also belonged
on the list of criteria; whether to add Dr. Cartwright’s other discovery, dyaesthesia aethiopica9,
the malady causing slaves to “slight their work,” to the diagnostic manual;
which gene predisposed slaves to drapetomania and dyaesthesia; where the thirst
for freedom could be found in the brain; and, perhaps, whether or not these
were real illnesses or only constructs useful to understanding what Dr.
Cartwright called the “diseases and physical peculiarities of the Negro race.”
Dr. Cartwright’s disease, in short, and
the promise it held out—that a widely observed form of suffering with
significant impact on individuals and society could be brought under the light
of science, named and identified, understood and controlled, and certain thorny
moral questions about the nature of slavery sidestepped in the bargain—might
have spawned an entire industry. A small one, perhaps, but one that would have
no doubt been profitable to slave owners, to doctors, maybe even to slaves
grateful for their emancipation from their unnatural lust for freedom—and,
above all, to the corporation that owned the right to name and define our
psychological troubles, and to sell the book to anyone with the money to buy it
and the power to wield its names.
• • •
Even if you’re one of the
many people who are suspicious of psychiatry and skeptical of its claims to
have identified the varieties of our suffering and collected them in a single
volume, you might be thinking that I’m not being entirely fair here, that even
if the Civil War hadn’t come along ten years later and rendered Cartwright’s
outrageous invention moot, doctors would have quickly consigned drapetomania to
the dustbin of medical history. You might point out that even at the time
sensible people objected—Frederick Law Olmsted, for instance, whose Journeys and Explorations in the Cotton Kingdom includes a
mordant account of “the learned Dr. Cartwright10”
and his diseases, and the unnamed doctor who satirized Cartwright in the Buffalo Medical Journal by suggesting that drapetomania
occurs when “the nervous erythism11
of the human body is thrown into relations with the magnetic pole . . . thus
directing [the slave’s] footsteps northward.” You might say that in introducing
a book about the DSM with an anecdote about a diagnosis that is so obviously
specious, and in implying that this is somehow emblematic of the diagnostic
enterprise, I am taking a cheap shot.
And you may be right.
On the other hand, especially if you are a
gay person, you might not be so quick to think that drapetomania is merely a
low-hanging cherry that I’ve picked to flavor my tale. Because you might be old
enough to remember back forty or fifty years, to a time when homosexuality was
still listed in the DSM. Which meant that doctors could get paid to treat it,
scientists could search for its causes and cures, employers could shun its
victims, and families could urge them to seek help, even as gay people
conducted their intimacies in furtive encounters, lived in fear and shame, lost
jobs, forwent careers, and chained themselves to marriages they didn’t want. They underwent countless therapies12—shocks
to the brain and years on the couch, behavior modification and surrogate sex,
porn sessions that switched from homo to hetero at the crucial moment—in
desperate attempts to become who they could not be and to love whom they could
not love, to get free of their own deepest desires, all in the name of getting
well. And all this, at least in part, because a society’s revulsion had found
expression in the official diagnostic manual of a medical profession, where it
gained the imprimatur not of a church or a state, but of science. When doctors
said homosexuality was a disease, that was not an opinion, let alone bigotry.
It was a fact. When they wrote that fact down in the DSM, it was not a
denunciation. It was a diagnosis.
Or maybe you’re among the 11 percent of the U.S. adult population13
whose daily regimen includes taking a dose or two of Lexapro or Paxil or some
other antidepressant, and you’ve been doing that for years, ever since a doctor
told you that you had Major Depressive Disorder (or maybe she just said you had
clinical depression), meaning that your sulkiness and dissatisfaction were
symptoms of a mental disorder, and that this was a chemical imbalance that
those drugs would fix. And maybe they did, because at least for a little while
you felt better; but then you got tired of
feeling numb14, of gaining weight, of not wanting
sex and not being able to have an orgasm even if you did; and then you tried to
get off the drugs only to find that your brain off drugs is an unruly thing,
that your old difficulties returned or new ones arose when you stopped taking
them. Which might mean, you told yourself, that you indeed have that disease,
but every once in a while—when you read about the placebo effect15, or you hear
that this chemical imbalance does not, as far
as doctors know16, really exist, or when you look at
the DSM and realize that there are more than
seventy combinations of symptoms17 that can result
in this one diagnosis and that any two people with the diagnosis may have only
one symptom in common—you wonder whether what your doctor told you is true and
whether you have now changed your brain chemistry, perhaps irreversibly, to
cure a disease that doesn’t exist.
Or maybe you’re a parent of a child who
drove you to despair with his tantrums and defiance, whom you took to doctor
after doctor until finally you found the one who told you that he had Bipolar
Disorder, but that this was really good news, because that disease could be
cured with a daily dose of Depakote or Risperdal. And sure enough, your kid
calmed down, but now he weighs twice what he should and there’s sugar in his
urine and dark circles under his eyes, and you’re beginning to think—especially
since you heard about how drug industry money influenced doctors to make that
diagnosis and how pharmaceutical companies still haven’t fully tested these
drugs on children and how doctors massaged those diagnostic criteria to fit
your kid—that maybe your psychiatrist was wrong when he said that Bipolar
Disorder is the same kind of disease as diabetes, a chemical problem that you
leave untreated only if you are a bad parent.
Or maybe you’re like me—a mental health
professional who has been faithfully filling out insurance forms for thirty
years, jotting down those five-digit codes from the DSM that open the money
taps, rendering diagnoses even though you are pretty sure you’re not treating
medical conditions, and for just a moment you hesitate, contemplating the bad
faith of pouring a lie into the foundation of a relationship whose main and
perhaps only value is that it provides an opportunity to look someone in the
eye and, without fear of judgment or the necessity to manipulate, speak the
truth. And, having contemplated it, you tell yourself whatever story you have
to and you sign the paper, and the best you can do is to curse the DSM in a
kind of incantation against your own bad faith.
Or maybe you’ve never had truck with the
mental health industry, but the other day you were talking with a friend and
explaining to her that you had to wash your dishes before you could leave your
house, and you found yourself saying, “I’m just so OCD, you know?” Or you’ve
heard your friends do the same thing with their own or others’ quirks. “He’s
pretty ADHD,” they might say. Or, “She’s clinically depressed.” Or, “Sorry,
that’s just my PTSD.” And maybe you’ve been brought up short by the way the
DSM’s lingo has infiltrated our self-understanding or wondered what it says
about us that we describe the habits of our hearts in a pastiche of medical
clichés.
If you are one of those people, which is
to say if you have had occasion to take the DSM seriously (and even the book’s
most ardent defenders will tell you this was your first mistake), then you may
be sympathetic to my rhetorical move. You may understand that Dr. Cartwright
did what he did because he could, because the power to give names to our pain
is a mighty thing and easy to abuse. Cartwright seems to have intended to serve
the interests of slave owners and white supremacists and their economic system
by providing “another [of ] the ten thousand18
evidences of the fallacy of the dogma abolition is built on,” but surely the
doctors who insisted that homosexuality was a disease were not all bigots or
prudes. Nor are the doctors who today diagnose with Hoarding Disorder people
who fill their homes with newspapers and empty pickle jars, but leave
undiagnosed those who amass billions of dollars while other people starve,
merely toadying to the wealthy. They don’t mean to turn the suffering inflicted
by our own peculiar institutions, the depression and anxiety spawned by the
displacements of late capitalism and postmodernity, into markets for a
criminally avaricious pharmaceutical industry.
The prejudices and fallacies behind
psychiatric diagnoses, and even the interests they serve, are as invisible to
all of us, doctors and patients alike, as they were to Dr. Cartwright’s New
Orleanian colleagues or to all those doctors who “treated” homosexuals. The
desire to relieve suffering can pull a veil over our eyes. And sometimes it
takes an incendiary example or two to rip that veil away.
• • •
So I apologize for my cheap
shot. I apologize to the epidemiologists and sociologists alarmed by
ever-rising rates of mental illness and disability; and to the patients who
have benefited from a diagnosis; and to the interested civilians who have the
intuition that there is such a thing as mental illness, that it belongs under
the purview of medicine and that as such it ought to be cataloged, whatever the
difficulties; and to the doctors who can argue cogently that the advantages of
doing so far outweigh the costs. I apologize to the reasonable folks who think,
reasonably, that the DSM is the culmination of a lot of honest hard work by
smart and well-intentioned people doing their best at an impossible task, and
that it should be given the benefit of the doubt. I apologize to the people who
acknowledge that even if the DSM is not the Bible it’s cracked up to be, it
still, as the backbone of a medical specialty that has done yeoman service,
deserves its authority over our inner lives.
But that doesn’t mean I’m sorry. By apologize, I mean what the ancient Greeks meant. I mean to
explain. Because I think drapetomania is not a historical novelty or an anomaly
or an accident. It is not the exceptional error that proves the rule that
science is self-correcting and will ultimately punish arrogance and
incompetence. The story of drapetomania is a cautionary tale, just as the ones
about homosexuality and childhood Bipolar Disorder are, and just as the story
about a disorder that sits quietly today in the DSM-5 (my vote is for Internet
Use Disorder) will be in some tomorrow. All these stories tell us why our inner
lives are too important to leave in the hands of doctors: because they don’t
know as much about us as they claim, because a full account of human nature is
beyond their ken.
While I’m explaining myself, let me tell
you a story.
In 2012, I got a voice-mail message from a
former patient; I’ll call him Sandy. I last saw him about ten years ago. I’d
worked with him from the time he was in his junior year in high school until he
finished his graduate studies. He’d been plagued by anxiety so severe that he
was unable to attend school and, eventually, to leave his house at all. Early
on in therapy, he’d told me that he was sure he was gay, and that this was what
had led him to hole up in his room contemplating suicide as the preferable
alternative to what his parents and pastor, who hadn’t deleted homosexuality
from their book of sins, called “the gay lifestyle.” We talked about this, and
more generally about what therapists and patients talk about: parents, friends,
regrets, confusion, and fear. I can’t tell you why, but therapy worked, at
least enough to get him to overcome his self-loathing and his parents’
disapproval and to come out, in all senses of that phrase. Last I knew, he had
a job and a life in a faraway city. He could work, love, and stay alive, which,
by my lights, is about all we can ask for. He kept in touch sporadically via
e-mail or phone to tell me what he was up to or to let me know he’d seen
something I’d written in a magazine.
The message went like this:
“I know I shouldn’t call you, and I
promise I won’t call you again. But you’ve got to help me. They’ve sucked all
the bones out of my body. I’m here in this hotel room and my bones are gone. My
mother and my father and James. They’ve done this to me. And I don’t want to
die. Please don’t let them kill me. Don’t let them. You’re the only one who can
help. You know I love you, and I love Ellen Goldstein, too. Good-bye.
Good-bye.” (I made up those names.)
He didn’t leave a number, but according to
caller ID, he was calling from a Holiday Inn a thousand miles from where, as
far as I knew, he had last been living. Sandy had checked out by the time I
tried to return the call. I don’t know where he went next. But I am pretty sure
about one thing: his parents and James, whoever he was, did not suck the bones
out of his body, and they probably weren’t about to cook Sandy up in a stew, or
whatever he was sure they were going to do. I would guess they didn’t even know
where he was. I’m not even sure Sandy knew where he was. As I write this, I
still don’t know what became of him.
Now, if you’re like me and most everyone I
know, the first thing that you think when you hear a story like this is that
Sandy is mentally ill. But what do we mean when we say this?
The first answer is that he is crazy. That
is, he is behaving in a way that is abnormal, bizarre, out of touch with
reality. The technical term here is psychotic or delusional. I think this is self-evident, and even if I
didn’t care about Sandy, I wouldn’t think it is benign, a sane response to an
insane world, say, or some salutary plunge into the collective unconscious. He
was in trouble; he was, as the current jargon goes, dysfunctional;
his inner life had gone haywire; he needed help.
But what kind of trouble? And what kind of
help?
This brings us to the second answer: that
his craziness is best understood as the manifestation of a disease that is
medical in nature, that is in some essential way no different from all the
other diseases that afflict us, and that is best left to doctors to understand
and treat.
We have become accustomed to thinking of disease in a very specific way: as a pathology of the body,
something gone wrong in our tissues or our cells or our molecules. You secrete
too much of this or don’t produce enough of that, or the rate of the other
thing is too high or low, and that is why you can’t walk up stairs without
losing breath, or why you are in pain or are losing weight, and why, if you
don’t do what the doctor says to do, if you don’t take his pill or let him
plunge his scalpel into your skin or drip poison into your veins, you will
continue to suffer, or your suffering will get worse, or you will die.
But before you will submit to the cure,
you have to believe that the doctor knows something about your pain that you do
not, that she can identify that disease, that she is on familiar terms with it,
that she knows it by name. She must, in other words, give you a diagnosis.
Diagnosis, not
unlike drapetomania, comes from two Greek words,
meaning “to learn” and “apart.” It is a knowledge that sorts one thing from
another. The Greeks understood how hard it is to parse the world, especially
when it comes to complex experiences. “Love
is a madness19,” Socrates tells Phaedrus, and to
understand that madness, to untangle it from other experiences, he says that
two principles must be upheld. “First, the comprehension of scattered
particulars in one idea” that is clearly and consistently described. But,
Socrates continues, we can’t gather the particulars together under just any
idea. No matter how vividly described or comprehensive the categories, and no
matter how well they seem to cohere, they must also be fashioned “according to
the natural formation, where the joint is, not breaking any part as a bad
carver might.” A good diagnosis must be more than the fancy of the
diagnostician, more than merely deft. It must also be accurate. It must carve
nature at its joints.
What is true for the madness that is love
is true for any madness at all—or, for that matter, any suffering that doctors
purport to understand. The diagnostician’s job is to find the disease that
unites the scattered symptoms and makes them manifest in precisely the way they
do, to say with certainty that this distress is the result of that illness and
no other. The diagnostic enterprise hinges on an optimistic notion: that
disease is part of a natural world that only awaits our understanding. But even
if this is true, nature gives up its secrets grudgingly, and our finite senses
are in some ways ill suited to extracting them. More important, our prejudices
lead us to tear nature where we want it to break. Science, especially modern
medicine, is founded on this equally optimistic idea: that experts can purge
their inquiry of prejudice and desire, and map the landscape of suffering along
its natural boundaries.
Greek doctors, as it turned out, were not
so good at this. They had some ideas about what those natural formations were,
largely having to do with four bodily humors—blood, bile, phlegm, and
melancholy—that, if thrown out of balance, could cause illness. But humoral
theory was more metaphysics and wishful thinking than truth. Even Hippocrates
and his disciples seemed to know this, as they traded mostly in empiricism—the painstaking observation of the way symptoms
appeared to the doctor’s senses, the courses they took, the outcomes they
reached, and the interventions that affected them.
In the nineteenth century, most doctors
still believed that humoral imbalances caused disease. Before John Snow20 could persuade
the local government to close the infected well that caused the 1854 cholera
outbreak in London, he had to overcome the common idea that the disease was
carried by a miasma, bad air that could upset humoral
balance. Louis Pasteur and Robert Koch21
had to work hard to convince their colleagues that germs caused diseases like
rabies and anthrax, and that they (the germs, not the colleagues) could be
targeted and killed. As the microscope and the chemical assay provided
incontrovertible evidence of germs and their destruction, doctors were won over
to the germ theory, and soon it seemed that they had begun to fulfill Socrates’
dictum to find the natural joints that separated our ills from one another.
By the turn of the twentieth century, doctors
were stalking disease like Sherlock Holmes stalked criminals. Under the
magnification of their microscopes, syphilis, diabetes, and streptococcus, to
name just a few, soon yielded their secrets and their terrifying hold on us.
With their newfound ability to parse suffering, to track it down to the bodily
processes causing it, and then to dispatch it with a potion or a surgery,
doctors gained prestige—and with it, money and power. They were rewarded as
much for their prowess in relieving suffering as for the promise they now
embodied: that they could use science to give a name to someone’s suffering and
then, having named it, to relieve it.
This revolution in medicine accounts in
part for the immense appeal of considering craziness to be just another disease.
If scientific understanding and cure were possible for the suffering of the
body, then why not for the suffering of the mind? If Sandy’s conviction that
his bones have been sucked out of his body is some kind of metaphor, if the
content of his delusion brims with meaning—an expression of impotence, a lack
of backbone, an inability to hold himself up—then it is out of the reach of the
microscope and the X-ray. It requires what the ancient doctors offered:
interpretation and the invocation of metaphysics, of something beyond the
symptom. But if the delusion is only another symptom, if it is not, in
principle, different from the malaise and relentless thirst of an untreated
diabetic, or the narrowing of vision of a glaucoma patient, or the fever of
someone with malaria, then it can be brought under the physician’s purview. It
doesn’t need to be understood in itself any more than fever or thirst does. It
can be explained, it can be treated, and it can be cured.
If you’ve gotten sick or injured and a
doctor has restored you to health or if you’ve seen this happen to someone
else—and who hasn’t?—then you know the lure of this promise. If you’ve watched
your child descend into psychosis or your husband spin out into mania or
yourself struggle to get off the bed onto which depression has laid you, then
you know it even better.
On the other hand, if you’ve been involved
with the mental health industry, then you probably also know that the promise
is not always fulfilled. Even if doctors can settle on a name for Sandy’s
illness—and this is not a sure thing; they are likely to be torn between
Schizophrenia and Bipolar Disorder—they will not be able to scratch out a
prescription, tell him to take two and call in the morning. He may end up
taking a drug indicated for a different diagnosis, or a cocktail of pills—one
to quell his hallucinations, one to temper his agitation, one to relieve his
depression, and one to help him sleep—and the combination may change monthly or
even weekly, or it may work for a while and then stop. No one will be able to
explain why that happened, any more than they will be able to explain why the
drugs worked in the first place. No honest psychiatrist will claim that she
cured Sandy’s, or anyone’s, mental illness; and while she is being honest, she
may acknowledge that, for the most part, her treatments are targeted at
symptoms, not diseases, and that she selects them as much by intuition and
experience as by scientific evidence.
But psychiatry’s appeal is not just about
the possibility of cure, which is why the profession continues to flourish even
when it cures nothing and relieves symptoms only haphazardly. It’s in the
naming itself. What Wallace Stevens called the “blessed
rage to order22” is so deep in us that it is in
our origin story: the first thing the Bible’s authors have Adam and Eve23 do to establish
their dominion over Eden is to name its flora and fauna. That story doesn’t
have a happy ending, and neither does the one I’m about to tell you (although
in the latter case, there is good reason for that). But the rage itself is
surely blessed, or at least as blessed as we humans can be, and as noble. Give
a name to suffering, perhaps the most immediate reminder of our insignificance
and powerlessness, and suddenly it bears the trace of the human. It becomes
part of our story. It is redeemed.
• • •
But what kind of story? And
what kind of names?
The DSM-IV, the most recent edition of the
manual,* sorts psychiatric problems into chapters like “Mood
Disorders” and “Feeding and Eating Disorders” and from there into individual
illnesses like Major Depressive Disorder (MDD) or Bulimia Nervosa, each of
which might have its own specifiers, so that a complete diagnosis might read
Major Depressive Disorder, Recurrent, Severe, with Melancholic Features. For
each disorder, criteria are listed. There are, for instance, nine criteria for
a Major Depressive Episode; if you meet five of them, then you have fulfilled
the necessary condition for that diagnosis; and if you meet four others in
addition, then you have sufficient symptoms to earn the MDD label. In addition
to the criteria, the DSM supplies text, a
not-quite-narrative account of the prevalence, family and gender patterns, and
other associated features of the disorder, and instructs doctors how to
differentiate among disorders that resemble one another. Depending on how you
count—whether or not you consider each subtype its own disorder, for
instance—the DSM-IV lists around three hundred disorders in its nearly one
thousand pages.
You could think of the DSM as a handbook
designed to help doctors recognize the varieties of psychological travail, not
unlike the way Audubon’s field guides help ornithologists recognize birds. You
could think of it, as some people (especially its critics) do, as the Bible of
psychiatry, providing a scriptural basis for the profession. You could think of
it—and this is what the APA would like you to do with the DSM-5*—as a living document, akin to the U.S. Constitution, a
set of generalizations about the present, flexible and yet lasting enough to
see an institution into the future. Or you could think of the DSM as a
collection of short stories about our psychological distress, an anthology of
suffering. You could think of it as the book of our woes.
All of these work; I favor the last one,
but then again, I’m hardly unprejudiced, and even I have to admit that the DSM
barely qualifies as literature. It’s lacking in plot, and it bears all the
traces of having been written by committee; it is, as Henry James said of the
nineteenth-century novel, a “loose, baggy
monster24.” But then again, unlike the works
of Tolstoy and Thackeray, the DSM belongs to a genre that is forgiving of poor
writing, that ends up inviting and rewarding it. The book avoids the Latinate
jargon that physicians tend to favor, but it is written by doctors and designed
to be used in medical offices and hospitals around the world; it is a medical
text. Which, nowadays anyway, means it is a scientific text, one that casts its
subjects into dry, data-driven stories, freed from the vagaries of hope and
desire, of prejudice and ignorance and fear, and anchored instead in the laws
of nature.
• • •
I’m not sure that this is the
right genre for understanding us, and I’m not alone in my doubts. Psychiatry
didn’t always have dominion over the landscape of mental suffering, at least
not the kind that shows up in everyday life. Psychiatrists, once known as
“alienists,” originally presided over asylums housing people too crazy to
function outside them. The treatments the doctors doled out, if they doled out
any at all, varied from hospital to hospital and took place largely out of the
view of polite society. Psychiatrists did not appear on television to give
relationship advice. They did not suggest ways to beat the winter blues. They
did not prescribe cocktails of psychoactive drugs to accountants and
schoolteachers while telling them what they suffered from.
Not that there weren’t doctors doing those
things or their equivalents. But most of them were neurologists like George
Beard, who suggested, toward the end of the nineteenth century, that symptoms
ranging from “insomnia, flushing, drowsiness25,
bad dreams” through “ticklishness, vague pains and flying neuralgias” to
“exhaustion after defecation” added up to a disease that, in his bestselling American Nervousness, he christened neurasthenia.
Or Silas Weir Mitchell, author of the bestselling Fat
and Blood, his account of how to treat neurasthenia and hysteria (the
details of which I won’t go into; just use your imagination on the title and
you’ll get the idea), who was the inspiration for “The Yellow Wallpaper,”
Charlotte Perkins Gilman’s famous fictionalized account of the rest cure she took at his hands. Or John Harvey Kellogg, who teamed
up with his industrialist brother, Will, to introduce America’s fatigued brain
workers to the wonders of flaked cereals, electric light baths, and pelvic
massage. Or Sigmund Freud, whose ideas about intrapsychic conflict as the
source of psychological turmoil, which he called neurosis, landed on American
soil (along with Freud himself) in 1909.
Whatever the merits of their particular
theories, these doctors had one thing in common. People flocked to them, to the
spas where nurses swaddled them for their naps, to the offices where they were
shocked or steamed or vibrated, and to the analysts’ couches where they
disburdened themselves of their family secrets and lurid fantasies. The
everyday psychopathology of the masses was a burgeoning and protean market,
especially among the swelling ranks of the affluent; and doctors, armed with
the authority of the microscope and the pharmacy, had seized it.
The enormous opportunity created by the
democratizing of mental illness, and exploited by neurologists, was not lost on
psychiatrists. In the first third of the twentieth century, they began to
escape the asylum, setting out mostly for private offices, where they, too,
began to minister to the walking wounded, mostly by practicing psychoanalysis.
Their colleagues/competitors included neurologists, but they also included
anthropologists and art historians and social workers—nonmedical people who had
been trained in psychoanalysis and had hung out their shingles. Given the
ascendant power of medicine, these lay analysts might well have failed to
capture much of the market from doctors, but the New York Psychoanalytic
Society, dominated by psychiatrists, was not content to wait for the invisible
hand to lift them to dominance. In 1926, for reasons it didn’t spell out
explicitly, it declared that only physicians could practice psychoanalysis.
Back in Vienna, Freud, who had long
loathed America as a land of the shallow and unsophisticated, was livid. “As long as I live26,”
he thundered, “I shall balk at having psychoanalysis swallowed by medicine.” He
spelled out the reasons for his objections in The Question of
Lay Analysis. Medical education, he wrote, was exactly the wrong
training for the therapist’s job. “It burdens
[a doctor27] with too much . . . of which he
can never make use, and there is a danger of its diverting his interest and his
whole mode of thought from the understanding of psychical phenomena.” Instead
of learning from “the mental sciences28,
from psychology, the history of civilization and sociology,” Freud wrote,
would-be physician analysts would learn only “anatomy, biology and the study of
evolution.” They would thus be subject to “the temptation to flirt with
endocrinology and the autonomous nervous system,” and to turn psychoanalysis
into just another “specialized branch of medicine, like radiology.”
Steeped in the wrong genre, Freud worried,
doctors would not provide the densely layered readings of their patients’
suffering that he had offered in his essays on subjects like melancholia and
narcissism, in case studies about delusional characters like the Wolf Man and
the Rat Man, and in books declaring the significance of the seemingly
insignificant, of dreams and jokes and slips of the tongue. They would not try,
as analysts surely would, to understand the reason Sandy thought someone had
sucked out his bones, as opposed to the infinity of other delusions he could
have had. Instead, they would offer the kind of cure suggested in their medical
texts, the kind that doesn’t care what, if anything, the delusion itself might
actually mean.
Freud might not have minded that first
DSM, which was issued in 1952, thirteen years after his death. He might have
recognized his legacy in the names of the sections—“Disorders of Psychogenic
Origin” and “Psychoneurotic Disorders”—and of diagnoses such as anxiety
reaction and sexual deviation. He might have been
pleased by the literary descriptions, steeped in psychoanalysis, which turned
up, for instance, in the definition of depressive reaction as
the result of “the patient’s ambivalent
feeling29 toward his loss.” Buoyed by the
continued presence in the book’s 132 pages of his notion that the mind was a
host of inchoate and often contradictory feelings, Freud might have been
willing to acknowledge that his forecast of a hostile takeover of
psychoanalysis by medicine had been wrong. He might even have admired his
descendants for their cleverness in avoiding that fate and yet still claiming
the perquisites of the doctor, for having figured out how to have it both ways.
But Freud might also have predicted that
it was only a matter of time before the strain between the reductive impulse of
medicine and the expansive nature of psychoanalysis raised internal havoc. The
problems began in 1949, before the first DSM was published, when a psychologist showed30
that psychiatrists presented with the same information about the same patient
agreed on a diagnosis only about 20 percent of the time. By 1962, despite various attempts31
to solve this problem, clinicians still were agreeing less often than they
disagreed, at least according to a major study. In 1968, at just around the
time the second edition of the DSM came out, research showed that for any given
psychotic patient, doctors in Great Britain32
were more likely to render a diagnosis of manic depression than schizophrenia,
while doctors in the United States tended to do the opposite—a difference that
was obviously more about the doctors than the patients.
In the meantime, one of psychiatry’s own
had turned against it. Thomas Szasz, an upstate New York doctor with a
libertarian bent, argued in The Myth of Mental Illness (1961)
that psychiatrists had mistaken “problems of living”—the age-old complaints
that characterize our inner lives—for medical illnesses, and the result was a
loss of personal responsibility (and a sweetening of the pot for doctors). Also
in the early 1960s, Erving Goffman and Michel
Foucault33, among other academics, chimed in
with their view that mental illness was more sociological than medical, and
that psychiatrists were pathologizing deviancy rather than turning up genuine
illness—which they (along with Szasz) believed existed only in cases where
physiological pathology could be identified as the source of the trouble.
The arguments about diagnostic agreement
and the nature of mental illness might have remained arcane academic topics had
it not been for a Stanford sociologist, David Rosenhan, who, in 1972, sent a
cadre of healthy graduate students to various emergency rooms with the same
vague complaint: that they were hearing a voice in their heads that said
“Thud.” All the students were admitted with a diagnosis of schizophrenia, and
although they acted normally once they were hospitalized (or normally for
graduate students; they spent much of their time making notes, behavior that
was duly jotted down in their charts as indicative of their illness), the
diagnosis was never recanted. Some were released by doctors, and others had to
be rescued from the hospital by their colleagues, but all were discharged with
a diagnosis of Schizophrenia, in Remission.
Rosenhan’s recounting of his exploit, “On
Being Sane in Insane Places,” appeared in the January 1973 edition of Science. Later that year, gay activists, including some
psychiatrists, after years of increasingly public and contentious debate,
finally persuaded the APA to remove homosexuality from the DSM—a good move, no
doubt, but one that, especially after what had happened to the graduate
students, couldn’t help but reveal that even when psychiatrists did agree on a
diagnosis, they might have been diagnosing something that wasn’t an illness.
Or, to put it another way, psychiatrists didn’t seem to know the difference
between sickness and health.
Forty years, two full rewrites, and two interim
revisions of the DSM later, they still don’t. Psychiatrists have gotten better
at agreeing on which scattered particulars they will gather under a single
disease label, but they haven’t gotten any closer to determining whether those
labels carve nature at its joints, or even how to answer that question. They
have yet to figure out just exactly what a mental illness is, or how to decide
if a particular kind of suffering qualifies. The
DSM instructs users34 to determine not only that a
patient has the symptoms listed in the book (or, as psychiatrists like to put
it, that they meet the criteria), but that the
symptoms are “clinically significant.” But the book doesn’t define that term,
and most psychiatrists have decided to stop fighting about it in favor of an
I-know-it-when-I-see-it definition (or saying that the mere fact that someone
makes an appointment is evidence of clinical significance). Instead, they argue
over which mental illnesses should be admitted to the DSM and which symptoms
define them, as if reconfiguring the map will somehow answer the question of
whether the territory is theirs to carve up.
This kind of argument leads to all sorts
of interesting drama, much of which you will soon be reading about, but none of
it can answer the question I posed about Sandy: Is disease
really the best way to understand his craziness? How
much of our suffering should we turn over to our doctors—especially our
psychiatrists?
I don’t know the answer to that question.
But neither do psychiatrists. Even in a case as florid as Sandy’s, they cannot
say exactly how they know he has a mental illness, let alone what disorder he
has or what treatment it warrants or why the treatment works (if it does),
which means that they cannot say why his problem belongs to them. That’s no
secret. Any psychiatrist worth his or her salt will freely acknowledge (and
frequently bemoan) the absence of blood tests or brain scans or any other
technology that can anchor diagnosis in a reality beyond the symptoms. What
they are more circumspect about is the disquieting implication of this
ignorance: that if a physician wants to claim that drapetomania and
homosexuality and, as the DSM-5 has proposed, at one time or another,
Hypersexuality and Internet Use Disorder and Binge Eating Disorder are
medical illnesses, there is nothing to stop him from doing so and if he is
shrewd and lucky and smart enough to persuade his colleagues to follow him, the
insurers, the drug companies, the regulators, the lawyers, the judges, and,
eventually, the rest of us will have no choice but to go along.
So while the psychiatrists who author the
DSM and I share an ignorance about how much of our inner travail should be
considered illness, only the psychiatrists have the power to decide, and only
the American Psychiatric Association claims those decisions as intellectual
property that is theirs to profit from. That’s why I think you should be more
disturbed by their ignorance than mine. After all, if the people who write the
DSM don’t know which forms of suffering belong in it, and can’t say why, then
on what grounds can the next instance in which prejudice and oppression are
cloaked in the doctor’s white coat be recognized? Or, to put it more simply,
why should we trust them with all the authority they’ve been granted?
• • •
That’s a question that
psychiatrist Allen Frances has been asking recently. Frances knows a great deal
about power and psychiatry. Indeed, The New York Times
once called him “perhaps the most powerful psychiatrist
in America35.” That was in 1994, when Frances,
who then headed the psychiatry department at Duke University School of
Medicine, was chair of the DSM-IV task force, the APA committee responsible for
that revision. He’s retired now, and not as powerful, but he’s a lot more
famous, mostly because he has spent the last four years waging a scorched-earth
campaign against his successors, largely on the grounds that they are abusing
their power. He’s warned anyone who will listen that the DSM-5 will turn even
more of our suffering into mental illness and, in turn, into grist for the
pharmaceutical mill.
Frances is seventy years old, a big,
swarthy man with a prominent brow set off by a shock of white hair. I once
heard a bartender tell him he looked like a cross between Cary Grant and
Spencer Tracy. The bartender may have been flirting or fishing for a bigger
tip, but he had one thing right: Frances, like those stars, exudes charm and
authority in equal measure. He’s soft-spoken, his voice high and reedy, and his
patter is compulsively self-effacing, but like certain dangerous animals, he’s
unpredictable, and always ready to spring.
I hadn’t known Frances for very long
before he said something to me that he came to regret. It was just before dawn
on a morning in August 2010. He’d finished his workout and cracked open his
first Diet Coke of the day in the kitchen of the California home he shares with
his psychiatrist wife, Donna Manning. The jihad Frances had launched against
his former colleagues had made him appealing to magazines like Wired, which had sent me to get the skinny on this loyalist
denouncing the new regime. Since I’d arrived the day before, he’d been giving
it to me, volubly and forcefully; and now we returned to one of the recurring
themes of yesterday’s conversation: the way the DSM seemed to grant
psychiatrists dominion over the entire landscape of mental suffering, a perch
from which they could proclaim as a mental disorder any aberration they could
describe systematically. I asked him whether he thought a good definition of
mental disorder would establish the bright boundary that would sort the sick
from the unusual, and thus keep psychiatry in its proper place.
“Here’s
the problem36,” Frances said. “There is no
definition of a mental disorder.”
I mentioned that that hadn’t stopped him
from putting one into the DSM-IV, or the people who were then making the DSM-5
from fiddling with it.
“And it’s bullshit,” he said. “I mean you
can’t define it.”
This was the comment that Frances would
come to regret—or at least, when it appeared in the
lead of the Wired article37,
to regret having said to me. He soon found himself explaining it—to other
writers, to his mildly titillated grandchildren, to attorneys who used it to
discredit his testimony as a forensic expert, and, worst of all from his point
of view, to Scientologists and other opponents of psychiatry who used it to
draft Frances into their cause. Frances never quite blamed me for having turned
his words into aid and comfort to the enemy. But even so, he was pretty sore
about it, especially, he said, because my use of his words might encourage
mentally ill people to go off their medications. I had turned him into my
Charlie McCarthy, he complained—not by putting words in his mouth, but by
throwing my tone into his voice.
I’m sure Frances would have used a
different phrase if he’d thought about it. He didn’t intend to dismiss the
diagnostic enterprise, let alone all of psychiatry, but rather to say only that
it is impossible to find that bright line and probably not worth the bother,
that a good clinician can be trusted to determine significance and then, with
the help of a decent diagnostic manual, figure out which disorder to diagnose
and get on with the treatment. He was shooting from the hip, and even though I
don’t regret reporting his comment, I can see why he wishes I hadn’t.
On the other hand, metaphors often have
significance beyond their author’s intent, although, as Freud pointed out,
sometimes analysis is required to ferret it out. Fortunately for us, there is a
philosopher of bullshit. His name is Harry Frankfurt, and he’s taught at Yale
and Princeton, and in 2005 he published a tiny gem of a book called On Bullshit. “Bullshit is
unavoidable38 whenever circumstances require
someone to talk without knowing what he is talking about,” writes Frankfurt.
“Thus the production of bullshit is stimulated whenever a person’s obligations
or opportunities to speak about some topic exceed his knowledge of the facts
relevant to that topic.” Filling in the gap between opportunity and knowledge
requires the bullshitter to stand “neither on
the side of the true39 nor on the side of the false,” he
adds. “His eye is not on the facts at all, as the eyes of the honest man and of
the liar are, except insofar as they may be pertinent to his interest in
getting away with what he says.”
For the last fifteen years, some of the
smartest psychiatrists in the world, people who have studied diagnosis for
their entire careers, people motivated, at least in part, by the desire to
relieve suffering, have worked longer and harder, and taken more fire, than
they ever expected as they revised the DSM-IV. But if you ask any one of them
(and I have asked many) about the DSM’s diagnoses and criteria—new and old—he
or she will tell you they are only “fictive placeholders” or “useful
constructs,” the best the profession can do with the knowledge and tools at
hand. They are fully aware, in other words, that their opportunity (although
they may call it an obligation) to name and describe our psychological suffering
far exceeds their knowledge. They have intentionally, if unhappily, stood on
the side of neither the true nor the false, and for the sixty years since the
first DSM was published, they have gotten away with it.
I don’t mean to say that the DSM is
nothing more than bullshit, or that the APA is merely trying to hoodwink us in
order to maintain its franchise or make a buck (or a hundred million of them,
which is what the DSM-IV has earned it). That would be as glib as tarring the
entire diagnostic enterprise with Dr. Cartwright’s brush. And as uninteresting:
finding bullshit in a professional guild’s attempt to strengthen its market
position would be no more remarkable than discovering gambling in Casablanca.
But what are neither glib nor uninteresting are the circumstances that make it
necessary and possible for the 150 men and women on the DSM-5 task force and
work groups to have it both ways, to manufacture fiction and yet act as if it
were fact. If the story of the DSM-5 has any redeeming value, if it is more
than a story about parochial disputes and internecine warfare, it is that it
can reveal the conditions that motivate the publication of the DSM and the
interests that another revision serves.
Some of those circumstances are
straightforward enough, and depressingly banal. If fully 10 percent of your
guild’s revenue, and an uncountable amount of your authority, depend on a
single book, a book that once saved your profession from oblivion and since
then has brought it fabulous riches, you don’t give it up easily. But other
circumstances are less obvious and more dangerous, and the idea that gives
psychiatry the power to name our pain in the first place—that the mind can be
treated like the body, that it is no more or less than what the brain does,
that it can be carved at its joints like a diseased liver—is perhaps the most
important of all. It reflects what is best about us: our desire to understand
ourselves and one another, to use knowledge to relieve suffering, even if it
results in a kind of reductionism that insults our sense of ourselves as
unfathomably complex and even transcendent creatures. It also reflects what is
worst—the desire to control, to manipulate, to turn others’ vulnerabilities to
our advantage. The first impulse demands a search for truth at all costs. The
second makes it imperative to get away with whatever you can in order to
exploit a market opportunity. When those impulses collide, commerce—and often
bullshit—will prevail.
Chapter 2
Allen
Frances is not the first psychiatrist to draw a bead on his profession’s
inability to distinguish between illness and health. Neither is he the first to
worry about the effects of this uncertainty on public confidence in his
profession. The two concerns have gone hand in hand since at least 1917, when
Thomas Salmon gave a talk in Buffalo, New York, to the American
Medico-Psychological Association (the new name for the Association of
Superintendents, which would later be renamed the American Psychiatric
Association).
“The
present classification of mental diseases is chaotic1,”
Salmon told his colleagues. “This condition of affairs discredits the science
of psychiatry and reflects unfavorably upon our association.” He proposed a
solution: a classification of twenty different mental diseases “that would meet
the scientific demands of the day.”
Although his organization was already
seventy years old, Salmon’s list was one of the first proposals for a
psychiatric nosology, or
classification of diseases. Earlier psychiatrists had kept track of their
patients, but their concerns ran much more to the statistical than to the
diagnostic. In part, this was because they were making their count at the
behest of the Census Bureau, which, starting in 1840, had wanted to know just
how many people were “insane,” but not which forms of insanity they had. When
those numbers increased dramatically throughout the mid–nineteenth
century—especially in neighborhoods where new asylums had been built—their
explanations were more sociological than physiological or psychological. “It cannot be supposed2
that so many people were suddenly attacked with insanity when these
establishments were opened or enlarged,” said Massachusetts doctor Edward Jarvis,
head of his state’s Commission on Lunacy. Rather, he explained, “the more the
means of healing are provided and made known to the people, the more they are
moved to intrust [sic] their mentally disordered
friends to their care.” Supply, at least when it came to mental hospitals,
could create demand.
But what had driven these recently
discovered patients insane in the first place? “Within
the last fifty years3, there has unquestionably been a
very great real increase of the malady [insanity] in the progress of the world
from the savage to the civilized state.” Not that “these two great facts, the
development of mental disorder and the growth of human culture, stand as cause
and effect,” he added quickly. But then again, Jarvis was more than just
saying. There were two types of causes of insanity—physical (as in “palsy,
epilepsy, fever, and blows on the head”) and moral, “those which first affect
the mind and the emotions.” This second type of cause was surely on the
increase, a by-product of all that progress and the brave new world it had
ushered in.
In an uneducated community4, or where men are
born in castes and die without stepping beyond their native condition; where
the child is content with the pursuit and the fortune of his father, and has no
hope or expectations of any other, these undue mental excitements and struggles
do not happen, and men’s brains are not confused with new plans nor exhausted
with the struggle for a higher life, nor overthrown with the disappointment in
failure. In such a state of society, these causes of insanity cannot operate.
Upward mobility carried risks
with it, and so did modern education. Indeed, the “professional insane”—doctors,
lawyers, teachers, and the like—were uniquely subject to the demands that
“arise from excessive culture and overburden the mental powers.” Which is why,
he thought, 3.75 percent of them were on the rolls in Massachusetts.
“From
all this survey5,” Jarvis concluded in 1872, “we are
irresistibly drawn to the conclusion that insanity is a part of the price we
are paying for the imperfection of our civilization.”
Jarvis’s conclusion made the particulars
of his patients’ afflictions less important than their demographics and
geography and economics, and their relief more a matter of social than medical
remedy. This may well have reflected some idealism on his part and a sense that
psychiatry’s job was to help perfect civilization rather than to cure
individuals. But there is a less noble reason for Jarvis’s and his colleagues’
nosological inattention: they simply couldn’t compete with their
microscope-armed brethren. As the magnificently named psychiatrist Pliny Earle complained
in 1886:
In the present state of our knowledge6, no
classification of insanity can be erected upon a pathological basis, for the
simple reason that, with slight exceptions, the pathology of the disease is
unknown. Hence, for the best understood foundation for a nosological scheme for
insanity, we are forced to fall back upon the symptomatology of the disease—the apparent mental condition, as judged from the outward
manifestations.
All the statistical analysis in the world,
and all the recommendations for the perfection of society, would not make
psychiatrists real doctors; real medicine was practiced upon individual
patients, upon their errant physiologies and the bugs that had made them go
haywire. As if this weren’t trouble enough, the democratization of mental
illness had so favored neurologists that by the time World War I broke out,
psychiatry, according to historian Edward Shorter, “had become marginal7
to the mainstream of medicine.” So when Thomas Salmon presented his
classification of diseases to his colleagues in Buffalo, it was clear that they
risked professional demise if they could not fill in the gap between
opportunity and knowledge by meeting those scientific demands.
• • •
Salmon’s solution took
inspiration from an earlier attempt to solve the same problem. In the late
nineteenth century, a German doctor named Emil Kraepelin had noted the
nosological chaos in which psychiatrists claimed with certainty that their
patients suffered from “masturbatory insanity” or “wedding night psychosis” or
“dementia praecox,” but couldn’t say how they knew what these conditions were,
or where one started up and another left off, or, most important, whether or not
they existed.
Kraepelin would have liked to ground his
nosology as his colleagues in other specialties did. “Pathological anatomy8,”
he wrote, offered “the safest foundation for a classification,” but the brain,
where that pathology would most likely be found, was way beyond the reach of
the instruments of the time. So he settled for what Pliny Earle had lamented as
second best. He proposed that the landscape of mental suffering could be
effectively mapped if a doctor observed it carefully and systematically enough,
if, that is, he stuck faithfully to the phenomenon as it presented itself in
the clinic. Discern how symptoms grouped together in patients, how, for
example, delusions of grandeur went together with mania, or how hallucinations
dogged the same patients who were paranoid, and then chart the course and
outcome of those cases, and you have the basis for an accurate taxonomy of
insanity, one that, or so Kraepelin promised, would line up with the pathological
anatomy that doctors were sure to discover in the future.
Kraepelin’s method required patience and
discipline and, above all else, a steely determination not to indulge in “poetic interpretation9
of the patient’s mental process, [which] we call empathy.”
“Trying to understand another human
being’s emotional life,” he once told his students, “is fraught with potential
error . . . It can lead to gross self-deception in research.”
Early in his career, Kraepelin got a job
in an Estonian asylum. He didn’t speak the local language, so it was a perfect
opportunity to hone his method for discerning the nature of his patients’
illnesses undistracted by empathy. He observed their behaviors, noted them on
cards, sorted them according to which ones appeared together, and chronicled
what happened to the patients who had those groups of symptoms. In 1893 he
published the first in a series of textbooks in which he gave names to the
illnesses he claimed to have discerned and provided descriptions of how they
could be recognized.
Kraepelin’s taxonomy had to compete with
Freud’s rich and riveting accounts, and it languished, especially in the United
States. But when Salmon introduced his nosology, he didn’t write about Oedipal
complexes or reaction formations. Instead he
took a Kraepelinian approach10, laying out neat
categories of mental illness, many of which, including dementia praecox and manic-depressive insanity and involutional melancholia,
were cribbed directly from his German forebear.
Salmon shared something else with
Kraepelin: ignorance about the biochemical origins of mental illness, coupled
with the assumption that when they were finally discovered, as they inevitably
would be, they would prove that the diseases existed in the way we expect
diseases to exist, and that psychiatrists had known all along what they were
talking about.
Salmon had renewed the promissory note
issued by Kraepelin, and the market was quick to take on the debt. A year after
his talk, the association issued the Statistical Manual11 for the Use of Institutions for the Insane, based largely
on Salmon’s nomenclature. The book pleased the Census Bureau enough that it
adopted the categories for its own ongoing attempt to include the mentally ill
in its count of Americans. The Statistical Manual was
revised ten times between 1918 and 1942, but it remained, as the title implied,
primarily a guide to data collection, focused mostly on institutionalized
patients whose ills were presumably biological in origin. It also remained
brief: its last edition ran to seventy-one
pages12 covering, besides Salmon’s
original handful of diagnoses, eight “psychoneuroses” added in response to the
ascendancy of psychoanalysis.
By 1940, the American Psychiatric
Association (the name Salmon’s organization had adopted in 1921) had a membership of only 2,295 doctors13.
But World War II, with its influx of soldiers suffering war neuroses (later to be known as Posttraumatic Stress Disorder), had
induced the army to increase the ranks of its psychiatrists, and by the end of
the war, thanks to some quick on-the-job training, there were 2,400
psychiatrists serving in the army alone. It wasn’t long before the swelling
ranks of psychiatrists sought to extend their success to the civilian walking
wounded. “Our experiences with therapy14
in war neuroses have left us with an optimistic attitude,” wrote two prominent
psychiatrists in 1944. “The lessons we have learned in the combat zone can be
well applied . . . at home.”
But neither psychoanalysis, the dominant
mode of therapy, nor the Statistical Manual was
entirely well suited to these new psychiatrists. Psychoanalysis, with its focus
on early childhood as the fount of all pathology, couldn’t really explain why
so many soldiers, presumably normal before the war, became mentally ill after
exposure to its horrors. Neither could the Statistical Manual,
with its focus on constitutional and presumably incurable illnesses, account
for what seemed to be transient and dramatic reactions to the environment.
Psychoanalysis
proved easy enough to adapt15, especially now that Freud was
dead and couldn’t object. Freud’s insistence that only early childhood trauma
caused neurosis could be modified without losing the basic idea that
intrapsychic conflict was the culprit. Trauma later in life, such as a war,
could also disrupt intrapsychic functioning and leave people unable to adapt to
new and difficult circumstances. This failure could be understood as a psychoneurotic reaction, and analysts, armed with this
notion, recast psychoanalysis as a theory of adaptation to life circumstances,
and their practices as a ministry to the walking wounded.
But the Statistical
Manual presented a different kind of problem. Its basic terms didn’t
even come close to describing what psychiatrists were seeing in the clinic.
Indeed, they complained, only 10 percent of
their cases16 fit into the classification
system. So they began to improvise, stretching diagnostic categories to fit
their patients, inventing labels when that didn’t work, and borrowing disease
names from other medical specialties whenever they could. The armed forces
developed their own nosology, as did the Veterans Administration, and these
began to compete for primacy with the edition of the Statistical
Manual that had been issued in 1942. In 1948, George Raines, chair of
the APA’s committee on nomenclature, summed up the situation he faced:
At least three nomenclatures17 were in general
use, and none of them fell into line with the International Statistical
Classification . . . One agency found itself in the uncomfortable position of
using one nomenclature for clinical use, a different one for disability rating,
and the International for statistical work. In addition, practically every
teaching center had made modifications of [the Statistical
Manual] for its own use and assorted modifications of the Armed Forces
nomenclature had been introduced into many clinics and hospitals by
psychiatrists.
Psychiatry, or at least the
APA, was once again mired in the chaos that Salmon had lamented three decades
earlier as a threat to the viability of his profession.
Raines decided to put off a revision of
the Statistical Manual scheduled for 1948 in favor of
a total revamping. Drawing on the armed forces’ classification, input from
psychiatric teaching hospitals, polls of the APA’s membership, and reviews of
the scientific literature, he and his committee assembled a revised manual,
which they submitted to the membership in 1950. The proposed book still
provided labels and descriptions for conditions presumed to be unresponsive to
the environment as either cause or cure. But it also contained definitions of reactions, disorders resulting from traumatic life
circumstances and accounted for by the updated, adjustment-focused version of
psychoanalysis that had emerged since the war.
Raines’s revision offered something for
private practice and hospital psychiatrists alike. It also had a different
focus from the earlier manual—largely, Raines explained, because the recent
establishment of the National Institute of Mental Health meant that statistical
analysis, once the “stepchild of [the]
Federal Government18,” would now be handled by public
officials. Freed from that drudgery, psychiatrists could pay closer attention
to diagnosis, and the new revision stood ready to aid them with eighty-seven
diagnoses to choose from, each with a paragraph describing a prototypical
patient. If, for instance, a patient was complaining of “diffuse” anxiety, “not
restricted to situations or objects . . . not controlled by any specific
psychological defense mechanism . . . characterized by anxious expectation and .
. . associated with somatic symptomatology,” then the doctor could diagnose Anxiety Reaction19. On the other
hand, if “the anxiety . . . is allayed, and hence partially relieved, by
depression and self-depreciation . . . precipitated by a current situation . .
. associated with a feeling of guilt for past failures or deeds . . . [and]
dependent on the intensity of the patient’s ambivalent feeling toward his
loss,” then the patient had Depressive
Reaction20. Because
of this new focus, the manual had a new name: The Diagnostic
and Statistical Manual: Mental Disorders.
When it was released in 1952, the DSM’s
nomenclature imposed some order on the professional landscape. As insurance
payments came to play an increasing role in the medical marketplace, those new
diagnoses proved useful, especially to private-practice doctors. But these
successes came at a cost: by delineating a realm of “disorders of psychogenic origin21
or without clearly defined physical cause or structural change in the brain,”
the DSM represented a partial abandonment of Kraepelin’s promise that mental
disorder could be understood like physical disease, and eventually would be
explained as the manifestation of brain pathologies. And by incorporating
Freudian concepts like defense mechanism and ambivalence toward loss, the DSM glossed over a question
that had been looming since the New York Psychoanalytic Society claimed
psychoanalysis for medicine. Were those psychogenic disorders really medical
problems? Should psychiatrists continue to try to carve up the landscape of
mental suffering in the way that the rest of medicine was carving up the
afflictions of the body?
By 1963, leading psychiatrists such as
Karl Menninger were beginning to think the answer was no. “Instead of putting so much emphasis22
on different kinds . . . of illness,” he wrote, “we propose to think of all
forms of mental illness as being essentially the same in quality and differing
quantitatively.” Menninger didn’t think the search for “what was behind the
symptom” should be abandoned. Rather, he believed, like Edward Jarvis, that
psychiatrists should focus their attention not on hypothetical brain
disturbances or quasi-medical psychogenic diseases, but on “Man in transaction with his universe23”—the
economic, political, and social world in which psychological life was lived.
Many of his colleagues shared Menninger’s
dour view of diagnosis, and, glad as they were to use the book to get insurance
payments, they otherwise ignored not only the DSM, but nosology in general. By
the late 1960s, it had become a professional
backwater24; discussions of disease
classification were relegated to the last session of the last day of
professional conferences. But even if the DSM had managed to put Kraepelin’s
promissory note into abeyance, if not to abandon it entirely in favor of
Menninger’s transactional view, still a market based on confidence cannot
tolerate outstanding debt forever. After the repeated blows to psychiatry’s
credibility in the late 1960s and early 1970s—the reliability fiascos, the
Rosenhan caper, the homosexuality debacle—the note was finally called in. In
1975, a Blue Cross executive told the Psychiatric News, the APA’s house organ, that his industry was reducing
mental health treatment benefits because “compared
to other types of services25, there is less clarity and
uniformity of terminology concerning mental diagnoses.” And in 1978, a
presidential commission, convened, among other reasons, to set priorities for federal
funding, concluded that “documenting the total number of people who have mental
health problems . . . is difficult not only because opinions vary on how mental
health and mental illness should be defined, but also because the available
data are often inadequate or misleading.”
Whatever their patients were suffering
from, the doctors’ problem was obvious. The DSM did a lousy job of helping them
figure out and agree on which disease belonged to which patient, and even in
the cases where it succeeded (after all, how hard is it to diagnose
homosexuality?), the DSM didn’t help doctors prove that patients were suffering
from medical diseases rather than the human condition. Turning away from
Kraepelin and toward Freud had been a boon, but it had now become an
embarrassment. Unless something was done, it was going to be increasingly
difficult for psychiatrists to make a living.
• • •
The war over the homosexuality diagnosis26
finally came to an end in 1973, when a Columbia psychiatrist, Robert Spitzer,
sat down with both sides and hammered out a compromise. The DSM would no longer
list homosexuality as a disease, but it would still provide a diagnosis for
people who were gay and didn’t want to be: Ego-Dystonic
Homosexuality27, a condition, clinicians were
advised, that was the result, at least in part, of “negative social attitudes
[that] have been internalized.” It was a win-win: gay people would no longer be
subject to bizarre and pointless therapies (or to psychiatrist-assisted
discrimination), the APA would stop getting humiliated by protests, and
therapists everywhere would continue to get insurance dollars to treat gay
patients.
Like most compromises, this one left some
bad feelings. “If groups of people march28
and raise hell, they can change anything in time. Will schizophrenia be next?”
one psychiatrist fulminated. “Referenda on
matters of science29 [make] no sense,” said another.
But the compromise at least kept the profession from splitting at its seams
even as it began to regain its dignity and the confidence of its patrons in
government and industry. And it showed that Spitzer had a great command of both
the political and the scientific issues at stake.
When I met with him, Spitzer, nearing
eighty and hobbled by Parkinson’s disease, was barely able to walk from the
easy chair in his sunny living room to the kitchen table, where sandwiches
whipped up by his full-time aide awaited, but his mind seemed undiminished. He
certainly remembered what his profession was up against after the homosexuality
crisis, and he was not mincing words about it.
“Psychiatry
was regarded as bogus30,” he said. “I knew it would be
better off if it was accepted as a medical discipline.”
Like Salmon before him, he believed that a
nosology that met the scientific demands of the day was the key to restoring
credibility to his profession. He also knew that if he managed to fashion that
solution, “my colleagues would think I had done something very worthwhile.” So
he volunteered for the job of revising the DSM, and, given his successful
nosological diplomacy on the homosexuality front, the APA was delighted to have
him.
Spitzer also knew that even if his job was
to carve nature at its joints with the scalpel of scientific knowledge, he was
stuck with the same dull instruments that Salmon and Kraepelin used—which were
not all that different from what ancient doctors like Hippocrates had at their
disposal: their senses, and the empirical world they could apprehend. And while
ancient doctors could taste a patient’s urine or smell his sweat or peer into
body cavities for information the patient couldn’t provide directly,
psychiatrists were limited to the symptoms a patient could describe and the
signs embedded in his behavior and comportment.
Still, as Kraepelin had demonstrated, it
was possible to make observations carefully and group them systematically.
Spitzer’s attraction to this method wasn’t so much a matter of conviction as
predilection. “Ever since I was a child, I liked to sort things,” he said,
recalling that at summer camp he graphed his attractions to different female
campers. Of course, to sort out the girls successfully, you have to know which
categories to put them in, and what makes them belong in one or the other. You
have to believe that beauty and intellect and sense of humor are real
properties, and that your way of discerning them is accurate and consistent.
Like Kraepelin, Spitzer was certain that if he was careful enough in observing
them, the outward manifestations would reveal the underlying mental condition.
To Spitzer, it wasn’t the unfulfilled promise
of Kraepelin and Salmon, but rather psychoanalysis—with its claims that
psychopathology was the human condition, that same-sex love was the result of
damage inflicted in childhood by absent fathers and overbearing mothers, and
that, in general, mental suffering was the result of the eternal war among ego,
id, and superego—that had led psychiatry to near shipwreck. It was
psychoanalysis that had led psychiatrists like Menninger to abandon the idea of
sorting suffering into medical categories. It was psychoanalysis that had
persuaded doctors to sort mental disorders according to the inner turmoil that
had allegedly caused them—the Oedipal conflict, say, or a fixation on the anal
stage of infantile sexual development. And it was psychoanalysis that claimed
that when it came to our psychological lives, the line between illness and
health could be drawn by determining if the problem was the result of
intrapsychic conflict, of the lies we tell ourselves about ourselves, of the
truths we dance around or repress and transmute into symptoms.
Spitzer hadn’t much liked the
psychoanalytic training that had been required of him and most psychiatrists of
his era, and he really didn’t like being an analyst. “I was uncomfortable with not knowing31
what to do with their [patients’] messiness,” he said. “I just didn’t know what
the hell to do.” And it was obvious to him that Freud’s theory of mind was a
poor substitute for pathological anatomy, and the complexes and resistances and
defense mechanisms—the psychoanalyst’s stock-in-trade—were far too ungrounded
in any kind of empirical reality to be useful. Proving the existence of ego,
id, and superego was like proving the existence of the Holy Trinity. These
notions were more metaphysics than physics, psychoanalysis more religion than
science, and the crises of the 1960s and 1970s were the result.
Of course, this was exactly the problem:
psychoanalysis had thrived in the theoretical vacuum left by the continued
ignorance of how the brain works. So it wasn’t like there was a theory waiting
in the wings to replace it. But, Spitzer reasoned, if his only options were a
theory that couldn’t be proved (and that was leading his profession to disaster
after disaster) or no theory at all, then the correct choice was obvious. It
was time to abandon Freud’s pretense to understanding the origin and nature of
mental illness, and to return to the one thing Kraepelin said psychiatrists
could safely claim to know: what they could observe.
Spitzer was already working with a group
of researchers at Washington University in St. Louis to resurrect Kraepelin. By 1972, the group had described32
fourteen different diagnostic groupings, established the criteria by which
patients could be placed into one or another of them, and conducted research
showing that the diagnoses were reliable. Six years later, the Washington
University group issued the Research
Diagnostic Criteria33 (RDC), twenty-one categories with
checklists of the criteria by which each one could be known.
The RDC bore virtually no resemblance to
the DSM, then in its second edition. Where the DSM-II listed illnesses like
Depressive Neurosis, defined as a “disorder manifested by an excessive reaction
of depression due to an internal conflict,” the RDC created Major Depressive
Disorder, defined not in a paragraph full of Freudian jargon, but as a list of
symptoms:
A. One or more distinct periods34
with dysphoric mood or pervasive loss of interest or pleasure. The disturbance
is characterized by symptoms such as the following: depressed, sad, blue,
hopeless, low, down in the dumps, “don’t care anymore,” or irritable . . .
B. At
least five of the following symptoms are required to have appeared as part of
the episode for definite and four for probable (for past episodes, because of
memory difficulty, one less symptom is required).
1.
Poor appetite or weight loss or increased appetite or weight gain (change of
0.5 kg a week over several weeks or 4.5 kg a year when dieting)
2.
Sleep difficulty or sleeping too much
3.
Loss of energy, fatigability [sic], or tiredness
4.
Psychomotor agitation or retardation (but not mere subjective feeling of
restlessness or being slowed down)
5.
Loss of interest or pleasure in usual activities, including social contact or
sex (do not include if limited to a period when delusional or hallucinating)
(The loss may or may not be pervasive.)
6.
Feeling of self-reproach or excessive or inappropriate guilt (either may be
delusional)
7.
Complaints or evidence of diminished ability to think or concentrate, such as
slowed thinking, or indecisiveness (do not include if associated with marked
formal thought disorder)
8.
Recurrent thoughts of death or suicide, or any suicidal behavior
C.
Duration of dysphoric features at least one week, beginning with the first
noticeable change in the subject’s usual condition (definite if lasted [sic] more than two weeks, probable if one to two weeks).
Purged of shaggy concepts and
imprecise language, the RDC could tell clinicians exactly what to look for and
what they had found if they saw it—a method that would leave much less room for
disagreement.
The RDC may have renewed Kraepelin’s
promissory note, but, so Spitzer claimed, it also provided the means for paying
it off. Of course, Socrates’ observation still held: to gather together
scattered particulars into groups was not to carve nature at its joints. But,
Spitzer contended, all those observations, made by many researchers using the
same language, would add up to a body of knowledge for each disorder, and the nosology would inexorably gain substance35.
Two different teams researching depression, for example, would be able to claim
that they were looking at the same phenomenon, and as findings converged and
solidified, so would the case for the existence of depression as a disease. And
if that convergence couldn’t or didn’t occur, then that would be an indication
that there was something wrong with the category, that it had been ill
conceived or poorly defined, or that it just plain didn’t exist. Reliability—the extent to which diagnostic criteria would
yield agreement among clinicians—was not the same as validity,
or the extent to which the diagnosis described an actual disease. But beefed-up
reliability could at least make the profession seem less bogus.
“The use
of operational criteria36 for psychiatric diagnosis is an
idea whose time has come!” Spitzer wrote in 1978. Of course, he knew that
twenty-one diagnoses wouldn’t be nearly enough to cover the entire terrain over
which psychiatrists claimed dominion, or to ensure that all their patients
would qualify for a diagnosis and thus insurance reimbursement. He invited his
colleagues to name the disorders they thought they were treating, and he found
many of them eager to get in on the ground floor of the new scheme. He and his
committees winnowed the suggestions, developed the criteria by which the
survivors would be known, and assembled them into a diagnostic manual the likes
of which had never been seen. A 500-page hardbound tome, the DSM-III made the
spiral-bound, 134-page DSM-II look like a mere pamphlet. And by nearly doubling
the number of mental disorders, it also vastly expanded the manual’s scope,
turning it into an entirely new psychopathology of everyday life.
Even so, the DSM-III was not universally
popular among psychiatrists. Some thought its symptom lists, its plain
language, and its workaday disorder names degraded the profession. “Clerks
rather than experts can make this kind of classification,” one grumbled.
This, of course, was exactly the point.
Imagination was what had led psychiatry to founder; a Kraepelinian nosology was
the best way to prevent psychiatrists from steering their profession back onto
the shoals of unreliability. Spitzer had fashioned a dictionary of disorder
that allowed psychiatrists to identify our foibles without recourse to the
troublesome Freudian mumbo jumbo or, for that matter, any other mumbo jumbo.
And the result was sensational. The
DSM-III not only restored both internal and external confidence in psychiatry;
it was also an international bestseller. “It made an unbelievable amount of
money for the APA,” Spitzer said. “That was a huge surprise.” And looking back
on it, Spitzer has no question where the book’s popularity came from. “DSM-III
looks very scientific,” he told me. “If you open it up, it looks like they must
know something.”
• • •
The psychiatrists who wrote
and used the DSM-III indeed knew something. They knew that certain symptoms
tended to group together and that psychiatrists could reliably identify the
people who belonged in those groups. But Spitzer acknowledges that the book did
not solve the validity problem. He doesn’t even think it was supposed to.
Indeed, he told me, the APA hired him to achieve only the smallest of
bureaucratic goals—to bring the DSM into harmony with the World Health
Organization’s International Classification of Diseases, known as the ICD. When
I pressed him, he allowed that, of course, increasing reliability was also on
his—and the APA’s—mind. But validity? “No, no,” he said, “not at all.” That’s
not what they wanted, and that’s not what he meant to do.
Even now, in fact, the man who crafted the
deal to delete homosexuality isn’t sure that homosexuality is not a valid
disorder. “It has a distinct course, there’s no doubt about that,” he said,
adding that there are gender differences in prevalence and evidence that it is
a familial trait. But, he cautioned, “to decide whether it’s a disorder or a
normal variant, you’d have to decide whether homosexuality represents a
dysfunction. People who think it is a disorder would argue from an evolutionary
viewpoint that we are hardwired for heterosexual attraction.”
Some of those people would also argue that
a lack of heterosexual attraction is a disease to be cured, and in 2003, after
interviewing two hundred people who claimed to have been “cured” of their
sexual orientation by “reparative therapy,” Spitzer determined that “highly
motivated” patients could indeed change their preference, a conclusion he published in the Archives of Sexual Behavior37. The journal accompanied the article with fiercely critical
commentary, and in the popular press gay activists pilloried the man who had
freed them from psychiatry. Spitzer defended his work then, but more recently,
he told me, he had come to regret the paper and was considering “writing
something in which I would say the critiques are largely or in many ways true.”
In May 2012, Spitzer did exactly that. His
assumption that “participants’ reports of change were credible and not self-deception
or outright lying” had been incorrect, he wrote in a letter to the Archives38.
His subjects had told him they were no longer
attracted to people of the same sex, but “there was no way to determine if
[their] accounts of change were valid.” Spitzer apologized to the “gay
community” for making “unproven claims of the efficacy of reparative therapy”
and to “any gay person who wasted time and energy undergoing [it].”
Spitzer’s recantation, and his ongoing
uncertainty about homosexuality, reflect his questing and curious mind, which
seeks empirical answers to difficult questions and is always open to new
evidence. It also reflects his honesty about the limitations of his paradigm,
which can elicit detailed accounts of what people are experiencing, but can’t
say exactly what, if anything, to make of those accounts. Descriptive
psychiatry can’t determine whether or not a person’s story about his sexual
orientation is a true one. More important, it can’t tell us whether the list of
symptoms, no matter how reliable, constitutes a disease. It can gather
scattered particulars into a category called gay, but
it can’t say whether those amount to the natural formation known as disease. It can’t carve nature at its joints.
Spitzer is also honest about the fact that
the decisions he made to admit or exclude a diagnosis from the DSM-III were not
entirely scientific. “The categories that were added were concepts that
clinicians in those days thought were important,” he said, and their criteria
consisted of what “clinicians said was a good way of defining them.” Spitzer
was the nosological diplomat among clinicians squaring off over pet concepts.
He was perfectly suited to this role because, in addition to his predilection for
sorting, he said, “I love controversy. I love it!”
Spitzer no doubt had in mind the
controversy he had presided over as his committees fought about diagnoses and
criteria—but it was only a matter of time before a different kind of
controversy set in. It was exactly the kind of controversy that Thomas Salmon
had worried about, and the culprit was none other than Bob Spitzer’s DSM.
Chapter 3
Allen
Frances often sings praise as a prelude to criticism, and sometimes in exact
proportion. So when he tells me how brilliant Bob Spitzer is, how valuable he
has been to psychiatry, and then adds, “I don’t want anything in your book that
would hurt him the slightest bit,” which he does repeatedly, it is pretty clear
that he’s winding up to plunk him. Not that he doesn’t deeply respect
Spitzer—that’s obvious as soon as you see the two of them together—or doesn’t
mean the praise. But he definitely has a beef with the man he replaced at the
DSM’s helm.
The problem isn’t the DSM-III. The move to
descriptive diagnosis was, Frances believes, necessary and beneficial for
psychiatrists and patients alike. But almost immediately after that book came
out in 1980, the APA decided to revise it. The new book would be called
DSM-III-R, to reflect the fact that it was not a new edition, but a minor
revision to correct textual errors and tweak criteria that were proving
unwieldy. Spitzer was hired to direct the effort, but, according to Frances,
“Bob couldn’t resist playing with it. He couldn’t resist the committee
meetings, all the new diagnoses, all the excitement” as experts, once again
given the opportunity to enshrine their pet ideas, advocated for new labels or
criteria.
“In the
morning, everyone would be screaming ideas1,” Frances recalled.
“Bob [Spitzer] and Janet [Williams, Spitzer’s wife and a member of the revision
committees] would be on a blackboard, trying to put it into some kind of order.
Then we’d have lunch, usually a big lunch.” While the others ate, Spitzer and
Williams would refine the morning’s arguing into diagnostic criteria. When the
group reconvened, Frances said, “we’d be sleepy and much more subdued,” making
it that much easier “for the most powerful person in the room to rule.” The
wrangling continued after the sessions, as doctors collared Spitzer and lobbied
for their proposals.
The backroom dealing was bad enough,
Frances thought, but even worse, the fighting was in many ways pointless. “The
things that looked so different to the people involved never amounted to a hill
of beans,” Frances said. “Should the threshold for a diagnosis be four or five
symptoms, should the criterion be this item or that? The answers are almost
always arbitrary.” So in 1987, when Harold Pincus, then the APA’s director of
research, offered him the job of running the DSM-IV revision, Frances told him
he’d accept only if the process was entirely different. “The last thing I
wanted was to be in rooms full of people pontificating without evidence about
things that didn’t matter,” he said. As much as he might have coveted the job,
“I never wanted to be in one of those meetings again.”
Frances didn’t always feel this way. In
fact, at one time he was among the pontificators. “I knew the instinct,” he
said—the one that leads a doctor to think that he’s seeing a cluster of
symptoms that no one has put together before, and thus has discovered a new
disorder. “You think you’re smarter than everyone else, and that what you’re
seeing in this patient should be in the DSM.”
Frances himself had once followed the
instinct, nominating Masochistic Personality Disorder for
DSM-III, aimed at people who “employ
self-sacrificing and self-defeating behavior2 in service of
maintaining relationships or self-esteem.” His proposal came under withering
attack from feminists who considered it a way of blaming abusive relationships
on women’s psychopathology. It also, Frances said, turned out to be a “dumb idea3, because all the
behaviors in a diagnostic manual of mental disorders are by definition
self-defeating. The concept really adds nothing.” By 1980, he had abandoned the
proposal, having learned an important lesson about diagnostic manuals.
“Realizing in retrospect how dumb my own off-the-cuff suggestion was made me
more alive to the fallibility of the many other off-the-cuff suggestions DSMs
necessarily attract.”
As much as he wished to steer clear of the
dumb arguing, however, Frances was even more intent on avoiding the pitfall
that had snared Spitzer when he ran the DSM-III-R effort. “It’s much better to
have a common language than a Babel of different languages,” he said, and the
DSM-III had achieved that. But whatever stability and respectability this
success had brought to the field was threatened by DSM-III-R. When that book
came out in 1987, a year late, over budget, and even longer than the original,
clinicians once again had to master new diagnoses, researchers had to piece
together the new disorders with the old literature, and psychiatry, which had
just barely settled down, was once again in turmoil.
The DSM-III had systematized the
description of mental disorders, put labels on clusters of symptoms, but, as
the DSM-III-R process had proved, those clusters could be arranged and
rearranged indefinitely. Descriptive psychiatry was no small achievement, but
the categories, the boundaries between them, and the criteria within them—these
were not discoveries of nature at work, at least not in the same way that the
identification of streptococcus and influenza, their characteristics, and the
boundaries between them were. They were approximations, and even if they were
based on careful observations, they were forever in debt to expert opinion.
The expert who led the move to delete
homosexuality from the DSM might come to believe that homosexuality is a
disease, and then once again decide that it is not. With each change of opinion
comes the potential for instability and discord; and to Frances, this meant
that the DSM-III’s achievement was a fragile one. “The fact that we had a descriptive system only
revealed4 our limitations,” he said. “If you
believe that labels are only labels, you don’t want to keep changing the
language arbitrarily. It just confuses everybody.” If the DSM is not the map of
an actual world against whose contours any changes can be validated, then
opening up old arguments, or inviting new ones, might only sow dissension and
reap chaos—and annoy Frances in the bargain. If he was going to revise the DSM,
Frances told Pincus, then his goal would be stabilizing the system rather than
trying to perfect it—or, as he put it to me, “loving
the pet, even if it is a mutt5.”
Frances thought there was a way to protect
the system from both instability and pontificating: meta-analysis, a statistical method that, thanks to advances in computer
technology and statistical modeling, had recently allowed statisticians to
compile results from large numbers of studies by combining disparate data into
common terms. The result was a statistical synthesis by which many different
research projects could be treated as one large study. “We needed something
that would leave it up to the tables rather than the people,” he told me, and
meta-analysis was perfect for the job. “The idea was you would have to present
evidence in tabular form that would be so convincing it would jump up and grab
people by the throats.”
“We put a lot of faith in meta-analysis,” Frances
told me.
Not that he expected to use meta-analysis
to sort out the arguments, at least not very often. “You need lots of data from
lots of sources for a meta-analysis,” he said. “And I knew that the literature
didn’t have the data. I knew we couldn’t do a real meta-analysis of most of
what would come up.” If someone brought up one of those off-the-cuff ideas in a
meeting, or collared him with a pet proposal at dinner, Frances would just tell
him to bring him the data, which he was pretty sure didn’t exist. Meta-analysis
would protect the DSM-IV (not to mention Frances) from the pontificators, the
profession from confusion, the common language from its own tenuousness. With
statistics guarding the gate, the revision would be modest. It might also be boring,
but, Frances says, “dull is better than arbitrary.” Seven years after he met
with Pincus, when the DSM-IV was released, it was nearly four hundred pages
longer than the DSM-III-R, but most of the expansion was in the explanatory
sections. Only a few new diagnoses had crossed Frances’s threshold, and the
book remained fundamentally the same kind of manual. Just as he had promised,
Frances had deferred to the tradition originated by Spitzer.
• • •
Not every psychiatrist loved
the mutt. Among its more prominent detractors was Steven Hyman, who in 1996
became the head of the National Institute of Mental Health. A neurogeneticist
by training, Hyman hadn’t thought much about nosology before taking over at
NIMH. It “seemed a bit like stamp collecting6,”
he once wrote, “an absorbing activity perhaps, but not a vibrant area of
inquiry.” But then he realized that the DSM was “a critical platform for
research.” Its categories and criteria were the basis of decisions made by
journal editors, grant reviewers, regulators, and the Food and Drug
Administration, which meant that scientists were bound to frame their proposals
in the DSM’s language. “DSM-IV diagnoses controlled the research questions they
could ask, and perhaps, even imagine.”
“The
tendency [is] always strong7,” John Stuart Mill wrote in 1869,
“to believe that whatever receives a name must be an entity or being, having an
independent existence of its own.” To Hyman, who quoted Mill approvingly, this
tendency had led all the stakeholders in nosology—scientists, regulators,
editors, doctors, drug companies, and, of course, patients—to take the labels
as more than labels, as the names of actual diseases. They had, at least
according to Hyman, reified what were intended only as
concepts. And this was no mere abstract concern.
It became a source of real worry8 to me, that as
Institute director, I might be signing off on the expenditure of large sums of
taxpayers’ money for . . . projects that almost never questioned the existing
diagnostic categories despite their lack of validation.
The DSM, Hyman concluded, had “created an
unintended epistemic prison,” and anyone with a stake in the mental health
treatment system was trapped inside.
While he was at NIMH, Hyman had occasion
to confide his reservations to at least one colleague: Steven Mirin, then
medical director of the APA. Both men had been affiliated with Harvard and
lived in the Boston area, but they’d become friends only after they had both
arrived in Washington and their kids started attending the same schools. On a
weekend afternoon in the summer of 1998, they were eating lunch by the side of
Mirin’s suburban swimming pool when Mirin asked Hyman if NIMH would give the
APA money to get the next revision of the DSM up and running.
Mirin’s request for taxpayer money to
kick-start a project from which a private organization would reap huge profits
was not as untoward as it might seem. After all, the DSM is indispensable to
public health, and NIMH had helped fund the DSM-IV. Nonetheless, and despite
their friendship, Hyman said no. He told Mirin that a revision was premature,
not only because the ink was barely dry on the DSM-IV, but more important,
because psychiatrists had yet to come up with a better way to carve up the
landscape of mental illness. All they could do, Hyman thought, was continue to
create and refine concepts that would then be mistaken for real disease
entities, and further trap psychiatry in its epistemic prison. Until someone
figured out how to fashion a key, Hyman didn’t think there was much point to
another revision, and he wasn’t going to provide any public money for one.
After all, you don’t remodel a house when the foundation is infested with
termites.
Mirin didn’t fight back—mostly, he says,
because he didn’t disagree. “The DSM was a system based on descriptive criteria
influenced by experts in the field,” Mirin told me. “They had lots of opinions,
but these couldn’t necessarily be validated.” The uncertainty out of which the
diagnoses were fashioned could not help but show up in the clinic.
“It’s one thing to guess and another to
biopsy a tumor or to measure an enzyme,” Mirin said. And both he and Hyman knew
which method the DSM had saddled them with. Spitzer may have freed them from
Freudian metaphysics, but still, as Mirin put it, “we were stuck with making
diagnoses based on scripture.”
Even so, America’s leading psychiatrists
weren’t about to renounce the only scriptures they had—mostly because, as much
as they knew the DSM was flawed, they didn’t have anything with which to
replace it. “I realized that it got me
nowhere9 to criticize the DSM because that
did not offer a constructive alternative,” Hyman told me. “In fact, given the
way the DSM had controlled the imagination of scientists, there was little
information with which to see beyond it.”
Hyman may have been anguishing about
psychiatry’s predicament, but Mirin wasn’t losing any sleep over the fact that
his profession was stuck guessing about categories that didn’t really exist. “I
don’t recall feeling particularly tortured about it. The DSM was essential to
being paid for treatment. Without its methodology, payors would see mental
illnesses as figments of a provider’s imagination.” It was also essential to
the APA’s finances. After all, Mirin told me, “coming down the mountain with
the Ten Commandments sure sells a lot of books.”
• • •
Of all his accomplishments
during his tenure in Washington, Steve Mirin seems proudest of the time he
persuaded The Washington Post to
support legislation requiring insurers to pay for mental health care at the
same level as other medical services. So far, parity,
as this mandate was called, had only been implemented
in a few states, and often only for mental disorders considered by insurers to
be biological in origin. In 2002, there was a bill pending in Congress that
would make it binding everywhere and for the entire range of DSM-IV diagnoses.
President George W. Bush had endorsed it, but the bill seemed likely to sink
into the mud of the legislative process, in part, Mirin thought, because the Post10—“the
hometown paper of every member of Congress,” as he put it—had twice come out
against parity. So he arranged to meet on September 3 with an editorial page
editor to see if he could sway the paper’s opinion.
Mirin arrived expecting an hour with a
single editor, so he was surprised and pleased when six editors and a reporter
filed into the conference room and talked with him for nearly ninety minutes.
He may not have been losing sleep over it, but the editors did their best to
torment him with the discrepancy between the DSM’s authority and the actual
science behind it. They “asked questions11
such as ‘How do you diagnose mental illness?’ and ‘How do you tell if it’s
real?’ and ‘Do you have a science base like the rest of medicine does?’” Mirin
told the Psychiatric News.
Mirin was prepared for this inquisition.
His press office had briefed him about the ways of reporters, and his staff had
subjected him to a mock grilling. Nor did he have to face it alone. He’d
brought with him an expert on diagnostic questions: Darrel Regier, whom he had
recently hired to head up the APA’s research arm, the American Psychiatric
Institute for Research and Education. Mirin had recruited Regier from the
National Institute of Mental Health, where he had risen to the rank of vice
admiral in the Public Health Service. Regier was attractive to Mirin in part
because of his familiarity with the ways of government bureaucracies, but at
least as important was the fact that Regier, an epidemiologist as well as a
psychiatrist, had been measuring the levels of mental illness in the population
since the earliest days of DSM-III.
What Regier had seen didn’t inspire
confidence. As the head of the NIMH’s Epidemiological Catchment Area (ECA)
team, he had overseen a group of researchers who, starting in 1980, fanned out
across five U.S. cities armed with a questionnaire keyed to the diagnostic
criteria in DSM-III. They’d asked twenty
thousand people12, selected to reflect the general
population, about their worries and their sadness, about whether they heard
voices, about how they slept and ate. They tabulated the results and, in 1984,
began to release them in a series of journal articles.
The
ECA’s findings13 were stunning. In any given year,
more than 20 percent of Americans qualified for a DSM-III diagnosis. Nearly
one-third of us—eighty million people, according to the 1990 census—would have
a mental illness in our lifetimes. And the
sick among us were really sick14. Sixty percent
of those diagnosed with a mental illness had a comorbid
disorder, meaning they qualified for at least two diagnoses. Ninety-one
percent of people with schizophrenia had at least one other diagnosis, as did
75 percent of people with a depressive disorder. Fifteen percent had three or
more diseases. More than half of the people with a drug-related diagnosis, such
as Cannabis Abuse, also had a second (or third) diagnosis. Even more alarming, only 19 percent15 of the afflicted
had sought help for their troubles, a number that dropped to 13 percent in the
cases where only one diagnosis was warranted. It seemed that America had an
enormous but unacknowledged and untreated public health problem whose effects
on productivity, on family life, and on the body politic were unfathomable.
This potential fivefold increase in the
size of the market for psychiatry wasn’t so much an embarrassment of riches as
a plain embarrassment. Even accounting for the fact that epidemiological
studies, in which researchers go out looking for trouble, almost always yield
bigger numbers than studies that rely on numbers gleaned from doctors’ offices
and hospitals, the results beggared imagination. They also cast doubt on the
DSM. The questions at least had to be asked: Was the problem in the minds of
the people or in the methods of the doctors? Did the DSM-III make it too easy
to turn people’s everyday troubles into disease? Was the book that saved the
profession going to lead it to another downfall?
Two decades later, Regier thinks the
answers are all too clear. I interviewed him in 2010, in his spacious office on
a high floor of APA headquarters in Arlington, Virginia. At sixty-seven, he has
a smooth, unlined face. His tie is tightly knotted, his shirt as crisp and neat
as his office. He gives off a quiet confidence, the certainty of a man who has
crunched the numbers and seen the results, and concluded that “we just don’t
have good thresholds for identifying what we would consider mental disorders.”
Having eliminated any account of the origin or nature of mental illness in
favor of pure observation, the DSM-III had also eliminated the thresholds,
vague as they might be, provided by Freud’s insistence that mental illness was
distinguished by its origins in intrapsychic conflict. The resulting
symptom-based diagnosis is binary; if you have five of the nine symptoms of
depression, you have the same disorder as a person with all nine, just as if
you have a small stage 1 tumor in your lung, you have the same disease as
someone with the same kind of tumor who is about to die. With those five
symptoms, as with the first appearance of the tumor, you have crossed the line
from health to illness, and the rest is only a question of severity.
But, as those prevalence numbers made
clear, doctors using DSM checklists were all too likely to find disease
everywhere. There was no governor, no way to say this person was sick and that
one was simply unhappy, nothing like the CT scan that confirms that the patient
with the persistent cough and fatigue has a tumor in his lung. A doctor who
diagnosed strep entirely on the basis of symptoms was practicing bad medicine,
while a doctor who diagnosed depression only on the basis of symptoms was
practicing standard psychiatry. It seemed that in his attempt to make
psychiatry look more like the rest of medicine, Spitzer had actually fashioned
a book that only highlighted the differences.
The comorbidity rates—the frequency with
which people qualified for more than one diagnosis—were another embarrassment.
Here again, Regier said, the ECA studies pointed not so much to a sick
population as to a flawed manual. Spitzer had anticipated the possibility of
multiple diagnoses, and in the introduction to DSM-III he suggested that there
was a hierarchy of mental illness, that some disorders only had a narrow range
of symptoms while others contained multitudes. Schizophrenia, for instance, was
far more encompassing than major depression, so clinicians confronted with a
patient presenting symptoms of both were advised to render only a schizophrenia
diagnosis on the assumption that the low mood was part of the more
comprehensive disorder. Regier pointed out that this amounts to a claim that
the depression itself is “just noise,” of no inherent interest or value in
understanding the patient or their disorders. But the ECA team found that
people with symptoms of both schizophrenia and depression were different from
people with only schizophrenia in many ways. Ignoring their depression meant
failing to get a complete diagnostic picture and losing “an enormous amount of
data” about mental health. “The ECA blew the hierarchy out of the water,”
Regier said proudly. “It just didn’t make any sense when we started looking at
the data.”
Concerns like this led the APA to abandon
the hierarchy in the DSM-III-R, but the real problem, Regier told me, was not
the approach but something much more basic: the idea that DSM disorders are
discrete diseases that exist in nature in the same way as cancer and diabetes.
This, to Regier, is the fundamental flaw of the DSM, the one that accounts for
the high rates of both prevalence and comorbidity. “It makes it seem like an
anxiety disorder doesn’t have any mood symptoms and a mood disorder doesn’t
have any anxiety symptoms. But it isn’t that simple. It’s just not the way
people present.”
But it is the way the DSM presents mental
illness; indeed, that neat separation is the signal innovation of the DSM-III.
Fortunately for Mirin and Regier, by the time of their fateful meeting with the
Post editors, they’d turned their skepticism into a
strategy. “We walked them through how we understood mental illness, and what
our thoughts were about diagnosis and the DSM,” Mirin recalled. Not, of course,
their thoughts about the book’s failure to correspond to clinical reality or
about the way the categorical approach trapped diagnosticians in a tautological
loop (which, after all, were highly technical matters, known and understood
only by experts), but rather their thoughts about the troubles reported in the
daily paper that might make the average editor skeptical: the shifting sands of
psychiatric diagnosis, the prevalence rates, the frequent and repeated
revisions of the nosology, the disorders that came and went with dismaying
regularity. These they readily acknowledged, but then they turned them to
advantage. The problem wasn’t that psychiatry was inexact when compared with
the rest of medicine, but rather that the rest of medicine was nowhere near as
certain as it was cracked up to be. The glucose levels that constitute
diabetes, the cholesterol counts that call for treatment, the blood pressure
that qualifies as hypertension—these numbers had all changed over time, and
after no small amount of wrangling. To hold psychiatry to a more stringent
standard was unfair and would make victims of doctor and patient alike.
This approach was exactly the right one
for his audience. “They were smart people,” Mirin said. “They were
sophisticated enough to understand that what their doctor told them about
hypertension was not carved in stone, either.” If the Post’s
editors noticed the intellectual sleight-of-hand at work here, the way that
these leading psychiatrists were distancing themselves from the same claims to
certainty that had allowed the DSM to rescue psychiatry from the pseudoscience
precipice (or, for that matter, if they wondered whether or not they should
keep taking their diuretics), they didn’t say, at least not in print. Perhaps
they were afraid they’d seem unsophisticated or just plain dumb. Either way,
six days after the meeting, the paper came
out in favor of parity16, Congress passed a limited version
of the bill, and mental health professionals everywhere rejoiced. Six years and
many editorials later, parity became the law of the land. Mirin and Regier’s
strategy succeeded. They had spun the dross of diagnostic uncertainty into
gold.
• • •
Maybe you’re not smart or
sophisticated enough to understand this argument, either. Maybe you think Mirin
and Regier were just trying to have it both ways. You might then suggest that
those prevalence numbers were still a little fishy. You might wonder out loud
what would happen if 25 or 30 percent of the population exceeded the standard
glucose or blood pressure thresholds, but only 19 percent of that group—about 5
percent of the population—ever got sick enough to even show up at their
doctor’s office. You might then ask what exactly those numbers added up to,
whether they measured disease at all, and if the whole idea of hypertension or
type 2 diabetes had been created by an industry too interested in selling
treatments to people who were actually healthy. You might point out that
regardless of whether or not they are diseases in themselves or only risk
factors, blood pressure and glucose levels can at least be measured with a high
degree of certainty. And you might raise the question of whether or not it’s
really fair to compare conditions such as high glucose and blood pressure to
mental illnesses, whether or not telling a patient he has hypertension for
which he should take diuretics is really the same kind of intervention as
telling him he has a chemical imbalance that antidepressants will correct.
Darrel Regier would have an answer for
some of those questions. You think those numbers are high? Well, he would tell
you, or at least he told me, you should see the
Midtown Manhattan Study17. Regier started his training with
the people who ran that project, which began in 1952, took ten years to
complete, and was conducted exactly where you think it was. Researchers
canvassed 1,911 Manhattanites and concluded, according to Regier, that 85
percent of the population had a mental illness.
When Regier graduated from Indiana
University’s medical school in 1970, the Midtown Manhattan Study still
constituted the standard epidemiology of mental illness. “I was just coming out
of a residency where I was seeing really sick patients,” he said, “and I’m
saying to myself, ‘What are they talking about over here with all of these
people who have an occasional symptom but are never going to go into treatment?
What is normality if 85 percent have a mental illness?’”
The Midtown Manhattan Study is a talking
point for most defenders of the DSM. They cite that 85 percent number as
evidence that even if the DSM is an imperfect document, and even if it catches
an improbable number of people in its diagnostic net, at least it’s better than
what we had in the old days. We in the mental health business call this a downward comparison, and we sometimes recommend one to our
patients to help them put their problems in perspective. “Yes, it’s true your
wife left you for your next-door neighbor,” you might say, “but at least your
kids won’t have to commute as far as most children of divorce.” It’s usually a
pretty lame intervention, as that example indicates, and to the extent that
it’s successful, it’s often because you’re actually bolstering the patient’s
self-esteem by pointing out that he’s better off than the next guy.
Schadenfreudian therapy, you might call it.
You can’t exactly blame psychiatrists for
grasping at this straw. But some straws are flimsier than others. Take that 85
percent number, for instance. The Midtown Manhattan Study team, which was
headed by sociologist Leo Srole, never said that 85 percent of its subjects
were mentally ill. In fact, Srole and his colleagues hadn’t set out to diagnose
New Yorkers at all. Indeed, they wrote, they didn’t want to use the DSM or any
other diagnostic system because they were “designed
for classifying full-blown pathology18”—and didn’t do
such a good job of defining it in the first place. So rather than ask19
about symptoms of mental illnesses, they asked about childhood fears of thunder
and strangers, and current attitudes toward drinking and gambling. They
solicited subjects’ worries about the atom bomb and old age. They asked whether
they thought people talked behind their backs or if they wondered whether
“anything is worthwhile” or if they believed that “most people think a lot
about sex.” They paid attention to whether the interviewees were sloppy or
neat, nervous or relaxed, if they were facetious, dull, or rambling. They
attempted, in other words, to capture the everyday experience of the average
citizen and to determine how much psychological suffering it entailed.
To make their assay, Srole’s team devised a six-point classification20
of symptom formation. People at the “healthy extreme”
got a zero. At the next two stages were people who had “emotional disturbance
without apparent constriction or disability,” and the last three ratings
“span[ned] the morbidity range of the mental health spectrum.” These were the
people whose symptoms had “crippling effects on the performance of . . . daily
life roles”—as close to a working definition of mental illness as Srole’s team
ventured.
Like Karl Menninger and most mainstream
psychiatrists and sociologists at the time, Srole and his colleagues subscribed
to the Freudian notion that between the dynamics of our psyches and the demands
of civilization, virtually everyone was bound to be troubled and that, as they
wrote, “mental illness and mental health
[differed21] in degree rather than in kind.”
So when it turned out that something like 85 percent of the subjects (the actual number is 81.5 percent22)
scored more than a zero, the researchers could have been no more surprised than
the audience at a Woody Allen movie would be to discover that most Manhattanites
are at least a little neurotic. But Srole and his team weren’t making the
ridiculous claim that 85 percent of us are mentally ill. Rather, they were
reporting the unremarkable finding that if you sit down with people and ask
them about their emotional lives, you will find that most of them will confess
to some difficulty.
The abnormal people in this study, as in
most studies, were those at the ends of the spectrum—the 15 percent who claimed
to be free of psychic turmoil, and the 23.4 percent who scored in the morbid
range. This latter finding, Srole noted, was a bit of a surprise. It was more than double the rate of mental
illness23 found in an earlier study of
Baltimoreans. But it was fully one-third less than the
number of people who would, twenty-five years later, turn up as mentally ill in
Regier’s ECA study, and surely nowhere near 85 percent.
Regier knows that Srole’s study didn’t
really conclude that 85 percent of its subjects were mentally ill. Indeed, he cited the 23 percent figure accurately24
in a 1978 report to a presidential commission on mental health. He also knows
about the Baltimore study, and about a National Institutes of Health study
conducted by his mentor, psychiatrist Michael Shepherd, which found a
prevalence rate of around 15 percent. That, in fact, was the figure he used in
his report to the president: on any given day, he wrote, about 15 percent of Americans were mentally ill25.
Regier thinks Shepherd’s study is “a
classic,” and the 15 percent figure “wonderful.” It’s easy to see why he didn’t
lead his presentation to the Post editors with his
conviction, based on a quarter century of studying the subject, that prevalence
rates had been inflated by the DSM—published, remember, by the organization he
was working for—or, for that matter, that the categorical approach to diagnosis
didn’t reflect the reality of mental illness. He and Mirin had a guild to
represent, and telling the editors that parity laws would force insurers to pay
for the treatment of people who didn’t necessarily have illnesses that didn’t
really exist would probably not have been the best way to do that.
Besides, by the time they took on the Post, Mirin and Regier were already beginning to plan for
the DSM-5. The book they had in mind was no mere sequel. If it worked out the
way they wanted it to, it would be a DSM to end all DSMs.
Chapter 4
Steve
Mirin took Steve Hyman’s refusal to give the APA money for a new DSM as a
challenge. “Steve was putting pressure on the field to start to consider a
different approach to diagnosis,” he told me. Mirin shared both Hyman’s wish to
put psychiatry on a new footing and an idea about what that foundation should
be. “Steve and I had an agenda,” Mirin told me. “To introduce neuroscience into
diagnosis.”
The 1990s had been, by presidential
decree, the Decade of the Brain. Billions of dollars had been spent trying to
get the brain to give up its secrets. Much of that money had gone to brain
scanning devices, especially the functional magnetic resonance imager (fMRI), a
miracle machine that allowed scientists to glimpse the brain at work. No
university research lab worth its salt lacked one, and scientists, flush with
grant money, slid their subjects inside to perform innumerable tasks. They
solved math problems and played video games, remembered sad times and
anticipated pleasures, considered moral dilemmas, took drugs, looked at porn,
and even (in France, of course) had sex. All the while, the machines whirred
and clanked, recording a comprehensive account of the brain at work.
Actually, all the machines were tracking
was the movement of oxygen carried by blood through the brain, a record
reassembled by computers into images colorized for greater effect. Like kids in
the pee-wee league chasing a soccer ball, your blood races around your brain to
sites that are becoming active, and scientists inferred from observing this
movement that those areas were the parts of the brain responsible for the
behavior or experience under study. And so there was an unceasing flow of news
reports, accompanied by those increasingly familiar full-color fMRI images,
about what the brain did when it thought no one was looking, about which area
of the brain gave rise to this faculty or that thought, about the latest secret
of consciousness uncovered by science.
The enthusiasm was contagious. By the time
the Decade of the Brain had ended, Nobel laureate Eric Kandel was proclaiming
that “the mind is a set of operations1
carried out by the brain, much as walking is a set of operations carried out by
the legs.” The fact that the pictures that seemed to prove this were only
prettied-up shots of the blood rocketing around in the brain and that they left
unobserved the networks that connect these lit-up areas, not to mention that
they ignored the enormous philosophical questions begged by these claims—Was
the brain causing the experience, or simply responding to the mind’s demand? Could mind be reduced to
body? Was the whole of consciousness no more than the sum of its parts?—had
disappeared in the enthusiasm of conquering what had only recently seemed to be
an impenetrable terrain.
Kandel, a psychiatrist, believed that
scientists now knew enough to say something else with confidence about the
mind: that “all mental disorders2
involve disorders of brain function.” He never specified what involve meant, but Thomas Insel, Hyman’s successor at NIMH,
didn’t hesitate to turn this idea into something less equivocal—and less
tautological. “We can think of mental
disorders3 not just as brain disorders but as
disorders of brain circuits,” he told psychiatrists at a conference. This
equivalence meant that psychiatry would one day be transformed into “clinical
neuroscience.” Psychiatrists could finally move beyond the observation of
symptoms and signs, and uncover the world behind the world of mental illness,
so they could finally say with authority which mental disorders exist and who
has them. They would be able to leave behind the approach that was at once its
salvation and its scourge: a classification of diseases based on description
and observation but with no account of what caused them. And then they would be
able to meet the scientific demands of the day.
• • •
Neuroscience was not new to
psychiatrists. In the 1930s and 1940s, even as Freudian theory was coming to
dominate American psychiatry, powerful biological treatments—electroshock
therapy, insulin comas, and lobotomies—were convincing many doctors that the
brain could be treated like any other organ in the body. Its workings were
immensely complex, the biological psychiatrists allowed, but the difficulty of
unraveling them was only a formidable technical challenge. There was no reason
that the mysteries of consciousness could not be solved by understanding the
brain. Long before the first subject slid into the first fMRI machine, at least
some doctors thought it was only a matter of time before mental illness was
vanquished by the same weapons that had undone pneumonia.
Other psychiatrists were less sanguine. As
early as 1917, Adolf Meyer, director of the psychiatry department at Johns
Hopkins and the unofficial dean of American psychiatry, worried that biological
psychiatry was a collection of “neurologizing
tautologies4.” Sure, the brain was involved in
consciousness and its troubles, Meyer said, but to single it out as the cause of suffering was to go beyond the existing evidence,
and perhaps beyond any possible evidence. Post hoc, as the logicians say, does
not mean propter hoc. That a depressed patient emerged from a shock treatment
undepressed does not prove that the cause of depression was in the brain’s
electrical activity. Indeed, some shock therapists in the 1930s wondered if
they weren’t merely “driving the Devil out5
of our patients with Beelzebub.”
The doctors’ assertion that they had found
the source of mental illness was based on deduction; they had to assume that
the brain was the causal agent in order to conclude that mental illness was an
effect. They also had to assume that the neurological dysfunction, whatever it
was, was both the necessary and the sufficient condition for the psychological
problem. Brain-based psychiatry was in this respect no less tautological than
symptom-based psychiatry, the brain’s role as a causal agent more myth than
science. Scientists and laypeople alike, Meyer warned, should approach these
findings with caution.
But it
was hard to argue with the biological psychiatrists6
when their schizophrenic patients awoke from insulin-induced comas coherent and
rational (if only temporarily) or when their shock machines roused depressed
people from their torpor. It was even harder to argue with the doctors who in
the early 1950s experimented on themselves and lab animals with LSD, discovered
that the drug was closely related to a recently discovered brain
chemical—serotonin—and, based on the profound alterations of consciousness the
drug induced, concluded that the brain conducted its business in an
electrochemical currency. Most persuasive of all, however, was the
serendipitous discovery of drugs that seemed to target specific mental
illnesses, presumably by targeting those chemicals—Thorazine for schizophrenia,
for instance, and imipramine for depression. These developments were all
accidental, and scientists could not fully explain any of them, but even so,
they could not help but reinforce the idea that mental illnesses existed in
nature, specifically in the brain, and that they were not unlike infectious
diseases—the result of a biochemical process that could be found and turned
into a target for one of medicine’s magic bullets.
By the mid-1960s, biological psychiatrists
thought they were zeroing in on the process in question: deficiencies or
surpluses in the chemicals known as neurotransmitters. In 1965, Joseph
Schildkraut, a National Institutes of Health scientist, claimed to have
reverse-engineered antidepressants and found that they worked by increasing
levels of dopamine and adrenaline in the brain; depression,
he announced, must be the result7 of deficiencies
in those two neurotransmitters. Within a decade, however, scientists had
determined that Schildkraut was wrong, and they settled on another possibility,
their old friend serotonin. What seemed never to be in doubt as the doctors
rushed from theory to theory was the idea that one brain chemical or another
was the cause of mental suffering, just as one bacterium or another must be the
cause of infection.
By the early 1990s, millions were taking
Prozac for their serotonin deficiencies. Biological psychiatry had established
a foothold deep in the popular and professional culture. Our everyday
understanding of ourselves now included the idea that we are
neurotransmitter-powered thinking and feeling machines. All that was left was
to figure out the particulars.
But these details were especially
devilish. By the time Mirin and Hyman began dreaming of a DSM-5, near the end
of the Decade of the Brain, there was still not one biological test for a DSM
disorder. The idea that a lack of serotonin caused depression had been
abandoned for lack of evidence (and for contradictory findings) almost as
quickly as it arose, except in doctors’ offices, where it proved immensely
useful to physicians trying to persuade reluctant patients to take their drugs.
The attempt to find the genetic underpinnings of mental disorders had also been
frustrated.
In part, of course, the failure to find
the pathological anatomy of psychological suffering could be blamed on the
complexity of our neurochemistry and genetic architecture, especially when it
came to the brain. But Hyman thought there was an additional problem. “The gold standard was the DSM criteria8,”
he told me. “It struck me as a fool’s errand to try to develop a biomarker for
a fictive category.” The lack of molecular evidence only reinforced what
doctors like Mirin and Hyman already knew—that the DSM-III’s nosology only looked scientific, that the empire of psychiatry was still
built on air.
• • •
In 2002, the APA officially
announced that Spitzer’s mutt had had its day. In A Research
Agenda for DSM-V, a book that kicked off the official revision effort,
the APA acknowledged that the reification of the DSM-IV’s categories, “to the point that they are considered9
to be the equivalent of diseases,” had most likely “hindered research.” Nor was
“research exclusively focused on refining the DSM-defined syndromes [likely to]
be successful in uncovering their underlying etiologies.” Searching for the
causes of the illnesses listed in the DSM was proving to be not unlike a drunk
looking for his car keys under a streetlight even if that’s not where he
dropped them. Scientists were unlikely to find the causes of Generalized
Anxiety Disorder or Major Depressive Disorder or any of the other DSM
categories—as descriptive psychiatrists had been promising to do since
Kraepelin—because it increasingly seemed unlikely that they really were the
equivalent of diseases.
So the APA did what organizations
everywhere do when they find themselves flummoxed. They convened a committee.
To be exact, they convened thirteen committees that, beginning in 2004, held a
series of “planning conferences” at APA headquarters. Because the conferences
were explicitly devoted to finding that new paradigm—which, according to the Research Agenda, was “yet
unknown10”—the NIMH helped pay for them.
Among the people Regier appointed to
organize the conferences was a Columbia University psychiatrist named Michael
First. First had been the text editor for the DSM-IV and the editor of the
DSM-IV-TR. Since 1990, part of his salary at Columbia had been paid by the APA,
for which he consulted on all matters related to the DSM. He’d already worked
on DSM-5, editing the Research Agenda and writing its
foreword.
When he’s not traveling around the world,
lecturing on diagnostic issues or consulting to the Centers for Disease Control
or the World Health Organization or teaching clinicians how to use the DSM,
First can be found in a basement office at the New York State Psychiatric
Institute, part of Columbia Presbyterian hospital on the northern tip of
Manhattan. He’s bent over in his office chair when I arrive, searching for
something amid the piles of papers that have spilled over from his desk and
tables and onto the floor. Bearded and rumpled, he looks like a psychiatrist in
a New Yorker cartoon. When he talks, thoughts tumble
out like the papers in his office, one on top of another, but somehow usually
making sense. So you’d be mistaken to think that he’s absentminded. If I hadn’t
interrupted him, he would surely have reached into the mess and found just what
he was looking for, just as he seems to be able to rummage around in his memory
and retrieve the slightest detail of the DSM’s history.
“In a
way, I was born to do the DSM11,” First told me.
But he didn’t always think so. “When I first saw DSM-III”—at the University of
Pittsburgh’s medical school in 1978—“I thought it was preposterous. I saw the
Chinese-menu approach and thought, ‘This is how they do diagnosis in
psychiatry?’ It seemed overly mechanical and didn’t fit my idea of what the
study of the mind and psychiatry should be.”
First had a second love: computer science,
which he had pursued as an undergraduate at Princeton. He’d almost chucked
pre-med for computers, and during medical school, he continued his interest,
working with a team using artificial intelligence for diagnosis in internal
medicine. He took a year off to earn a master’s degree in computer science,
working on a program to diagnose neurological problems. When he returned to
medical school, he settled on psychiatry as his specialty, and his interest in
using computers to aid diagnosticians made that Chinese menu approach seem not
quite so preposterous. “I thought, ‘Well, psychiatry is actually relatively
straightforward. It’s got a book with rules in it already—an obvious good
fortune if I was going to try to get a computer to be able to do this.” Which
he was, and which is why he decided to go to the New York State Psychiatric
Institute, the professional home of Bob Spitzer, where he planned to exploit
his good fortune.
Spitzer had already flirted with
computer-assisted diagnosis in the 1970s, when he was first developing the
criteria-based approach. He’d abandoned the attempt, however, and soured on the
idea. First managed to negotiate a bargain: he could work on his program so
long as he helped out with one of Spitzer’s—an old-fashioned paper-and-pencil
test Spitzer was developing called Structured Clinical Interview for DSM
Disorders, or SCID. The SCID, which is still in use, is straightforward to use.
If you answer yes when the doctor asks you if you’ve been sad for two weeks or
more, then he is directed to ask you about the next criterion for
depression—whether or not you have lost interest in your usual activities. If you
answer no, then he moves on to a criterion for a different disorder. This goes
on for forty-five minutes or so, the questions shunting you from one branch of
the diagnostic tree to the next until you land on the leaf that is your
diagnosis.
First eventually did develop his own
diagnostic program. He called it DTREE, but it was a commercial failure. “I
learned a lesson,” First said. “Doctors don’t care much about diagnosis. They
use diagnosis mostly for codes. They don’t really care what the rules are.” When
a patient comes in complaining of pervasive worry and jitters, with a little
dread thrown in, most clinicians don’t take the time to climb around on the
diagnostic tree. They don’t bother consulting the DSM’s list of criteria to
diagnose Generalized Anxiety Disorder. They just write the code, 300.02, in the
chart (and on the bill) and move on.
“That was my first lesson in how people
think about diagnosis,” First told me.
First doesn’t think the solution is more
reverence toward the DSM. Indeed, there may be only one thing worse than not
paying attention to the DSM and that is paying it too much heed. “I think
people take diagnosis too seriously,” he said. The DSM may appear to be a
master text of psychological suffering, but this is misleading. “The fiction
that diagnosis could be boiled down to a set of rules is something that people
find very appealing, but I think it’s gotten out of hand. It is a convenient
language for communication, and nothing more.” The rules are important, but
they should not be applied outside of a very particular game.
In this respect, First thinks, “the DSM
has been a victim of its own success.” If it was merely the lexicon that gave
psychiatrists a way to talk to one another, then it might live in the same
dusty obscurity as, say, Interventional Radiology in Women’s
Health or Consensus in Clinical Nutrition does.
If it was treated as a convenient fiction fashioned by expert consensus, and
not the embodiment of a scientific understanding of human functioning, then
newspapers would not be giving psychiatrists valuable op-ed real estate to
debate its merits. If it hadn’t escaped its professional confines, it would not
be seen as a Rosetta Stone capable of decoding the complexities of our inner
lives. If it had not become an epistemic prison, psychiatrists wouldn’t be
languishing in it, trying to find the biological correlates of disorders that
don’t really exist, that were invented rather than discovered, whose inventors
never meant to make such mischief, and whose sufferers, apparently
unreasonably, take medical diagnoses seriously enough to expect them to be
real.
• • •
First is right about at least
one thing. Most clinicians don’t care what the DSM’s rules are. I know I don’t.
I rarely take it down off my shelf. I use only a handful of the codes and by
now I know them by heart.
At the top of my favorites list is 309.28,
which stands for Adjustment Disorder with Mixed Anxiety and Depressed Mood.
Here’s how the DSM-IV defines it:
A.
The development of emotional or behavioral symptoms in response to an
identifiable stressor(s) occurring within 3 months of the onset of the
stressor(s)
B.
These symptoms or behaviors are clinically significant as evidenced by either
of the following
1.
marked distress that is in excess of what would be expected from exposure to
the stressor
2.
significant impairment in social or occupational (academic) functioning
C.
The stress-related disturbance does not meet the criteria for another disorder
D.
The symptoms do not represent Bereavement
E.
Once the stressor (or its consequences) has terminated, the symptoms do not
persist for more than an additional 6 months
I’m sure you can see why 309.28 is popular
with clinicians, and why insurance company claims examiners probably see it all
the time. It sounds innocuous, which makes it go down easy with patients (if,
as I do, you tell your patients which mental illness you are now adding to
their medical dossier) and with employers or insurers or others who might have
occasion to scrutinize a patient’s medical history and be put off by a more
serious-sounding diagnosis. It offers all kinds of diagnostic flexibility. Take
Criterion B1, for instance. It is easy to meet; it is easy enough to use the
fact that the patient made an appointment as evidence of “marked distress.” And
that lovely parenthetical in Criterion E makes it possible to re-up the patient
even after the six months have elapsed.
But Adjustment Disorder also has a special
place in my heart because it was my own first diagnosis, or at least the first
one I knew about. I got it sometime in the early 1980s, when I was in my early
twenties and the DSM was in its third edition. I don’t remember why I wanted to
be in therapy or very much of what I talked about with my therapist. I do
remember that my father was paying for it. He was probably hoping I would
discover that my self-chosen circumstances—living alone in a cabin in the woods
without the modern conveniences—were a symptom of something that could be
cured. What I was being treated for, however, was not “Back to the Land
Disorder” or “Why Don’t You Grow Up Already Disorder,” but rather, as I
discovered one day when I glanced down at my statement on the receptionist’s
desk, Adjustment Disorder.
I guess the tag seemed about right. I
definitely wasn’t adjusting; and if it occurred to me that by calling my
lifestyle an illness (if indeed that’s what he meant to do, as opposed to just
rendering the most innocuous-sounding diagnosis possible), my therapist had
passed judgment on exactly where the problem resided, I didn’t think much of it
at the time. But I do remember that I noticed, for the first time, that I’d
been going to these weekly appointments in a doctor’s office.
It happened to be in a building adjacent to the office of my childhood
pediatrician, but it did not smell like alcohol or have a white-shoed woman
bustling about, nor did its business seem a bit related to the shots and probes
I’d suffered next door, so the discord stood out. But still the fact of that
diagnosis, right there in black-and-white, was undeniable. I was a mental
patient.
I was eventually cured of my
maladjustment—not by therapy, but by a family coup that resulted in my
grandfather’s being relieved of the farm he’d inherited from his mother. That
happened to be the land on which I’d built my home, and so I was evicted, my
cabin eventually bulldozed and the land converted to McMansions, and it became
necessary for me to earn a living. Of the many adjustments I have had to make,
diagnosing people in order to secure an income was one of the strangest—not
only because the DSM’s labels seemed so insufficient, its criteria so
deracinated, the whole procedure so banal in comparison with the rich and
disturbing and ultimately inexhaustible conversation that was occurring in my
office, but also, and much more important, because of the bad faith involved. I
didn’t mind colluding with my patients against the insurance companies;
sometimes I actually enjoyed the thought. I brought them in on the scam,
explaining exactly what diagnosis I was giving them, sometimes even taking out
the book and reading the criteria and occasionally offering them a choice. But
the fact that we were sharing the lie didn’t make our business any less
dishonest.
I know therapists who diagnose everyone
with Adjustment Disorder unless the insurance company limits benefits for its
treatment on the grounds that it isn’t enough of an illness to warrant much
treatment—at which point the patient often contracts a sudden case of something
much worse, like Major Depressive Disorder. Myself, I prefer to mix things up a
little. But mostly I prefer not to do business with insurance companies, so I
often don’t have to bother with such dilemmas. Of course, that means I get paid
less money, since not everyone can afford my rates without a little help from
their friends at Aetna, so I end up giving people a break in return for
steering clear of the whole unsavory business. Over the thirty years I’ve been
in practice, I’ve probably left a couple million dollars on the table by
avoiding the DSM. It’s an expensive habit, but I think of it as buying my way
out of bad faith.
And it’s not just my rank-and-file
colleagues and I who think of the DSM as if it were a colonoscopy: a necessary
evil, something to be endured and quickly forgotten, and surely not to be taken
seriously unless you have to. I once asked psychiatrist and former president of
the APA Paul Fink to tell me how the DSM was helpful in his daily practice.
“I have
a patient12 that I’ve been seeing for two
months,” he told me. “And my secretary said, ‘What’s the diagnosis?’ I thought
a lot about it because I hadn’t really formulated it, and then I began to
think: What are her symptoms? What does she do? How does she behave? I
diagnosed her with obsessive-compulsive disorder.”
“Did this change the way you treated her?”
I asked.
“No.”
“So what was its value, would you say?”
“I got paid.”
It is at least ironic that a profession
once dedicated to the pursuit of psychological truth is now dependent on this kind
of dishonesty for its survival. But I suppose that any system guided by the
invisible hand—financial markets no more than health care financing—is bound to
be gamed. And the DSM, whatever its flaws, has proved to be a superb playbook.
• • •
Maybe Michael First’s claim
that psychiatry is somehow the victim of the selfsame diagnostic manual that
pulled its chestnuts out of the fire sounds disingenuous to you, too. After
all, the DSM-III could easily have been written in the medical Latinese that
doctors usually use when they want to leave us out of the conversation, and its
authors could have stuck with those original few diagnoses instead of trying to
catalog every problem patients wanted help with, from bed-wetting to binge
eating, from Frotteurism (“recurrent, intense, sexually arousing fantasies,
urges or behaviors involving touching and rubbing against a nonconsenting
person”) to Factitious Disorder (when a patient, likely conversant with the
DSM, has no mental disorder other than the one that makes him make up having a
mental disorder), from Nightmare Disorder to Nicotine Withdrawal. Spitzer
didn’t have to invite his colleagues to nominate their favorite disorders or
try to repair psychiatry’s reputation with scientific rhetoric. Indeed, it is
hard to imagine any outcome of a DSM tailored to give scientific names to the
vast range of our travails other than the one Hyman and First decry. The whole
point was to get psychiatry taken seriously by proving that mental illnesses
weren’t just the figments of some psychiatrists’ imaginations and that
clinicians weren’t treating mere problems of living. If the DSM hadn’t been
written as an authoritative medical guide to all of mental suffering, it would
not have restored the profession to respectability. And it surely would not
have become a bestseller.
On the other hand, there’s plenty of
evidence that the framers of the DSM saw the possibility that their book would
fall victim to reification. Each edition has carried some version of this
disclaimer that appears at the beginning of the DSM-IV.
There is no assumption13 that each
category of mental disorder is a completely discrete entity with absolute
boundaries dividing it from other mental disorders or from no mental disorder.
They also foresaw the
potential for the book to be taken too seriously—especially by lawyers intent
on proving that their client has (or doesn’t have) a mental illness. “The purpose of DSM-III14,”
reads that manual’s introduction, “is to provide clear descriptions of
diagnostic categories in order to enable clinicians and investigators to
diagnose, communicate about, study, and treat people with various mental
disorders.” The use of the book for “nonclinical purposes” must be “critically
examined,” it says, especially when those uses involve the “determination of
legal responsibility, competency or insanity.”
But lawyers who wanted to turn the DSM
into a book of excuses, each diagnosis a way to get clients off the hook of
free will, weren’t the only people who had to be cautioned, and the DSM-III-R
devoted an entire page to a more general Cautionary Statement. It warned DSM
users that the diagnostic criteria reflected only a “consensus of current formulations15
of evolving knowledge in our field” and that “the proper use of these criteria
requires specialized clinical training.” Apparently, the necessity of
strenuously reminding readers not to take the book too seriously outweighed the
possibility of undermining its authority at the outset.
The disclaimers are not unlike the
wink-and-nudge signs at head shops announcing that bongs are not intended for
use with illegal substances. They also resemble the black-box warning16 the FDA has required on various antidepressants alerting
consumers that the drugs increase risk of suicide in children and adolescents.
No one knows how many people this cautionary note has stopped from taking
antidepressants, but since 2005, when it was added in bold type inside black
lines to the insert that everyone discards along with the cotton in the top of
the pill bottle, antidepressant sales have only skyrocketed. Disclaimers don’t
seem to be taken anywhere near as seriously as the products themselves.
Still, listening to First revel in the
technicalities of criteria sets and dimensional
measures and clinical utility, it’s easy to
believe that he’d be glad if psychiatric diagnosis had remained a wonky pursuit
of little interest to anyone outside the field. If the DSM only helped ensure
that one doctor’s study of schizophrenia used the same definition as another’s,
that a hallway consultation about a patient’s condition could be conducted expeditiously,
that a depressed patient with a diagnosis of Bipolar Disorder wouldn’t get
prescribed the antidepressant that might trigger a manic episode, that drug
companies could have their indications and epidemiologists their numbers and
bureaucrats their forecasts of disability—if only the DSM had stayed small and
obscure, First wouldn’t be submitting to my questions, which he’s doing pretty
graciously, and he would be free to get on with the work of sorting and
counting and defining that, like Bob Spitzer before him, he finds so
compelling. He also wouldn’t be so worried about the fate of the DSM-5. Because
it’s clear to him that the APA’s aspirations for the new manual are grander
than the evidence warrants. He should know. He authored that line in the Research Agenda about how the new paradigm was “yet
unknown.”
“The research agenda was really on a
lark,” he told me, referring to the conferences and papers that began the DSM-5
campaign. “I mean, it was pretty obvious there was no paradigm shift at hand.”
Assembling the experts and finding out what they were up to might set the stage
for a new approach in the future, but surely not in time for the DSM-5. The
fact that the paradigm would not be shifting anytime soon was fine for a guy
who only wants the DSM to help clinicians communicate and make decisions—ends
that could be served by tweaking the current model and holding all those pesky
questions about validity at bay until the paradigm actually shifted. But the
APA leadership, First thought, was not content to wait, which is why they
decided to invite so many biological psychiatrists to those planning
conferences.
“They had this idea that we had the wrong
people doing the DSM, and if we had the neuroscientists and geneticists around,
they’d tell us all we need to do to make a paradigm shift,” First said.
Despite his doubts, First organized the
conferences, attended all of them, wrote summaries of the proceedings, and
designed a website on which to post them. He might have been sure those
scientists would never find what the APA was looking for, but he soldiered on.
He no doubt did this out of loyalty—to his profession and to his discipline.
But he had another reason. The APA’s aspirations to meet the scientific demands
of the day might have been quixotic, its ambitions outsize, but First had an
ambition of his own: to lead the effort to produce the DSM-5.
Chapter 5
Michael
First wasn’t the only old DSM hand skeptical about the prospects for the
planning conferences. “When I heard about
them1, I was amazed,” Allen Frances told
me. “It was absolutely ridiculous from the beginning. There was no way you
could force a breakthrough like that.” If scientists had made those seminal
discoveries connecting mental disorders with brain function, Frances thought,
the paradigm would have already shifted. The attempt to “jump-start science”
was part of a “grand ambition that will take many decades to realize.”
It was that kind of ambition that Frances
attempted to dampen with his conservative approach to DSM-IV. And First had set
his sights similarly low for DSM-5. “However much we don’t like this paradigm,
it’s as good as we have,” he told me. “So let’s find out how to make it more
helpful to clinicians.” For all their talk about clinician communication, the
defenders of the DSM have precious little idea of exactly how it figures in the
way psychiatrists talk to one another, and how it can help them do a better job
of it. They’ve spent a lot more time dreaming up new diagnoses than looking
into the far less glamorous matter of clinical utility.
First thought the APA’s time and money would be best spent tweaking the
DSM-IV’s criteria and correcting its obvious errors, while focusing on making
the manual maximally useful to clinicians.
Neither First nor Frances seems
conservative by nature. Their politics, to the extent they discuss them, appear
to be well left of center. But when it comes to the DSM, they see themselves as
stewards of a tradition that, even if imperfect, it is important to uphold,
possibly because both men have witnessed the consequences of playing fast and
loose with the DSM.
Perhaps the most disturbing of these
consequences was unfolding as the preliminaries to DSM-5 were getting under
way. The trouble began at Harvard’s Massachusetts General Hospital, where
Joseph Biederman worked as a child psychiatrist. In the 1980s, he developed a
stellar reputation as a researcher and clinician working with children
diagnosed with Attention Deficit/Hyperactivity Disorder (ADHD). Author of more
than six hundred articles, winner of numerous professional awards, a perennial
choice as a U.S. News & World Report Top Doctor,
and an inductee in the Children and Adults with Attention Deficit/Hyperactivity
Disorder Hall of Fame, Biederman was what is known in his industry as a key opinion leader.
Sometime in the 1980s, Biederman’s
opinions turned to a particularly difficult group of his ADHD patients. These
were kids who, in addition to being fidgety and distractable, were from a very
early age—sometimes, so their parents said, from the time they were born—quick
to rage, slow to be comforted, and precocious in all the wrong ways:
threatening suicide before their peers even knew what the word meant, acting
out sexually before they’d reached puberty. They were defiant and contrary and
cranky all the time, hard for parents to parent, teachers to teach, and
therapists to treat.
Biederman
thought he detected in these children2 something
different from what he saw in other ADHD patients. In particular, he saw what
the DSM called a mood disorder in their chronic
irritability, their prolonged and frequent tantrums, and the profound sadness
that set in after the storm. ADHD diagnostic criteria did not include mood
symptoms, but there was a small literature
reporting a few cases of “hyperactive children3” who also had
“nervous irritability” and who went on to develop one of the best-known and
most feared mood disorders of all: what had been called manic-depressive
insanity by Kraepelin and, in the 1980s, was renamed Bipolar Disorder (BD).
Doctors generally considered it to be neurological or genetic in origin and
incurable, although it could be managed with mood stabilizers, usually lithium.
Biederman thought that he was on the verge
of a major discovery: that BD, the onset of which was generally agreed to be in
early adulthood, started much earlier. This would indicate that these kids
ought to be treated with mood stabilizers rather than the stimulants generally
prescribed for ADHD and that they and their parents should be prepared for a
lifetime of managing a chronic illness, just as juvenile diabetic patients are.
The appeal of this hypothesis to doctors
and parents was immense. It invoked one of the most time-tested diagnoses in
the DSM, it gave clinicians something to call these kids’ condition besides
“bad ADHD,” and it pointed in the direction of a new treatment. But there was a
problem. According to the DSM-IV, “the
essential feature of Bipolar Disorder4 is a clinical
course characterized by the occurrence of one or more manic episodes.” And
manic episodes have what the DSM calls Criterion A symptoms,
features necessary, but not sufficient, for the diagnosis—in the case of BD, “a distinct period of abnormally and
persistently elevated5, expansive, or irritable mood,
lasting at least 1 week.” But Biederman’s patients didn’t have episodes of
mania—or of anything else for that matter. Indeed, the parents’ major complaint
was that they never got a break from their children’s biliousness.
The DSM also lists Criterion
B symptoms for most disorders—features that must be in place in addition
to Criterion A for the diagnosis to be made. Manic
episodes have seven Criterion B symptoms6, four of which
are required for the diagnosis. And three of those seven symptoms—excessive
talkativeness, distractibility, and fidgetiness—also appeared on the list of
possible symptoms of ADHD. So it was hard to distinguish the two disorders.
Clinicians following Biederman’s lead might be only slapping a new label on
“bad ADHD,” one that moved the patients to a different, but still ill-fitting,
category. This kind of ad hoc diagnosing is exactly what the DSM, with its
symptom lists, is supposed to preclude.
So
Biederman set out to prove7 that the new label was a winner,
that it could reliably gather together particulars once thought to be
scattered, and point in the direction of a previously undiscovered natural
formation. If he looked only at the chronically irritable patients, he
wondered, would their Criterion B symptoms differ from the ones that the rest
of the ADHD kids had? If so, then this would be evidence that these kids
constituted a different diagnostic group from the others.
Sure enough, when Biederman and his team
looked carefully at the Criterion B profiles of the chronically irritable
group, they found that they were more likely to have the four symptoms that BD
does not share with ADHD than children who weren’t
irritable. The team also looked at levels of impairment among the irritable
group—the extent to which the patients’ symptoms interfered with their lives,
landed them in hospitals, or led to psychosis—and found a similar grouping: the
children who were chronically irritable and scored
high on the four unique Criterion B symptoms tended to be more impaired than
the ADHD kids. Taken together, Biederman said, patients with this distinct
profile account for around 20 percent of children diagnosed with ADHD. One in five of those patients8,
Biederman concluded, actually was bipolar and was getting exactly the wrong
treatment: stimulants known to aggravate mania.
Biederman’s
announcement provoked9 an outcry from his colleagues. They
argued that his proposal flouted hundreds of years of observations about the
episodic nature of mania. In addition, they pointed out, a recent
epidemiological study, conducted by people other than those trained and
supervised by Biederman, had turned up exactly zero children with mania.
Biederman’s own research indicated that his patients were not only more
irritable than ADHD patients, but also more withdrawn and prone to sulk—hardly
consistent with a diagnosis of mania. Critics also complained that by
rejiggering the criteria, he’d lowered the threshold for what was a very
serious diagnosis. The Criterion B symptoms that remained after eliminating the
ones that overlapped with ADHD—“grandiosity, decreased
need for sleep, flight of ideas (i.e., a free-flowing stream of consciousness) and
excessive involvement in pleasurable activities that have a high potential for
painful consequences”—weren’t these really just a working definition of
childhood at its most exuberant? And finally, they cited longitudinal studies,
which showed that plenty of “bad ADHD” kids indeed went on to develop various
mental disorders, but bipolar was not among them—a finding hard to reconcile
with the presumption that BD is a lifelong illness.
I’ll spare you the ensuing back-and-forth,
which is as bitter and rancorous, and as impenetrable, as most academic
controversies, and which continues more than fifteen years later. It’s not that
it hasn’t been entertaining, at least at points, as when Biederman was moved to
liken his critics to people who insist the earth is flat and circled by the
sun, and his own discovery to that of Edward Jenner, whose “smallpox vaccine was ridiculed10
when initially proposed”—suggestive comparisons for a man studying a disorder
with grandiosity among its symptoms. It also illustrates the bruising politics
behind the DSM, the way in which changing it is as much a legislative as a
scientific process, and the self-validating nature of diagnosis, by which once
you’ve created a diagnostic category, the fact that people fit into it becomes
evidence that the disorder exists. But what happened next is of much greater
significance, so suffice it to say for now that Biederman proved, to his own
satisfaction, that he was correct, that those “bad ADHD” kids really had BD.
Biederman didn’t try to change the DSM-IV
definition of Bipolar Disorder to reflect his findings. The book had just come
out when he began his campaign to convince doctors and parents that chronic
irritability was the juvenile form of episodic mania, and a revision wasn’t
expected for many years. Fortunately for him, however, he didn’t really need it
to change. The DSM provides, in addition to the seven variations on BD—Bipolar
Disorder, Single Manic Episode; Bipolar Disorder, Most Recent Episode
Depressed; and so on—a category called Bipolar Disorder Not Otherwise Specified
(BDNOS). (There are NOS categories for every major diagnostic classification in
the book.) The BDNOS category is designed for “disorders
with bipolar features11 that do not meet criteria for any
specific Bipolar Disorder.” In other words, if your patient doesn’t qualify for
the diagnosis, but you still think he’s bipolar, you can just go ahead and give
the kid the diagnosis anyway.
• • •
By the time children get to a
doctor of Joseph Biederman’s stature, they’ve generally been through any number
of therapists, pediatricians, and psychiatrists. They’ve been the subject of
countless meetings at schools, endless testing by psychologists, and home
interventions from social service agencies. Their parents have tried
everything—drugs and diets, hug therapy and tough love, private schools and
residential treatment and family therapy vacations, prayers, and even
exorcisms. And in the end they still have a child who seems unhappy nearly
every waking moment, who is likely to fly into a rage at the slightest
provocation, who holds a knife to his own throat and threatens to plunge it in
if he isn’t allowed ten more minutes on PlayStation. They are, in short,
devastated and desperate.
That’s why, when the important doctor
tells the beleaguered parents that their child is irrevocably mentally ill,
even if they are aware (which they usually aren’t) that he’s stretching the
truth, they listen. Besides, the news isn’t all bad. At least now they know.
They have been given a name for their (and their child’s) pain. And when the
key opinion leader tells his colleagues what he’s doing at Harvard for these
kids and offers them the opportunity to provide the same kind of explanation
and hope to their own patients, they are quick to follow him through the NOS
loophole.
And by 1999, parents could even go to
their doctors and suggest they do exactly that. That at any rate was the advice
of Demitri and Janice Papolos, a husband-and-wife team whose bestselling book The Bipolar Child explained that “thoughtful clinical investigators12
are beginning to realize that bipolar disorder in childhood presents a very
different pattern” from the adult version. Unfortunately, they wrote, only
psychiatrists conversant with the “latest
research findings” would recognize the symptoms13—the
unsettled infancy, the precociousness and separation anxiety, the nightmares
and fear of death and mercurial moods, the sweet tooth and bed-wetting and
maybe even the in utero kicking, or any of the forty or so other signs that
your child is bipolar that are listed in the book—and issue the proper diagnosis.
By 2001, parents could comfort themselves
and their diagnosed children with books such as Brandon and
the Bipolar Bear, in which Dr. Samuel explains to Brandon why he
(Brandon, not Dr. Samuel) dismembered his teddy bear. “You have bipolar disorder14,”
the doctor says. He explains that Brandon has a harder time controlling his
feelings because the chemicals in his brain “can’t
do their job right15 so their feelings get all jumbled
up inside.” He tells Brandon that he doesn’t have BD because he is bad, nor did
he get it from a classmate. Rather, he says, Brandon
most likely inherited it16.
Websites sprang up, self-help groups
formed, foundations were funded, and in August 2002, Time devoted
its cover to the “Young and Bipolar17”
and their families, who had been saved by receiving the diagnosis. Soon, the
magazine predicted, a “blood test that will allow bipolar disorder to be
spotted as simply as, say, high cholesterol” would shorten the period of
incorrect diagnoses and fruitless treatments. By 2003, Biederman’s opinion had
led his colleagues to conclude 6.67 percent
of office visits18 made by children for mental health
problems with a diagnosis of BD—up from less than half a percent in 1994.
It was possible that the new diagnostic
approach had uncovered a previously unknown epidemic. But as Duke University’s
chief of child and adolescent psychiatry, John March, told The
New York Times when the diagnostic increase was reported, “The label may or may not reflect reality19.”
No one questioned that there were many children whose explosiveness and
irritability terrified their parents and defied treatment. But did they really
have BD?
But March had it backward. The diagnostic
label had been redesigned specifically to reflect reality, and reality had
followed suit; those explosive children were now bipolar patients, and the
sooner parents thought of them (and taught them to think of themselves) as
afflicted with a chronic disease, the sooner they could get help. If Biederman
had set out to become the Johnny Appleseed of an entirely new disorder—“scary
impossible child disorder,” let’s say—rather than of a new version of an old
illness, then the websites and self-help books and cover stories would be
offering support for kids diagnosed with that disease, doctors would be arguing
about whether or not it reflected reality, and parents would be wondering
whether or not their kids warranted the SIC label.
But that’s not what Biederman did. Neither
did he tinker with, say, ADHD or Oppositional-Defiant Disorder (ODD), or simply
suggest that clinicians use a perfectly good DSM diagnosis—Disruptive Behavior
Disorder, NOS (312.9) seems well suited—and be done with it. He wasn’t
determined only to give these children a new diagnostic home. He also had a very
specific idea about where they belonged, and if the evidence didn’t support his
conviction, then he would change the rules by which the evidence was admitted.
It’s not clear why Biederman settled on
Bipolar Disorder. But it’s easy enough to imagine the possible motives: to
ensure that insurance companies would pay for the extensive treatment these
kids needed, which a diagnosis of ADHD or ODD did not always justify, but BD
does; to make his professional mark by changing one of psychiatry’s most
venerable diagnoses; to confirm a hunch. But the label also reflected another
reality: that, as Dr. Samuel tells Brandon, there
is “some medicine that could help20 you feel
better.” Indeed, just as Biederman was starting to persuade his colleagues to
be on the lookout for childhood mania, new treatments were coming to market to
supplement the old standby, lithium. Drug makers were touting anticonvulsants
such as Abbott Laboratories’ Depakote, and rebranding
atypical antipsychotics21—Zyprexa,
Seroquel, Abilify, and Risperdal—as mood stabilizers,
the category to which lithium belonged and surely a less terrifying term.
These treatments were not without their
problems. They are sedating—heavily so in the case of the antipsychotics—which
means that it is hard to know if they were treating BD or just tranquilizing
the children. They are also associated with devastating
side effects22: cataracts, obesity, diabetes,
tardive dyskinesia (a movement disorder characterized by tics and spasticity),
which add up to a twelve-to-twenty-year
decrease in life expectancy23 for treated
versus untreated patients. And even as the drug companies began to seek (and
eventually receive) FDA approval to use the drugs as mood stabilizers and to
rechristen them accordingly, they did not study their effectiveness (or their
side effects) in children—largely because BD wasn’t thought to affect kids.
Biederman and others did run some studies indicating that children’s symptoms
improved24 in response to the mood
stabilizers. But these were short-term trials, often eight weeks or less, and
could not possibly explore the consequences for a developing brain of daily use
of a powerful drug. Nor could the studies tease out the question of whether the
results were due to the overall sedative effects of the drugs or to something
specific to these patients. Neither did advocates of mood stabilizers for
children talk very much about the obesity and resulting diabetes that were
known side effects of the drugs. None of this ignorance put the brakes on the
bipolar express, however. Diagnosis and treatment rates continued to soar—by
2003, prevalence of BD among children25
had increased fortyfold over a decade and, hardly coincidentally, by 2005, antipsychotic use in children and adolescents26
had grown by 73 percent in only four years. In 2007 alone, half a million
children, twenty thousand of them under six years old, were prescribed drugs
that a decade before would have been prescribed only in the most dire
circumstances. Biederman’s diagnostic innovation was a runaway hit.
• • •
Skeptics eventually raised
questions about Biederman’s success. In 2006, Gardiner
Harris reported27 on the front page of The New York Times that young children on drug cocktails—and
often on government disability for their officially diagnosed Bipolar
Disorder—were sometimes no better off than they had been before treatment, that
their families were now torn apart not by their behavior but by the problems
created by the drugs, that the kids were gaining weight and becoming suicidal.
Most disturbing, Harris wrote, there was precious little scientific knowledge
about this subject. This, coupled with stories
such as that of Rebecca Riley28—a four-year-old
girl who was diagnosed at age two and a half with Bipolar Disorder and
prescribed a combination of an antipsychotic, an anticonvulsant, and an
antihypertensive, and whose parents were arrested when she died after they gave
her an overdose of the drugs—led to a disturbing conclusion: that no matter
their intentions, doctors were conducting an experiment on children.
In 2007, Charles Grassley, a Republican
senator from Iowa, convened a series of hearings on the relationship between
doctors and the pharmaceutical industry. “In
psychiatry29,” The New York
Times reported in 2008, “Mr. Grassley has found an
orchard of low-hanging fruit.” Psychiatrists were the lowest-paid specialists
in the country, with a median pay of just under $200,000—an income that you and
I might find quite acceptable, but which paled next to the $464,420 earned by
the average radiologist, and which, the Times
insinuated, made the $750 to $3,500 speaking gigs offered by drug companies
that much more attractive and the unseemliness of the business that much easier
to gloss over. In Minnesota, psychiatrists who had taken $5,000 or more from
antipsychotic manufacturers had written three times more antipsychotic
prescriptions than unfunded doctors, and Vermont psychiatrists were receiving
more drug company money than any other specialists in the state—an average of
$56,944 each. A Cincinnati doctor reported $180,000 in income from AstraZeneca
(makers of the antipsychotic Seroquel) over two years—bad enough, but, as
Grassley discovered when he subpoenaed Astra’s records, the doctor had actually
received $238,000, the unreported part funneled to her through a corporation
the doctor had set up to hide the income.
But this was all small beer compared with what Grassley found when he investigated Joseph
Biederman30. Biederman and an associate had
acknowledged a couple hundred thousand dollars in drug company income between
2000 and 2007, but Grassley, with the benefit of subpoena power, reckoned that
it was more like $1.6 million, and that another associate had raked in at least
another million. Much of this money was for the research that Biederman used to
prove that BD existed in kids and that antipsychotics were the best treatment,
but the Grassley committee found something out about that, too. Those studies
not only were small and inconclusive—as research conducted by just one group of
doctors tends to be—but also had one main patron: Johnson & Johnson, whose
Janssen Pharmaceuticals makes risperidone (Risperdal), one of the
antipsychotics often prescribed for bipolar kids.
This shouldn’t have been a big surprise.
The Johnson & Johnson Center for the Study of Pediatric Psychopathology was
one of the affiliations Biederman listed among his credentials. But if Grassley
had only discovered gambling in Casablanca, he had also revealed just how
unsavory that business was and how much it favored the house. Biederman’s pitch
to Johnson & Johnson for funding his center was that it would “move forward the commercial goals31”
of the company, and when he succeeded at that, he sold his patrons a research
project on the promise that it “will support
the safety and effectiveness of risperidone32 in this age
group”—something a scientist shouldn’t say out loud, even if he thinks it’s
true, and something he definitely shouldn’t write in an e-mail that an
ambitious senator might get hold of.
On the other hand, most scientists
wouldn’t testify in a sworn deposition as Biederman did in this exchange, which followed his testimony33
that he was a full professor at Harvard:
Lawyer: What’s after that?
Biederman: God.
Lawyer: Did you say God?
Biederman: Yeah.
Divine or not, Biederman didn’t always get
what he wanted. The company turned down his request for $280,000 to fund a
study, and it balked at paying him $3,000 for a talk at a medical school. But,
as a marketing executive pointed out in a plea on Biederman’s behalf, it wasn’t
such a good idea to poke the bipolar bear. “I
have never seen someone so angry34,” he e-mailed
his superiors, describing Biederman’s reaction to being denied the research
grant. “Since that time, our business became non-existant [sic]
in his area of control.” Should Johnson & Johnson not cough up the three
grand, the hapless marketer warned, “I am truly afraid of the consequences.”
There were, after all, plenty of other makers of equally unproven
antipsychotics ready to cozy up to this key opinion leader. (Biederman, who
denied any quid pro quo in his arrangement with Johnson & Johnson, was
sanctioned in 2011 for having “violated
certain requirements35” of the university’s policies. The
university forbade him to engage in industry-sponsored activities for one year,
required him to get approval for outside work for the two years immediately
following the ban, and imposed a “delay of consideration for promotion or
advancement.” It did not say how long his elevation to God would have to wait.)
Grassley
wasn’t stopping with Biederman36. He went after
Charles Nemeroff, head of the department of psychiatry at Emory University and
the beneficiary of more than $2.8 million in drug money over seven years,
nearly half of which had gone unreported to the university—a violation of
federal law. He revealed that Frederick
Goodwin37, the psychiatrist who hosted The Infinite Mind, an NPR program, had taken money from drug
companies on the same day he reported that mood stabilizers were safe and
effective treatments for pediatric Bipolar Disorder. (Goodwin responded to
Harris in a lengthy note on his website pointing out that he had never
concealed his drug company ties and that in his talks to psychiatrists he had
discussed lithium, a drug that has been
“generic for decades38 and doesn’t make enough money to
justify promotion by drug companies.”) And Harris reported that Stanford
psychiatrist Alan Schatzberg owned nearly $5
million in stock39 in a drug development
company—which might not have raised an eyebrow but for one thing: Schatzberg
was slated to become the president of the American Psychiatric Association in
May 2009.
Grassley was beginning to set his sights
on the guild to which all these doctors belonged. On July 10, 2008, Jay Scully,
the APA’s CEO, received a letter from Grassley on United States Senate
letterhead. The senator had read the stories in The New York
Times, he wrote, and he was not amused.
I have come to understand40 that money from
the pharmaceutical industry can shape the practices of nonprofit organizations
which purport to be independent in their viewpoints and actions. Specifically,
it is alleged that pharmaceutical companies give money to non-profits in an
attempt to garner favor in ways that increase sales of their products.
Grassley ordered the APA to disclose how
much of its income was drug money. The answer turned out to be a lot—according
to the Times, nearly
one-third of the organization’s $62.5 million annual revenue41
in 2006. Some of it came from advertising, but much of it went to educational
programs in which drug companies tutored doctors attending APA conferences in
the fine points of prescribing their drugs. The problem wasn’t a few rogue
psychiatrists who had somehow risen to the top of their field. It was woven
deeply into the fabric of the profession. It would have been nearly impossible
to justify prescribing antipsychotics sold by any manufacturer to
four-year-olds without the BD diagnosis. And the diagnosis would have been
impossible without a DSM that Biederman could exploit. As the Times had
reported earlier42, the DSM was not immune to
industry influence. The paper cited the
report of a team led by psychologist Lisa Cosgrove43,
which calculated that 56 percent of the doctors who made up the work groups
that produced the DSM-IV had financial ties to Big Pharma. Every member of the
groups recommending changes for mood disorders and psychotic disorders had
received drug money; and, as Cosgrove pointed out, “Pharmaceutical companies have a vested interest44
in what mental disorders are included in the DSM.”
Of course, the drug industry has a vested
interest in disease in general, and it has not restricted its creativity to
psychiatry. Restless legs syndrome45,
for instance, a disease invented as an alternative indication for
GlaxoSmithKline’s underperforming anti-Parkinson’s drug Requip, can’t be blamed
on the DSM. But there is no other field quite so susceptible to diagnostic
exuberance as psychiatry. While many diagnoses are made on clinical signs and
symptoms rather than on lab tests or other external validators, only in
psychiatry are all diagnoses made that way. Psychiatry
may have been low-hanging fruit for Grassley, but it was even riper picking for
the pharmaceutical industry.
• • •
“With every new revelation46,
our credibility with patients has been damaged, and we have to protect that
first and foremost,” former APA president Steven Sharfstein told The New York Times in the aftermath of the Grassley
investigation. “The price we pay for these kinds of revelations is
credibility,” E. Fuller Torrey, one of the country’s most influential
psychiatrists, chimed in, “and we just can’t afford to lose any more of that in
this field.” These doctors probably didn’t know just how closely they were
echoing the lament of Thomas Salmon. It was as if nothing had changed in a century.
And, indeed, in a crucial way nothing had.
That may be part of the reason that the
APA decided that it was time for a radical DSM revision, that even if the
paradigm had not really shifted, they couldn’t afford to stick with the tried
and untrue. Michael First attempted to stop them. He figured he had the juice
to criticize the APA’s reformist ambitions and still be tapped to head up the
new effort. “I thought they would need my skills, so I pushed,” he told me.
But he soon realized he had miscalculated.
“I stood my ground, but it was becoming more and more clear that I was getting
iced out.” And in April 2006, when he heard that the APA had appointed
University of Pittsburgh psychiatry professor David Kupfer as chair of the task
force and Darrel Regier as the vice chair, he was not surprised.
Even five years later I could still hear
disappointment in his voice when he told me, after a long pause, about hearing
the bad news. He sounded a little bitter as he recounted the DSM-5 leadership’s
failure to respond to his offer to repeat his stint as text editor, and its
refusal to take his ideas seriously, but no more than you might expect from a
guy who has seen the opportunity to do what he was born to do snatched away by
people who he thought had the wrong idea of how to go about it.
In the meantime, the task force’s attempts
to get the revision under way were hampered by the shadow of corruption that
was passing over the profession. In The Truth About the Drug
Companies, author and former editor of The New England
Journal of Medicine Marcia Angell had drawn attention to the unsavory
relationship between the industry and the profession. And with a series of
articles in prominent journals, she made it clear that the problem was not a
figment of sensationalist journalists’ imaginations.
Many psychiatrists thought the case
against them was overblown. They insisted that drug company money did not
influence their prescribing habits or, when it came to the DSM, their
deliberations about what would get into the book. They also pointed out that the $4 million or so the industry kicked down
every year47 for the APA’s “educational
programs” amounted to free money for the organization and its members,
providing training that ultimately benefited their patients. But, said Scully,
“my board thought that through48
and instructed me to phase out those programs,” deciding, he told me, that
“public trust was more important than money.”
The board of trustees also decided to
purge the DSM-5 of drug money. Task force and work group members would be able
to hold no more than $50,000 in drug company stock and had to limit their
earnings from the industry to $10,000 annually as long as they served. The
trustees didn’t say how they had established those criteria for diagnosing
corruption. Nor did they seem to have wondered whether this move was really the
best solution to the Pharma infestation. After all, the corruption wasn’t so
much financial as intellectual, the whole psychiatric-industrial consort
dancing together to mutual satisfaction. The drug companies didn’t have to pay
off psychiatrists to create particular diseases, not when whatever disorder
found its way into the DSM could be exploited as an indication for a drug; who
needs conspiracies when you have capitalism?
For their part, psychiatrists didn’t have
to be on the take to be eager to turn all the troubles their patients faced
into nails for their chemical sledgehammers; they only had to want to give
patients relief. And they surely didn’t have to be seduced into the medical
model at lavish lunches, not when from their first days in medical school they
had been, as Freud put it, “flirting with endocrinology and the autonomous
nervous system.” But then again, while the trustees may have been more worried
about public trust than money, they surely were still worried about money,
which would continue to flow only so long as the public was convinced that
psychiatrists were practicing real medicine.
The trustees also underestimated the
difficulty they would have in rounding up psychiatrists willing to take vows of
relative poverty in order to spend years arguing over diagnostic criteria.
Between those requirements and some others—that no university have more than
two members on the same committee, for instance, and that efforts be made to
recruit members from professions other than psychiatry and from outside the
U.S.—it took nearly two years49
from the time Kupfer and Regier were named to the time the eighteen-member task
force was assembled and appointed the 140 or so experts to the work group. So
even as they announced their roster in May 2008, they had to know that their
deadline—May 2012, which meant that they’d have to have a draft ready by the
end of 2011—already loomed impossibly near.
Michael First was not appointed to the
task force. He was not placed on any of the work groups. He was not assigned to
consult with the two work groups that requested him as an expert adviser. In
2007, the APA terminated the contract under which he had been the in-house DSM
expert, representing the organization around the world. He was not alone in
being left out in the cold. “All the people
at the top50 of the previous DSMs were
completely excluded,” he said. “There was some idea that the old forces would
impede the paradigm shift, stand in the way of a new vision.”
But the new forces were already losing
confidence in that vision, or at least hedging their bets. Setting out the
guidelines for making changes, the task force still asserted that “a new diagnostic paradigm must be developed51,”
but it also cautioned that the DSM-5 would “not in itself represent a ‘paradigm
shift.’” It vowed to maintain continuity with past editions, but it also
promised that “unlike in DSM-IV, there will be no a priori constraints on the
degree of change between DSM-IV and DSM-V.”
The new book, it seemed, would be a
departure, but then again, maybe it wouldn’t. The APA wasn’t going to constrain
itself, nor would it commit itself to change. Instead, it would try to have it
both ways.
Chapter 6
One of
Allen Frances’s heroes is Cincinnatus, the Roman dictator who, drafted out of
retirement to lead the army, slaughtered the enemy and promptly abdicated to
return to his beloved farm. In Frances’s version of the story, by the time the
DSM-5 effort got under way, he had lost interest in nosology.
“I was
bored stiff1 with the subject,” he told me. “I
was pursuing another of my life’s goals—being a beach bum.”
That was not the immediate purpose of his
retirement from Duke in 1997, ten years earlier than he had planned. And it
wasn’t boredom that drove him out. “Psychiatric
classification2 may be the only boring topic in
psychiatry,” he said. “Seeing patients and teaching never got boring,” and Duke
offered plenty of opportunities to do that, as well as to travel the world
giving talks, to conduct research, to add to his seventy-plus-page CV, to
collect awards and fellowships, and, if he’d been so inclined, to burnish his
reputation as the most powerful psychiatrist in America. Rather, it was a
personal matter: his wife Vera’s Parkinson’s disease was getting so bad that
she needed his full-time care.
According to the doctors, Vera wasn’t even
supposed to be alive by then. She had been diagnosed in 1988 with brain cancer
and given a year to live. “Perhaps not
surprisingly, the diagnosis3 was unreliable
and imprecise,” Frances said. “And the prognosis was simply wrong.”
In the end it wasn’t the cancer that took
her life. It was the treatment, which had caused her Parkinson’s. After it
worsened in 1997, they moved, first back to New York, where he had spent the
first twenty-five years of his career at Cornell and Columbia (where he worked
with Bob Spitzer), and then to San Diego. When planning for the DSM-5 started
in 1998, he was nursing Vera, sitting on the beach, reading history, and
spending time with his grandchildren, who lived nearby. After Vera died in
2007, he remained uninvolved. But then in 2009 a colleague told him about a
proposal for what Frances thought was an unreliable and imprecise diagnosis
with a questionable prognosis and a dangerous treatment—so dangerous, in fact,
that it got Allen Frances off the beach and into the fight of his professional
life.
Frances had already passed up one
opportunity to weigh in on DSM-5. In 2008, Bob Spitzer had called with some
disturbing news. The previous year, Spitzer, who by then was almost eighty
years old, semiretired, and hobbled by Parkinson’s, had asked the leaders of
the DSM-5 to forward him the minutes of the task force meetings. (Spitzer says
he was just curious.) Initially, the APA agreed to provide them. But then,
after a long silence, the organization informed him that because of the need
for “confidentiality in the development4
process,” his request had been nixed. Only APA trustees and members of the
DSM-5 task force and work groups would be privy to the proceedings. In fact, the APA had insisted5
that no one could participate in the revision without promising in writing
never to reveal what had gone on in their meetings.
Spitzer kept his counsel for a couple of
months. But then in early June 2008, the Psychiatric News ran
a story about the DSM-5. “We are rethinking6
the fundamental structure of DSM,” Regier told the reporter, “which would be a
first since 1980, when DSM-III was produced.” Not only that, but according to
APA president Carolyn Robinowitz, the revision process itself would be
different. The APA was committed to an effort that was “open, transparent, and
free of bias”—an indirect but unmistakable dig at Spitzer, who was known for
his autocratic management style.
“I was
dumbfounded7,” Spitzer told me, “and then
appalled.” It was bad enough that he’d been put out to pasture and that the APA
seemed almost paranoid in its attempt to “not let anyone know what the hell was
going on.” But the article’s disingenuousness in light of his exclusion was
intolerable. “I found out how transparent8
and open the DSM-V process was,” he wrote to the Psychiatric
News. Spitzer recounted his reaction upon discovering that participants
had been forbidden to “divulge, furnish, or make accessible to anyone” any
“pre-publication materials, group discussions, internal correspondence,
information about the development process, or any other written or unwritten information
in any form.”
I didn’t know whether to
laugh or to cry. Laugh—because there is no way task force and work group
members can be made to refrain from discussing the developing DSM-V with their
colleagues. Cry—because this unprecedented attempt to revise DSM in secrecy
indicates a failure to understand that revising a diagnostic manual—as a
scientific process—benefits from the very exchange of information that is
prohibited by the confidentiality agreement.
Spitzer’s complaints,
previously published in the Psychiatric Times, an
independent paper, had already stirred up psychiatrists across the country, and
this latest salvo made the national news.
Spitzer tried to recruit Frances’s support
for his opposition to the gag order. “I told
him I completely agreed9 that this was a disastrous way for
DSM-5 to start,” Frances said. “But I didn’t want to get involved at all. I
wished him luck and went back to the beach.”
But Frances left San Diego long enough to
attend a party for Columbia-affiliated psychiatrists held at San Francisco’s
Asian Art Museum during the APA’s 2009 annual meeting. Among the attendees was
Will Carpenter, the University of Maryland psychiatrist who headed the work
group for psychotic disorders. Carpenter’s committee was considering a proposal
for a new diagnosis to be called Psychosis
Risk Syndrome10. The disorder would address what
some psychiatrists who treated schizophrenia thought was a critical gap in the
DSM-IV. Schizophrenia generally comes on in late adolescence or early
adulthood, but doctors had noticed that many patients’ troubles started long
before, with symptoms that looked like signs of the disease only in retrospect,
after their first psychotic break. Some of these patients had gone to
psychiatrists, often taken as children or adolescents by worried parents. But
even if the kids were behaving bizarrely or harboring strange beliefs or having
hallucinations, their symptoms did not rise to the level of the DSM’s criteria
for schizophrenia. This in turn limited the benefits for which they were
eligible and the treatments that doctors might consider.
To psychiatrists like Carpenter, who spend
their days with patients ravaged by schizophrenia and who could only offer them
sedatives of limited efficacy that made them obese and shortened their life
spans, the idea of catching schizophrenia early and possibly preventing it was
irresistible. If doctors could determine just what those early signals were,
then perhaps they could test for them as they already did for high cholesterol
or blood glucose, identify those who were at risk, and head off the real
trouble before it arrived. In addition, an official diagnosis could attract
research dollars from industry and government, even as it helped psychiatry
keep up with the rest of medicine, which was increasingly interested in early
intervention.
But although researchers thought they had
identified the early warning signs—delusions, hallucinations, or disorganized
speech that didn’t rise to the level of full-fledged psychosis but occurred
more or less weekly for a month and led them or their parents to seek
treatment—and had followed patients who met those criteria for months or years,
they found a conversion
rate of 25 to 30 percent11, meaning that
only something like one-quarter of the patients went on to develop a psychotic
illness. That’s more than in the general population, of course, but still
pretty low for a disorder that purports to predict psychosis.
“I had
not been closely following12 the psychosis risk,” Frances said.
“But I knew enough about it to know that it was an absolute disaster.” Among
the things he knew was that to create a DSM disorder, which is to say a disease
that can be diagnosed by a checklist of symptoms, is to create a huge
opportunity for drug companies to market their products to doctors and
patients—especially when the new diagnosis lowers the threshold for being
declared ill. It was too easy, Frances thought, to confuse normal adolescent
bizarreness—strange haircuts and odd beliefs, high drama, and the occasional
emotional crisis—with the new criteria, especially for harried doctors trying
to help worried parents. And, most dismaying of all, the drugs most likely to
be prescribed for a diagnosis with psychosis in its
name were heavily sedating, obesity-inducing antipsychotic drugs, such as the
ones Biederman had used to treat his bipolar patients.
Frances sought out Carpenter at the party.
“Have you thought through these things?” he asked.
The discussion was brief. Frances saw
someone else he wanted to talk to. “I had a choice of being with my wife and a
friend I don’t get to see,” he told me, “or arguing diagnosis with Will
Carpenter. It was a no-brainer. Basically at that point I just didn’t care that
much.”
But before Frances abandoned the
conversation, he spotted another old hand from Columbia, Harold Pincus. He
called Pincus over, explained the situation, and asked him to pick up the
argument where he was leaving off. “Harold is smarter than me and more
articulate and more precise. So I figured it was no great loss.”
Carpenter
explained to Pincus13 what he says he would have told
Frances if he had stuck around: that there were other ways in which these
patients were set off from the rest of the world—“alterations in cognition,”
Carpenter told me, “and changes in gray matter.” He explained to Pincus that
the studies followed kids who were in treatment, which might have accounted for
the low conversion rates, and might, in fact, indicate that the diagnosis was a
good idea. He told Pincus he didn’t think drugs were necessarily indicated for
these patients, that they could be provided with psychosocial
treatments—which is what psychiatrists call therapy these days—and watchful waiting.
While Carpenter argued his
case—unsuccessfully, according to Pincus, who told me, “I still think it’s a crazy idea14”—Frances
set off on a tour of the museum. But the conversation stayed on his mind. It
reminded him of other times that he had remained silent while his profession
launched diagnostic epidemics on an unsuspecting public. Some, like the
childhood bipolar debacle, had had nothing to do with him; the DSM-IV
committees had not even taken up the question of childhood mania. But others
were the direct result of DSM-IV, and Frances regretted them.
One of the worst of these, in his view,
was called Bipolar II Disorder. It was among the few new disorders introduced
in DSM-IV. The doctors who had proposed it were trying to fix a problem that
had arisen in the few years since Prozac had been introduced: the new generation
of antidepressants had a tendency to cause depressed patients to become
manic—what psychiatrists call switching. Although
these patients had never been manic before, closer examination showed that they
had had episodes of hypomania—times when they had a
mood “clearly different from the usual nondepressed mood,” but not fully manic,
and not lasting as long as a full-blown manic episode. Four days of “elevated,
expansive, or irritable mood,” a decreased need for sleep, and increases in
“distractibility” and “goal-directed activity” were now enough to qualify for
what had once been considered a rare and debilitating disease. The lowered
diagnostic threshold came along just before the FDA gave the drug industry the
go-ahead to market their drugs directly to the public, thus changing forever
the meaning of the phrase “Talk to your doctor.” Advertisements touting Zyprexa
and Abilify and other antipsychotic drugs as treatments for the new disease
soon appeared; suddenly twice as many people had bipolar disorders as
previously thought, and antipsychotics rocketed to the top of the charts. Some
key opinion leaders were suggesting to their colleagues that many of their
patients—indeed as much as 5 percent of the population—weren’t depressed but
rather were on the “bipolar spectrum,” which is why they weren’t responding to
antidepressants and should be switched to antipsychotics.
“We couldn’t have foreseen any of this,”
Frances said. But he did see it happening, and he failed to use his clout as
head of the DSM-IV to speak out against it. He had also remained silent when he
was vice chair of the APA’s program committee in the 1980s and the
pharmaceutical industry had all but taken over the organization’s training
programs. And there was one other time he had not spoken up, and he now
regretted it. Early in his training at the New York State Psychiatric
Institute, he had taken on a patient, a medical student. He had diagnosed him
with pseudoneurotic schizophrenia15—“a
local concoction invented by the PI director,” Frances remembered, “and one
that everyone seemed to us to have.” The effect of this diagnostic fad on the
patient, who Frances thinks now was merely anxious and depressed, not
schizophrenic, was devastating. “We kept him locked up for a year,” he said,
and the patient never got back to medical school. “It was the original sin of
my career.”
As he toured the museum, Frances said,
these failures nagged at him. The prospect of “more
kids getting unneeded antipsychotics16 that would make
them gain twelve pounds in twelve weeks hit me in the gut.” And if Will
Carpenter—“a fine man and a great psychiatrist”—couldn’t see the danger, then
no one else was likely to. “I was stuck without an excuse,” he told me. “If not
me to correct it, who? If not now, when?”
When the tour was over, Frances found Bob
Spitzer’s wife at the party. (Spitzer was too ill to attend.) He told her to
tell Spitzer that he’d be joining his crusade. He never returned to his
conversation with Carpenter. But Carpenter already knew something momentous had
happened. “It was over in seconds,” he said, “but it lasted just long enough
for it to be clear that the trigger had been pulled.”
Chapter 7
The first
time Jay Scully met with his DSM-5 troops, in the spring of 2008, he warned
them about what they were getting themselves into. “People are going to write dissertations1
on what you are doing. Reporters are going to be all over you. It’s probably
going to be DSM-5: The Musical.”
The drama started almost immediately. The
task force appointed Kenneth Zucker, a University of Toronto psychologist, to
head up the sexual and gender identity disorders work group. Among the group’s
members was another Toronto psychologist, Ray Blanchard. The appointment of two
non-American nonpsychiatrists may have helped the diversity statistics, but it
infuriated transgendered people, who had a direct stake in the outcome.
Zucker
was known for research2 purporting to show that the
conviction that one had been born with the wrong sexual organs was acquired and
thus, at least in some cases, malleable. He argued that some young children who
expressed the desire to be the opposite sex should be discouraged from acting
out their wishes, that girls who wanted to play with soldiers should be given
dolls and that boys who wanted to wear skirts should be forced to dress like
little men, lest they grow up into people with Gender Identity Disorder (GID).
For his part, Blanchard had earned the wrath of the transgendered by suggesting
that at least some of them did not suffer from having been born with the wrong
sex organs, but rather that they derived erotic pleasure from fantasizing that
they were the opposite sex, a fetish
Blanchard called autogynephilia3.
To many transsexuals, Blanchard’s
suggestion that their condition was nothing more than an abnormal sexual inclination—what
the DSM calls a paraphilia—seemed to trivialize their
suffering, and Zucker’s notion that transgender children could be put back on
the right track smacked of the bad old days of sexual reorientation therapy for
homosexuals. And they had a very practical concern: surgeons and
endocrinologists would not provide sex-change procedures (and couldn’t get paid
by insurers) without an official diagnosis of GID. If Blanchard’s and Zucker’s
views carried the day, the work group might modify or remove a diagnosis that
had been crucial to the gains transgender people had made.
Nearly as soon as the appointments were
announced, the protests started rolling into APA headquarters. The National Gay
and Lesbian Task Force, which had led the charge against the homosexuality
diagnosis in 1973, issued a press release charging that Zucker and Blanchard
were “out of step4”
and that the APA was not “keeping up with the times when it comes to serving
the needs of transgender adults and gender-variant children.” If the irony of
pleading with psychiatrists not to take away a
diagnosis that explicitly pathologized an inborn condition occurred to them,
they did not note it in the communiqué.
In late May, the APA sent out a statement
pledging a “thorough and balanced5”
revision that would be “based on sound scientific data but also sensitive to
the needs of clinicians and patients.” The effort would start with an
assessment of “DSM-IV’s strengths and problems,” move to a “comprehensive
review of scientific advancements,” and then, using “targeted research analyses
and clinical expertise,” generate changes that would be subject to scrutiny
from the larger professional community before being assembled into a final
draft. There would even be a website where the public could eventually take a
crack at the proposed revisions. The process would be orderly, deliberative,
rational, nonarbitrary, and, it seemed, prolonged—too prolonged to be getting
into particulars at this point.
It was a strange way to make a case for
the scientific soundness of the DSM-5. After all, if the revision was going to
be scientific, then why would the APA need to be sensitive to the needs of
clinicians or patients or, for that matter, anyone else? A revision of cancer
nosology based on “scientific advancements” like the increased ability to
genotype tumors might conclude that certain patients actually belong in a
different diagnostic category from the one they currently occupied. This might
render them no longer eligible for treatment—a development that ought to make
doctors sensitive to their patients as they deliver the bad news, but one that
should not figure into whether or not the diagnosis is revised. As Joseph Biederman
might have pointed out, if Galileo had been sensitive to the needs of the
priests, we might still think that the sun moves around the earth.
The authors of the APA statement seemed to
grasp this problem. After reassuring all the “stakeholders” that they would be
listened to, they ended by urging people to recognize that “the DSM is a diagnostic manual6
and does not provide treatment recommendations or guidelines.” Those complaints
had evidently gone to the wrong department. Not that such a department existed,
at least not yet, but the APA did promise to set up a committee to look into
the matter of GID treatment. In the meantime, perhaps because it was so proud
of itself for listening to complaints that were, by its lights, irrelevant, the
APA didn’t seem to notice that, as it had when it came to the “paradigm shift,”
it was signaling that it would take whatever position was expedient, even if it
ended up both asserting and undermining its scientific authority in the same
one-page statement.
Scully had barely put out the GID fire
when the Psychiatric News ran Spitzer’s letter
complaining about the gag order. He teamed up with Regier, Kupfer, and Nada
Stotland, then the APA president, to fashion an
immediate rejoinder7. Spitzer, they wrote, had
misunderstood the intent of the confidentiality agreement. The organization was
only trying to protect work group members from any “fear of recrimination” that
might pressure them into “premature conclusions and misconceptions,” which
might “damage the viability of DSM-V.” They did not spell out exactly who might
seek recrimination, or what form it would take, or why, if the process was
scientific, any of that should matter. They didn’t explain how sheltering their
experts from outside views would help them be sensitive to the concerns of the
rest of the world or protect the rest of the world from experts like Joseph
Biederman. Neither did they elaborate on the claim that controversy could be
harmful, let alone on what it meant to “damage the viability” of the DSM.
But the APA leaders didn’t really think
they needed to answer such questions. In fact, in their view, it was Spitzer
who had some explaining to do. He had failed to acknowledge the long public
record, dating back to the Research Agenda, and
including fourteen books and more than eighty peer-reviewed papers, all of
which were in the public domain (even if they had been authored mostly by the
same experts who were now being protected from controversy). He had given short
shrift to the fact that the APA had “invested a great deal of effort to develop
a process allowing appropriate communication while protecting the integrity and
value of the DSM-V.” And he had misrepresented the agreement by failing to note
a parenthetical clause allowing members to divulge material “as necessary to
fulfill the obligations of [his or her] appointment.” A member who isn’t quite
sure if he or she would be in violation, they added, “can simply ask.” People
evidently could say whatever they liked, as long as they got permission.
Two years later, in fall 2010, Scully
tried to be philosophical about this drama—“I suppose that’s the nature of the
scientific process; scientists argue with each other”—but he was leaning
forward, bouncing his arms on his knees, like he was having a little trouble
staying in his seat. He is a big man, a blue-eyed blond with fair skin that
flushes when he’s mad, which he was now that I had brought up this subject. He was
evidently still smarting from the attack, which he thought was “pretty
personal” and totally misplaced. In fact, Scully said, anyone was free to say
anything. He didn’t mention the part about getting permission.
Neither did Darrel Regier. In our interview
the next day, I told him about a work group member, a psychiatrist who would
talk to me only anonymously and who had declined to ask permission—for fear, he
said, of “reprisal.” Regier wanted to know8
who the doctor was.
I described a conversation I’d had
recently with a psychiatrist named Sid Zisook. Thinking he was a task force
member, I had asked Zisook if he had reservations about letting me interview
him. “I’m not on the task force9,”
he told me. “And if I were, I wouldn’t be talking to you.”
“Sid said this?” Regier asked. He looked
wounded.
David Kupfer had joined us by phone from
his office in Pittsburgh, so I couldn’t see his reaction. But there was hurt in
his voice as he explained that he had “encouraged everybody to talk”—so much
so, he said, that colleagues in other specialties were saying, “My God! Nothing
like this has ever happened in internal medicine or pediatrics. You guys are
pretty brave to put all that stuff out there.”
Before I could ask Kupfer if he was
calling Zisook a coward, Regier spoke up. “I’m putting myself in Sid’s shoes,”
he said. “I think the secrecy stuff was so well sold by some of our critics
that even some of our friends started to believe it.”
And it’s not only the critics who had
victimized the APA. It was also their own people, although not the
psychiatrists. “Unfortunately, the lawyers . . . It’s a misnamed thing,” Scully
said. All the lawyers were interested in was “protecting the integrity and
value of the DSM-V.” The gag order was actually an “intellectual property
agreement” designed to prevent anyone from using “material that belongs to the
APA” for their own personal enrichment. And this wasn’t just any intellectual
property, but one that “we’re putting $25 million into creating” and whose
value could be diluted if some unscrupulous psychiatrist decided to publish his
own DSM, or maybe write an embarrassing tell-all musical. This was what the
lawyers had failed to make clear, what Spitzer had misunderstood, and what made
the wound he inflicted all the more grievous: that the APA, like any
corporation, had to protect its brand against pirates and bad publicity.
• • •
“We have enemies10,”
APA president Nada Stotland told her troops as they assembled for their 162nd
annual meeting in May 2009. Antipsychiatry was alive and well, and its troops
would be sure “to use doubts about the DSM to undermine our profession.” It was
as if only people out to get the APA would question its credibility.
Stotland didn’t say exactly whom she had
in mind, although she did mention the Church of Scientology, whose most
prominent member, Tom Cruise, had publicly scolded his ex, Brooke Shields, for
taking Paxil and then told NBC’s Matt Lauer that “psychiatry is a pseudoscience11”
and “there is no such thing as a chemical imbalance.” Stotland probably would
have counted those pesky transsexuals among them as well. But it’s a safe bet
that she wasn’t thinking of Allen Frances and Bob Spitzer. On the other hand,
she gave the speech the night before Will Carpenter pulled Frances’s trigger.
Frances didn’t bother with warning shots.
In July 2009, he fired off a full-on salvo from his BlackBerry—his sole link to
the Internet, which he’d purchased a couple of years previously, and only after
“Michael First shamed me into it12”
by telling him that if he didn’t have a link to the Internet, Frances’s
grandchildren would come to regard him as he had regarded his Yiddish-speaking
grandfather. It was the first time he’d used the device for anything other than
e-mail.
The three-thousand-word missive ended up
in the June 26 issue of the Psychiatric Times. Under
the headline “A Warning Sign on the Road to DSM-V: Beware of Its Unintended
Consequences,” Frances wrote that his successors had “displayed the most
unhappy combination of soaring ambition and weak methodology.” Their attempt to
effect a paradigm change was “absurdly premature.” They were heedless of the
fact that because psychiatry was “stuck at its current descriptive level . . .
until we make a fundamental leap in our understanding of what causes mental
disorders . . . there is little to be gained and much to be lost in . . .
changing the system.” They had compounded that error by populating the work
groups with experts from “the atypical setting of university psychiatry,” whose
clinical experience was limited to “highly select patients treated in a
research context” and who tended to be far more worried about “missed cases”
than about diagnosing people with illnesses who weren’t really sick. The task
force had given them precious little guidance, leaving the experts free to pursue
their pet projects, like Psychosis Risk Syndrome. And they were preparing to
field-test the new diagnoses, using them with real patients in the controlled
settings of academic medical centers, without having first subjected the new
criteria to outside scrutiny and then refined them, as Frances had in the
DSM-IV. Conducting a field trial on what amounted to a rough draft of the new
DSM would be “flying blind.” It couldn’t possibly tell psychiatrists anything
about how the final draft would perform in the real world.
This was Frances’s biggest complaint: that
the DSM-5 leaders seemed heedless of the way that the new revision threatened
to put psychiatry even more into the “business of manufacturing mental
disorders” and that those lowered thresholds and new diagnoses and revamped
criteria would touch off diagnostic epidemics. “The result would be a wholesale
imperial medicalization of normality,” he wrote, “a bonanza for the
pharmaceutical industry but at a huge cost to the new patients caught in the
excessively wide DSM-V net.” Operating in an echo chamber of experts, secretive
and sealed off from outside views by its “ludicrous confidentiality
agreements,” the task force couldn’t even see how far off course it had veered.
Neither could it grasp how far behind schedule it already was, how time
pressure would “soon lead to an unconsidered rush of last-minute decisions.”
Barring a “midterm course correction”—which Frances thought required the
appointment of an external review committee with no ties to the DSM—the DSM-5
would be “an embarrassment and a burden to the field,” creating problems that
would “haunt psychiatry for many years to come.”
The APA didn’t waste any time firing back.
“Setting the Record Straight13”
appeared in the next week’s issue of the Psychiatric Times under
the byline of the organization’s new president, Alan Schatzberg (the Stanford
psychiatrist whose drug company ties had raised Grassley’s dander), along with
Scully, Regier, and Kupfer. They accused Frances, as they had Spitzer before
him, of launching his salvo with “disregard for the facts”; taken together,
these were “unjustified ad hominem attacks” to which the APA now reluctantly
had to respond.
“The process for developing the DSM-V has
been the most inclusive ever,” they wrote. More than 400 scientists and 200
advisers had bolstered the 150 experts from sixteen countries who constituted
the task force and work groups. Their discussions had not been inhibited by the
confidentiality agreements, nor had any of them been stopped from presenting at
professional meetings, in journals, and even “in countless interviews to the
mainstream press.” Indeed, if the proceedings were really secret, they asked,
then how could Frances have gotten hold of enough information to fashion his
litany in the first place? It wasn’t their fault that he had mistaken their
drafts as “final decisions, rather than as statements of work in progress.” Far
from being secretive, the DSM leaders were really the victims of their own
transparency.
Frances had gotten one thing right: “The
DSM-V work groups were freed from the constraints inherent in DSM-IV’s
conservative process.” The task force had not, however, simply emancipated them
from Frances’s shackles. They had given the committees marching orders: to
optimize clinical utility, to use research evidence to guide their
recommendations, and to maintain continuity with previous editions. “We are
setting up a process that will allow the new DSM to change with new developments,
rather than being reified for a decade or more,” they wrote. The authors didn’t
add “like some DSMs we know.”
Neither did they name Spitzer or Frances
when they complained that the “DSM-III categorical diagnoses are now holding us
back,” or that the “DSM-IV system poorly reflects the clinical realities of
[our] patients,” or that “researchers are skeptical that the existing DSM
categories represent a valid basis for scientific investigations.” And they
left out Frances’s name when they suggested that what some might see as a
revision in disarray and up against time constraints was really only the rapid
process made possible “thanks to new publishing technologies, not even imagined
in the early 1990s.” The DSM could be nimble, not the lumbering beast Frances
had created and with which they were now stuck.
In case the point wasn’t clear, and
speaking of ad hominem attacks, the APA signed off by reminding readers that
Frances had promised them a “full disclosure” at the outset of his screed,
allowing that “it is reasonable for you to wonder whether I have an inherently
conservative bias or am protecting my own DSM-IV baby.”
“It is unfortunate,” the APA leaders
wrote, “that Dr. Frances failed to take this [promise] to heart when he did not
disclose his continued financial interests in several publications based on
DSM-IV.” As a matter of fact, they went on, he had been informed—at the very
same APA meeting at which he had suddenly become galvanized—that his royalties
would end upon publication of the new revision. This coincidence, the APA
suggested to readers, was something that “should be considered when evaluating
his critique and its timing.”
Allen Frances had made his way onto the
APA’s enemies list. Of course, that wasn’t how Schatzberg was going to put it.
Nor would Will Carpenter, when he ended his own Psychiatric
Times rebuttal by responding to Frances’s charge that the task force was
overly ambitious. “Soaring ambition is
another matter14,” he wrote. “Here my empathy is
with Allen. If I had directed DSM-IV, I imagine that I would think that anyone
trying to improve on my work must be very ambitious indeed.” Nor would Renato
Alarcon, a work group member, when he suggested, also in the Psychiatric
Times, that Frances was “letting
nostalgia and passion15 obstruct clarity of vision.”
Instead of talking about enemies and taking the risk of sounding even more
paranoid, they did what their training told them to do when confronted with
disturbing behavior. They offered empathy, even pity, and, of course, a
diagnosis.
• • •
Not that you need special
training to approach enmity in this fashion, although psychiatrists may be
better at turning supposed insight into a person’s character into a weapon.
Passive aggression may be particularly unseemly when it comes from the people
in charge of our mental health, but claiming that a person who disagrees is ill
motivated, that his objections are really the result of malfeasance or dishonesty,
that if he weren’t deluded by ideology or greed or ignorance, if he weren’t
somehow pathological, then he’d come to see things the right way—this is a
ubiquitous feature of American political life.
And here is a place where science, at
least the psychiatric form of it, and politics really come together. Whether
among senators or psychiatrists, the exchange of diagnoses generates more heat
than light, and the smoke it gives off obscures the trouble that gave rise to
the disturbing behavior in the first place. But there was one vulnerability
that no one, defender or critic, was discussing, at least not in public. Even
Frances muted this concern in the blogs he was thumbing out with regularity,
which now appeared in Psychology Today as well as the Psychiatric Times. He did, however, address it in a letter
to the APA trustees that was also signed by Spitzer. “You must understand16,”
they wrote, “that the APA has never held a guarantee on the DSM franchise.
There have been serious objections in the past that it is inappropriate for one
professional ‘guild’ to control a document with such wide usage and great
public health importance.” Frances knew that psychiatrists had been lucky
enough to be in the right place—asylums—at a time when the Census Bureau took a
sudden interest in counting the insane. History had bestowed the franchise on
the APA, and history could take it away—and with it the riches it had brought
the guild.
When Frances and Spitzer warned the trustees
that to ignore this was to “bet the house,” they meant that literally. The APA’s financial picture17
was bleak, the organization battered by hard economic times and the partial
purge of Pharma. Income from the drug industry, which amounted to more than $19
million in 2006, had shrunk to $11 million by 2009, and was projected to fall
even more. Membership was dropping, off by nearly 15 percent from its highs,
and with it income from dues and attendance fees. Journal advertising was off
by 50 percent from its 2006 high of $10 million. Only the DSM-IV had remained
steady, reliably bringing in between $5 and $6 million annually, nearly 10
percent of the APA’s income and just enough to keep the APA in the black. Losing
that money could be fatal. The credibility problem first noticed by Thomas
Salmon now had a price tag on it.
The APA already had a competitor for its
franchise: the World Health Organization. Its International Classification of
Diseases had an entire section devoted to psychiatric disorders. In fact, the
diagnosis codes found in the DSM are really taken from the ICD. As Michael
First, who now works on the ICD, pointed out, “In
reality, clinicians in the United States18, all of us,
don’t ever have to buy a copy of the DSM.” Most practitioners don’t know this,
he added—at least not yet. But “the franchise depends on the quality of the
book. If they put out a crappy product, people could just say, ‘This is so bad,
I don’t need to use it anymore. I’ll just go use the ICD.’” And when we
therapists go to do that, we will discover something else that most of us don’t
know: the ICD, created by a public agency,
is available for download19 from the WHO’s website. It won’t
take up any space on our bookshelves, and, perhaps its best selling point,
anyone can browse it for free.
That fact is likely to impress many
clinicians who think they have to shell out two hundred bucks when the new book
comes out, especially when they discover that the ICD is quick and to the
point—no checklists to go down, no long pages about prevalence or family
characteristics or recording procedures, which are of much less interest than,
say, reimbursement rates, to the average clinician. The APA leaders had to know
that all the spin control, all the denunciations, all the confidentiality
agreements in the world might not be enough to counter the fact that stalwarts
like Frances and First were doubting the soundness of the new book. If a crappy
product unleashed a public battle, then the rest of us might discover that the
DSM was nowhere near as necessary as it had been cracked up to be. That
wouldn’t be good for the APA’s bottom line.
And here is another way in which the
politics of DSM resembles the politics of the larger world. For who can doubt
that what politicians are really arguing about is money?
• • •
Even when they weren’t
arguing so openly about dollars—back in the 1970s, before anyone knew that the
DSM-III would be a bestseller—the writers of the DSM understood that turning
diagnosis into a bureaucratic function left them with only an aspirational
relationship to modern medicine. Spitzer may have wrested psychiatry from
Freud’s grasp and dipped it into the stream of scientific rhetoric, but where
he held it most firmly was where it was the weakest. He had left the profession
unable to stave off the next drapetomania, except perhaps on the grounds of
decency and common sense—important considerations, but not scientific or immune
to local mores.
Having eliminated theories about the
nature and causes of mental illness, Spitzer had also taken away his
colleagues’ ability to draw a line between illness and health. A man may be
feeling as fit as a fiddle, but a radiologist who spots a mass in his lung or a
cardiologist looking at the results of an echocardiogram might have a better
idea about his state of health. A woman may be missing her period, suffering
nausea in the morning, and feeling lousy all day, but an obstetrician who can
read a blood test can reassure her that she is not sick, only pregnant. But no
psychiatrist, listening to a patient’s woes, can listen to his complaints and
offer similarly certain appraisals.
This was not merely an abstract problem
for Spitzer. For he was well aware there was at least one group of people who
met all the criteria for a mental illness but who, on the other hand, could
only be considered sick at the risk of psychiatry’s always fragile credibility.
Their existence was confirmed not by an enemy of psychiatry playing gotcha, but
by one of the DSM-III’s own—a Washington University psychiatrist and task force
member named Paula Clayton. She was part of the team that had perfected the
Research Diagnostic Criteria, the prototype of the DSM-III approach, and she
had made an unsettling if unsurprising
discovery20: people who had recently suffered
the death of a loved one often had at least five of the nine symptoms of
depression, which meant that if you went strictly by the book, they were
mentally ill.
The grief over grief was a scientific and
political disaster waiting to happen. How would it look when clinicians began
to diagnose mourners with mental illness and declared for themselves a
territory that was among the last bastions of religion? And yet if a clinician,
suffering from a sudden attack of common sense, was free to decide that the
patient wasn’t really sick even if he met the criteria, then wouldn’t that
return psychiatry to the days when clinicians’ assumptions determined the line
between illness and health, and psychiatry was reviled for its unreliability?
Spitzer’s solution was characteristically
wily. He carved out an exception to the depression diagnosis and deftly
inserted it at the back of the DSM-III. In a section called “Conditions Not
Attributable to a Mental Disorder That Are a Focus of Treatment or Attention,”
a clinician could learn that the recently bereaved may well have all the
symptoms of depression, but because “a full
depressive syndrome21 frequently is a normal reaction to
the death of a loved one,” the patient’s condition was better understood as
Uncomplicated Bereavement. Clinicians confronted with the absurdities of the
descriptive approach were thus given cover to ignore it even as their
prerogative to treat the recently bereaved was preserved (although insurers
rarely if ever pay for treatment of those non-mental-disorder conditions).
The bereavement exclusion22, as it came to
be known, became part of the diagnostic criteria in the DSM-III-R, where it
acquired a time limit: after two months of meeting five of the nine criteria,
the bereaved became mentally ill. But certain thorny matters—notably, whether
or not a clinician should distinguish among the death of a parent or child, the
death of a celebrity, and the death of the family dog—remained up to the
individual clinician to decide. Even so, it was a win-win, which may be why no
one seemed to notice that the loophole amounted to saying that people who had
all the symptoms of a disorder had the disorder—unless they
didn’t. The criteria didn’t really add up to a mental illness until a
doctor determined that a disorder was present and by this judgment transformed
suffering into the symptoms of a disease.
This is, in part, as it should be. Isn’t
this what we go to doctors for—to learn, from someone who knows,
the true nature of our suffering, to find out whether that nagging pain is the
leading edge of something horrible or just a random twinge, to find out if our
persistent malaise is grief or depression or maybe even a malfunctioning
thyroid? Even before we ask for remedy, this is what we ask of our doctors: to
lay bare the beginnings of our suffering, to elicit our present crisis, to tell
us what is going to happen in the end. Without that story, we might not take
their pills, and—since so much of our response to medication is the result of
placebo effects, and placebo effects in turn depend on the patient’s belief in
his or her doctor—the pills might not work.
On the other hand, most of us won’t accept
just any tale about our woes. We want our doctors’ stories about us to be based
in fact, not opinion. We want them to make sense, which, if they start telling
us that grieving the loss of a parent is an illness, they don’t. That’s why the
bereavement exclusion was necessary: without it, the DSM loses its credibility,
and the doctors who use it cannot perform their healing magic.
• • •
Spitzer did something else to
juice the credibility of the DSM-III, something that no one else had done, at
least not in a diagnostic manual: he tried
to define disease23. This is harder,
and a lot more audacious, than it might seem. Like life
and obscenity, disease is one of those phenomena that
you might recognize when you see it—but go ahead and try to define it.
You have to admire Spitzer for making the
attempt, for not simply cribbing Webster’s and then
moving on to his list of diseases and the symptoms by which they would be
known. But you also have to understand that he really had no choice. So long as
psychiatry had no scientific knowledge about which ingredient was missing from
the chemical soup roiling inside your head, so long, that is, as diagnosis was
still a matter of a doctor deciding that you had a disease and then telling you
which one it was, psychiatrists needed to be able to say with certainty how
they made that decision, and why it wasn’t simply a matter of personal
prerogative. They needed a definition that would serve as a gatekeeper to the
kingdom of illness, that would reassure the public that the profession didn’t
intend to claim sovereignty over all our troubles, that would keep
homosexuality out and depression in—that would, as Spitzer put it in the
introduction to DSM-III, “present concepts
that have influenced the decision24 to include
certain conditions and to exclude others.” Without that barrier, DSM would not
be a medical text but a collection of old wives’ tales.
Spitzer understood from the beginning that
the commonsense definition of disease—“a progressive physical disorder with
known pathophysiology”—simply couldn’t be stretched to cover mental illness. He
finessed this problem by proposing that disease was
only one of a number of medical disorders—conditions
that had “negative consequences . . . an inferred or identified organismic
dysfunction, and an implicit call to action.” Mental disorder, he argued25, was “a medical
disorder whose manifestations are primarily signs or symptoms of a
psychological (behavioral) nature.” This was a clever move on Spitzer’s part,
acknowledging that mental illnesses were not diseases in the usual sense, even
as he preserved their place in “real medicine.”
But it wasn’t clever enough to sneak past
the members of the American Psychological Association, who immediately
recognized the proposal as a way to maintain physician dominion over mental
suffering, and they sent a letter protesting it.
“These
guys have some chutzpah26,” Spitzer groused to the APA’s
president as he prepared a letter in response. But he didn’t dispute the
psychologists’ conclusion. Indeed, he may have gotten a fight he’d been
spoiling for all along. He suggested that the exchange of letters be “made
public to our membership, as it would be another way of demonstrating our conviction
that psychiatry is a specialty within medicine. It would also make it clear to
our profession that DSM-III helps psychiatry move closer to the rest of
medicine.” If they saw their generals aggressively moving to consolidate their
power, Spitzer thought, the morale of the rank and file might improve.
The definition Spitzer finally settled on
wasn’t quite so chauvinistic as the original. But it had plenty of its own
chutzpah.
In DSM-III each of the mental disorders27
is conceptualized as a clinically significant behavioral or psychological
syndrome or pattern that occurs in an individual and that is typically
associated with either a painful symptom (distress) or impairment in one or
more important areas of functioning (disability). In addition, there is an
inference that there is a behavioral, psychological or biological dysfunction,
and that the disturbance is not only in the relationship between the individual
and society. (When the disturbance is limited to a
conflict between the individual and society, this may represent social
deviance, which may or may not be commendable, but is not by itself a mental
disorder.)
Mental disorder occurs,
Spitzer seems to be saying, when something has gone wrong in the mental
apparatus, and the result is distress or disability. But what is the tip-off
that something has gone wrong? The presence of distress or disability, of
course. And how can a doctor determine whether it is clinically
significant? The definition doesn’t specify, but one obvious method is
to say that the mere fact that a patient’s suffering is significant enough to
make him or her show up at the clinic suffices. And once the patient has
arrived, who gets to decide whether the disturbance is limited to a conflict
between individuals and society, whether, say, an impoverished person’s
distress is caused by poverty or internal dysfunction? Doctors, of course, who
might be no more reliable at judging whether a person needs psychiatric
treatment than barbers are at judging whether a person needs a haircut.
This definition, an obvious response to
the homosexuality debacle, was an attempt by the general to fight the last war,
and it doesn’t really make diagnosis any less circular. Indeed, it just places
the already circular definitions of the individual mental disorders inside the
larger circle of clinical significance. And in case you weren’t dizzy enough,
the DSM-III-R added one more loop: “The
syndrome or pattern28 must not be merely an expectable
and culturally sanctioned response to a particular event.” For its part, DSM-IV devoted seven of its 886 pages29
to a list of “culture-bound syndromes,” including ataque de
nervios, an “idiom of distress” common in Latin American groups that an
unsuspecting doctor might mistake for an anxiety disorder; pibloktoq,
an “abrupt dissociative episode” found among Eskimos, in which a person might
rend his or her garments, break furniture, or eat feces, but does not suffer
from mania or Dissociative Identity Disorder; and koro,
an “intense anxiety that the penis will recede into the body and possibly cause
death” that sometimes afflicts Malaysians but which should not be mistaken for
a psychosis or Depersonalization Disorder.
The impetus here is obvious. The gay
activism that led to the deletion of homosexuality was on the leading edge of
the identity politics that took hold in the 1980s and 1990s. The DSM had to
keep up with the times, to reassure the public that psychiatrists were not out
to pathologize mere difference or to declare certain identities inherently
sick. But how is a physician to know what responses we should expect of
ourselves when confronted by unprecedented events like 9/11 or the financial
meltdown of 2008? Why is a response that is neither expectable nor culturally
sanctioned, but clearly justified, such as, say, occupying Wall Street, any
more disordered than blithely taking home multimillion-dollar bonuses for
running a company into the ground? And why do doctors get to decide which, if
any, of those behaviors is symptomatic of Antisocial Personality Disorder?
Like the bereavement exclusion, these
definitions don’t really serve to limit psychiatry’s prerogative to decide what
is sick and what is healthy. Instead, they daub whitewash over the fractures in
its conceptual infrastructure. And the result is an edifice that holds up only
if you don’t place any weight on it.
In this respect, all these loopholes are
not unlike epicycles, the little curlicues Ptolemaic astronomers built into the
orbits of planets to account for why the heavenly bodies were not where they
should have been if they moved, as Ptolemy said they must, in perfect circles.
Epicycles, not unlike the codicils and caveats in the DSM, are a way to stave
off the challenge of the enemy, intended more to preserve the authority of a
profession and the dominion of its paradigms than to get to the truth. Unlike
the DSM, epicycles have already gone down in history as the epitome of bad
science.
Chapter 8
If
psychiatry’s attempt to close the gap between opportunity and knowledge with a
definition of mental disorder will always yield bullshit, psychiatry’s
aspirations to scientific respectability are still not doomed—at least not
according to Allen Frances. But you have to be willing to accept one premise:
that, as he puts it, “psychiatric
classification is necessarily1 a sloppy
business.”
But even if the definition of mental
disorder is bullshit, Frances thinks, the mental disorders themselves are not.
The categories may be arbitrary, their existence impossible to prove, and the
lines between them as artificial as the lines between countries, but the fact
is that an identifiable group of people do, for instance, have “recurrent and persistent thoughts2”
that are “intrusive, inappropriate and cause marked distress,” that are “not
simply excessive worries about real-life problems,” that can only be suppressed
by some “other thought or action,” and that are recognized as “a product of
[the patient’s] own mind.” To say, as the DSM-IV does, that those people have
Obsessive-Compulsive Disorder is not, in Frances’s view, to make any grand
claims about how (or even whether) mental illness exists in nature. It is only
to glean from research what unites this population of sufferers and then to
capture it in language that helps clinicians communicate with patients and
colleagues and that provides researchers with categories for their work in
developing treatments. A DSM diagnosis may be a construct, in other words, but
it is not only a construct.
Neither does using a label require some
guiding definition about whose troubles are illness and whose mere suffering.
Implementing labels requires only a faithful observation of people who come to
doctors’ attention, a careful sorting of patients, a scrupulous attention to
detail in fashioning the criteria, and then a highly skilled, careful clinician,
one to whom the sloppiness of classification is a reason to exercise caution.
And if all those conditions are in place, the criteria will indeed detect
populations who can then be served by doctors alerted to the contours, if not
the exact nature, of their patients’ troubles. The diagnostician, to use one of
Frances’s favorite metaphors, is not so much a pathologist looking for a virus
in a blood sample as he is a baseball umpire trained to call balls and
strikes—even if an agreement to abide by an ultimately arbitrary tradition is
the reason that pitches have those names and the strike zone has the exact
boundaries that it does.
That’s why Frances was so galled by the
ambition that he saw in his successors, and why they seemed so reckless to him:
they had failed to account for the fragility of a system that hinges on rules
inscribed in language rather than on lab tests encoded in numbers. They were
heedless of the possibility that once doctors started speaking the revised
language, all kinds of hell could break loose. And even worse, they seemed to
have lost track of the people who would be consigned to that hell: the
patients.
“A
diagnosis is a call to action3 with huge and
unpredictable results,” he said. “No decision can be right on narrow scientific
grounds if it winds up hurting people.”
The Bipolar II epidemic was a case in
point. There was no question in Frances’s mind that making a new diagnosis was
the correct decision on narrow scientific grounds. Research clearly showed that
people who became manic after starting antidepressants tended to have a history
of hypomanic episodes and that those spells tended to last for less than the
week required for a diagnosis of mania. But he failed to consider how many people
would get hurt if the diagnostic threshold was lowered, how easy it would be
for a harried doctor to render the diagnosis and write a prescription with the
pen supplied by the drug company rep who had just taken her to lunch. Real-life
psychiatric diagnosis could not take place in a bell jar filled with experts
and their pet theories. There would always be unintended consequences. That’s
what Frances said he was trying to say to the DSM-5 leaders. “I just wanted them to learn4
from my mistakes.”
• • •
Even if definitions of mental
disorder weren’t bullshit, they wouldn’t solve the validity problem, at least
not by themselves. To declare a boundary between illness and health is not to
guarantee that any particular category of illness is real. In fact, definitions
could worsen the problem. “One of the
reasons5 that diagnostic classification has
fallen into disrepute,” Eli Robins and Samuel Guze wrote in 1970, “is that
diagnostic schemes have been largely based upon a priori principles
rather than upon systematic studies.”
Robins and Guze were leaders of the team
at Washington University that developed the descriptive approach that Spitzer
adopted for DSM-III. They recognized that the history of science, and
especially of medicine, was littered with examples of prejudice-blinded
researchers following their often unacknowledged traditions and principles down
dead-end alleys. These beliefs aren’t always as dunderheaded as the ones that
shaped Samuel Cartwright’s understanding of a slave’s thirst for freedom or
Freud’s notions about same-sex attraction. In the nineteenth century, for
instance, doctors believed that illnesses should be classified by their signs
and symptoms—a conviction that had prevailed since Hippocrates had given birth
to Western medicine, and which was not unreasonable, given that doctors had
little else to go on. So there was really no reason to doubt that patients with
genital sores were suffering from a disease different from what patients with a
skin rash had, and patients with general paresis, a form of dementia, had yet
another illness. There wasn’t even a reason to think that this scheme was based
on any a priori principle, that it was anything other
than a faithful account of how nature itself sorted diseases.
That all changed when some doctors,
notably Louis Pasteur and Robert Koch, began to insist that there was more to
disease than met the unaided eye. Beneath the appearances, the pustules and the
fevers and the complaints, was a microbial world populated by the real sources
of illness. And if the detectable presence of viruses and bacteria was not
convincing enough, the successes of pasteurization and anthrax inoculations
soon had doctors abandoning those first principles and peering into microscopes
to find the germs that caused diseases. Among the first organisms they spotted
was a spirochete, a spiral-shaped germ they named Treponema pallidum, which was present in patients with
sores, rashes, and dementia alike. They
concluded that T. pallidum6
was the natural formation that united those scattered particulars, which they
now recognized as different stage of syphilis. By century’s end, doctors were asking
questions about bacteria and viruses in addition to signs and symptoms, and
seeking cures in drugs that targeted those microbes rather than remedies
tailored to those outward appearances. Unfettered by archaic beliefs, they were
free to find the truth about what ailed us.
But a century after the advent of the germ
theory, as Robins and Guze knew too well, psychiatrists had yet to discover a
“schizococcus” bacterium or a “depressenza” virus or
anything else that would reduce the profession’s dependence on a priori
principles, and the disasters of the late 1960s and early 1970s were the
result. So the two men proposed a solution that they thought could keep
descriptive psychiatry safe from belief, at least until those bugs could be
found: a five-step process toward validity7
that, so they said, required no assumptions, that purely through the accretion
of evidence would converge to confirm (or disconfirm) that an alleged disease
really existed.
Start with clinical description, Robins
and Guze said, with a careful account of how patients present themselves, and
establish the criteria that link similar patients. Add laboratory
studies—including psychological tests—that will confirm (or not) that those
people belong together. Develop exclusion criteria so that a patient who is,
say, depressed but also has hallucinations and delusions gets grouped with the
schizophrenics rather than the depressives. Do follow-up studies to make sure
that the people you’ve grouped together have similar outcomes, as you would
expect if they were suffering from the same disease. And study the patients’
families to see if their members share symptoms, which would indicate that
there is some genetic link among the patients. By working all of these angles,
they argued, doctors would eventually accumulate enough evidence to say which
mental disorders were valid and which were only figments of an enthusiastic
doctor’s imagination.
But nearly forty years after Robins and
Guze proposed these validators—four decades in which criteria for inclusion and
exclusion were written and rewritten, tests conducted, families studied, and
patients followed—Darrel Regier told the Psychiatric News
that “validity tests . . . have not lived up8
to the expectations of Robins and Guze.” Even after Virginia Commonwealth
University behavioral geneticist Kenneth
Kendler added another validator9—differential
response to treatment, on the questionable grounds that a response to an
antidepressant, for example, confirmed that the patient had MDD in the first
place—the patterns that had emerged were weak and confusing. Indeed, by 2010
Kendler himself was still complaining that “the
[diagnostic] categories10 in use have been heavily
influenced by expert opinion, which . . . has been heavily influenced by a priori factors.”
Psychiatrists had evidently been fooled
again. The new a priori—Spitzer’s principle that mental disorders could be
classified by their criteria—has led them “to
consider our major diagnostic categories11 to be obvious
and even ‘natural,’” Kendler wrote, when, in fact, they were “fuzzy constructs
that shift when viewed in different ways.” These benighted psychiatrists had
fallen for their own ruse. They had forgotten that the DSM was fashioned by
experts, which meant that the diagnostic categories tended to reflect the a
priori principles of those experts—which, of course, the rank and file largely
shared. “We cannot develop a progressive scientifically based nosology shaped
by a single expert-driven conception of psychiatric illness, no matter how wise
its advocate,” Kendler wrote. Evidently, it is one thing for the public to
believe the experts, and quite another, at least in the view of one key opinion
leader, for the experts to believe themselves.
But Kendler wasn’t ready to get rid of the
experts and replace them with, say, a WikiDSM. Nor was he joining with the “critics of psychiatric diagnoses12,”
who, so he wrote, insisted that “there is no truth out there” and who would
simply give up on the DSM. Indeed, he became a member of a DSM-5 work group and
eventually the head of a committee reviewing its scientific soundness. But like
Frances, he thought revisers took on a “heavy and conservative burden.” They
had to avoid the kind of bruising battles in which “different constituencies in
psychiatry . . . vie with each other for influence and control,” and, upon
seizing power, “reshape the nosologic system in their own a
priori image.” The result, he feared, would be “wide fluctuations
between different systems with divergent theoretical perspectives and no net
progress.”
Kendler didn’t point out, because he
didn’t need to since his intended audience knew it in their bones, that DSM-III
was about as wide as a fluctuation can get. Bob Spitzer seized power, wrenched
psychiatry away from its Freudian principles, and reshaped it in his own image.
He might have gotten away with imposing this profession-saving paradigm shift
by sheer force of will, but it was a desperate measure taken in desperate
times, and not one you would want to repeat—especially if you want your
revisions to lead to a closer approximation of the reality of mental illness
and your constituency to have more faith in you than they do in other
institutions known more for their thrashings over divergent theoretical
perspectives than their net progress, like the United States Congress.
That goal is possible, Kendler wrote, but
only if changes are made slowly and carefully. In fact, if you are careful
enough, a good outcome is nearly guaranteed, thanks to the process of epistemic iteration, a concept Kendler borrowed from
mathematics, where it is defined as:
A historic and scientific process13 in which
successive stages of knowledge . . . build in a sequential manner upon each
other. . . . When correctly applied, the process of epistemic iteration should
lead through successive stages of scientific research toward a better and
better approximation of reality in a “spiral of improvement.”
It’s easy to see the appeal of this
promise. Kendler himself is the researcher who reported that when Walter
Cassidy, the psychiatrist who first proposed diagnostic criteria for
depression, was asked why he set the threshold at six out of ten symptoms, he
responded, “It sounded about right14.”
If you know that your origins are murky and your tools blunt, and yet you want
to claim that you are nonetheless heading toward clarity, then it behooves you
to put your money on a “wonderful property
of iteration15” and its “capacity to get to the
real solution regardless of the starting point.”
And if you know that your nosology has
gyrated wildly through the years, that it has been buffeted by history, its a
priori principles brought to light and debunked and hidden away again, if you
know that the doubt thus kindled will become your enemies’ weapon, if you know
that you and your allies must be able to “assure
ourselves16 that each revision of our manuals
contains improvements on its predecessor,” then what better talisman to carry
into battle than epistemic iteration, with its nearly magical power to ensure
that even as you are making your mistakes, truth is all along accumulating, that
those fluctuations are really only what Kendler calls “wobbly iterations17,”
that every day in every way your map of our suffering is getting better and
better, and that sooner or later, the experts, well versed in expertise, will
produce a DSM that, as Kendler puts it, “asymptotes
to a stable and accurate18 parameter estimate”?
But psychiatry is not mathematics. The way
we suffer, unlike the way numbers behave, changes with time and circumstance,
and experts’ opinions of what ails us change the way we think of ourselves and
our travails. Kendler insists that mental illnesses must exist in nature.
Rewind the tape of history to the dawn of civilization, he says—about ten
thousand years ago, when our biological apparatus would have taken shape but
history had yet to make us into who we are—and start again. Record the result,
and do this a thousand times. While it is likely that in each iteration you
will see psychiatrists arriving at different criteria by which they know our
mental illnesses, you will also see the illnesses themselves, just as you are
sure to see diabetes and strokes and broken bones.
Of course, just because Kendler says
that’s what will happen, it’s not necessarily what would happen. Indeed, the
thought experiment falters when you consider that Kendler borrowed the scenario
from paleontologist Stephen Jay Gould19.
In the original version, Gould rewound the tape to the beginning of earth’s
history to point out that given all the accidents, the asteroid crashes and ice
ages and tectonic shifts, it was very unlikely that human life as we know it
would emerge in any of those do-overs. His rhetorical point was that it was
folly to assume that the long arc of evolution bends toward anything in
particular, that only Whiggishness or presentism or some kind of Voltairian
optimism—not to mention a huge dose of species-level narcissism—would allow a
person to claim that we are the inevitable culmination of creation, let alone
that our endeavors lead inherently toward progress.
“We
follow the tape forward20 until modern science and medicine
develop,” Kendler writes, but this is the whole lesson of Gould’s experiment:
We cannot know if anything like modern science and medicine will develop. We
cannot simply assume that people will come to identify their subjective
troubles as mental, much less place them in doctors’ hands. Gould figured that
each new spool would be entirely different, not simply an instant replay.
If Kendler has assumed his conclusions
here, it is because he has to assume that mental illness exists in the same way
as diabetes and strokes, and that the only alternative is to believe “there is
no truth out there.” He has to believe these things because he is a
psychiatrist, and only a notion of historical inevitability can justify the
enormous hubris, the inescapable a priori principle of psychiatry: that our psychological
suffering is medical—which, as our reel has unspooled,
means located in bodily processes gone awry. Go to the tape, Kendler seems to
be saying, and you will find that doctors’ failures so far, including the
faulty DSM that urgently needed replacing, are just detours on the road to
Parnassus and not a disastrous wrong turn.
Psychiatry is not inevitable. It’s not
baseball, either. Those wobbly iterations aren’t just bad calls that frustrate
a batter and raise a crowd’s ineffectual, if vocal, ire. They are diagnoses
that change people’s lives, that render homosexuals unfit for employment, that
subject children to untested and powerful drugs, that encourage patients to
think of their troubles as chemical imbalances rather than meaningful signs of
something gone wrong in their lives. If you go to see a psychiatrist, you
probably don’t enter the office as if you were going into Fenway Park. You
don’t think you are about to take part in a game whose rules are arbitrary if
venerable and negotiable. You don’t expect the number of symptoms that add up
to depression to change like the strike zone has or diagnoses to enter the DSM
like the designated hitter was added to the rulebook. If you’re anything like
me, as much as you might like baseball, you expect more from your doctors than
that.
You might also think there is a difference
between the current DSM and the current Official Rules of
Major League Baseball—and not just that one costs $95.89 on Amazon,
while the other can be downloaded for free and, in its 2011 edition anyway, has
an excellent picture of Curtis Granderson crossing home plate on its cover. You
might well believe that one compiles the laws of nature and the other the rules
of the game, and if you do, it is in part because we all want to believe that
someone somewhere can understand and help us when we suffer. But it is also
because psychiatrists—with their scientific-looking DSM, with their assurances
about epistemic iteration, with their talk of chemical imbalances and their
medications to treat them—have spent the better part of the past four decades
telling you, and acting like, it is so.
• • •
Darrel Regier’s August 2009
interview with the Psychiatric News was part of a
concerted effort to counter Frances’s warnings that the DSM-5 was headed for
disaster. “The ‘disastrous result21’
in most clinicians’ and researchers’ minds would be for DSM to continue on the
same path it has been on for 30 years,” he told the News.
That’s why his task force was proposing “significant revisions,” and why the
new manual, he wrote in an American Journal of Psychiatry
article, would “attempt to address22
the consequences of continuing to use the original . . . hierarchical structure
of ‘pure’ diagnostic categories.” Frances and Spitzer’s DSM was simply too bad
to be left alone.
Regier may have been making a wholesale
critique, but he was quick to say that “a wholesale revision was not in the
cards.” What Regier had in mind was nothing as radical as casting the
categories to the wind. Instead, he said, diagnostic labels and criteria would
be joined by dimensional measures. The problem with
the categorical approach was that it forced clinicians into binary decisions.
Did the patient have OCD or MDD, ADHD or BDNOS? Too often the result was more
than one diagnosis—the comorbidity problem—or a diagnosis that didn’t really
capture the clinical picture. And then there were the “patients with clinically
significant distress and impairment,” whose symptoms spanned many diagnoses
without reaching a diagnostic threshold in any one. People could be a little
depressed, a little anxious, a little obsessive-compulsive, but still in a lot
of distress. Wouldn’t it make sense to be able to identify, measure, and study
these cross-cutting symptoms as dimensions of
pathology without necessarily attributing them to a particular category?
“The single most important precondition
for moving forward to improve the clinical and scientific utility of DSM-V will
be the incorporation of simple dimensional measures,” Regier wrote. Their
“prominent use” would be “one, if not the major, difference between DSM-IV and
DSM-V.” The revision would focus on measuring the severity of symptoms, both
within and across diagnoses. This alone would not entirely spring psychiatry
from its epistemic prison, but, especially once researchers could “establish better syndrome boundaries23”
and “identify continuous measures of the constituent symptoms,” he told me in
an e-mail, they would be able to determine the “statistically valid cutpoints
between normal and pathological.” Getting to this goal, of course, would
require categories based on “a full understanding of the underlying pathophysiology
of mental disorders.” But even if this was a long way off, it was important to
take the first step now. “Delaying the introduction of dimensional measures in
this version of DSM will simply retard both clinical and research progress,” he
wrote.
But it wasn’t as if DSM-IV lacked
dimensional measures. Some diagnoses, such
as depression24, had severity specifiers, in which
clinicians rated a patient’s disorder from zero to five and reported this as
the last digit of the diagnosis code. And the DSM-IV also provided a Global Assessment of Functioning25
scale, which clinicians were supposed to use to indicate a patient’s
functioning on a scale of zero to one hundred. But, as we clinicians soon found
out, when we rated a patient’s functioning too high or his severity too low,
insurance companies used these numbers as their own kind of statistical
cutpoint—to cut off benefits. So we quickly adapted—inflating the ratings or
ignoring them altogether, not telling unless we were asked.
Regier needed a more comprehensive and
scientific approach to dimensional assessment than what the DSM-IV offered, but
this presented a problem. Very few severity tests for DSM-IV diagnoses had been
developed and validated. Nor did he have a huge literature to draw on for
measuring cross-cutting symptoms. The National
Institutes of Health had created PROMIS26 (Patient
Reported Outcomes Measurement Information System) to gather information on how
patients thought they were faring, but while this offered a way to determine,
say, how anxious a person was or how well he was sleeping, Regier could not say
how this kind of data would be integrated into the diagnostic system. To get
dimensional measures in place for the DSM-5 required a “bottoms-up27 [sic] approach for instrument development,” he wrote, but the
group that had been assigned to dive into that task started its work only in
January 2009. Field trials, in which those tests would presumably be studied,
were slated to begin in summer 2009, so they had had just a few months to put
together their tests. To critics, this seemed like an indication of disarray. “If they really want to do dimensional
assessment28,” Michael First told me, “they
should wait the five or ten years it would take for the scales to be ready.”
But Regier did not think it was necessary
to have all this nailed down before the book was published. “We don’t expect the DSM-529
to be perfect or etched in stone for the ages,” he told me in an e-mail. This
expectation, after all, was the central trouble with the previous DSMs;
designed to look scientific, they had proven too easy to reify. And even if the
DSM-5 was not going to be anchored in the bedrock of neurobiology, even if it
could not fulfill the promise of paradigm change with which it had been born,
still it could achieve one thing: the ratcheting back of expectations for the
revision, and for psychiatric nosology itself. Diagnostic
criteria “are intended30 to be scientific hypotheses,
rather than inerrant Biblical scripture,” he wrote. And the DSM was not
scripture. It was a “living document.”
It was a clever rhetorical move. Regier
had turned the reification of the DSM into just another of those “epistemic
iterations” that Kendler wrote about, a wobbly step on the way to the truth.
The categorical approach had served its purpose, and now it was time to back
away from it, and from the misguided fundamentalists who took the diagnoses
literally. It was time to pirouette on the back of those new dimensional
measures into the “spiral of improvement.”
Chapter 9
Throughout
the summer and fall of 2009, Allen Frances kept up his attack. He became a
regular contributor to the Psychiatric Times,
blogging, sometimes in every issue, about what he thought the APA was doing
wrong. By the time he posted a blog titled “Advice
to DSM V1,” the APA was probably not in the
mood to take it.
“There is no magic moment when it becomes
clear that the world needs a new edition of the DSM,” he reminded his
successors. A revision of the ICD scheduled for fall 2012 had reportedly been
delayed—and, as he also pointed out, because the codes used by the DSM-5 came
from the ICD, a new DSM that preceded a new ICD would soon have outdated codes.
Wouldn’t it be better to coordinate the release of the DSM and the ICD, and in
the bargain give the revision the time it deserved?
Getting out from under deadline pressure
was the key to saving the DSM-5, Frances thought, and this now became his mission.
Unintended consequences were the unknown unknowns of the APA’s revision
campaign, and haste only increased their likelihood and severity. Even a good
diagnostic change could make unexpected trouble. For instance, he wrote, the
DSM-IV had fashioned new criteria for ADHD. They were clearer and easier to
remember, and in the field trials the new
criteria identified 15 percent more2 kids with ADHD
than the old criteria had—an acceptable result, Frances thought at the time.
But once the criteria went into wide use, the
actual increase was 28 percent3—an outcome he
attributed in part to the ease with which doctors, as well as parents and
teachers, could apply the simplified criteria.
Of greatest concern to Frances, however,
was the task force’s failure to take “the most important step in the
development of any DSM”: to release a complete first draft. Without one,
experts outside the work groups could not weigh in on either the proposed
revisions or the procedures by which they would be tested, which meant that the
field trials might use a faulty methodology to investigate faulty diagnoses
comprising poorly written criteria—a compounding of errors that would, he was sure,
turn out to be the “fatal flaw” of DSM-5.
This haste, combined with tunnel vision,
was particularly distressing, he wrote, because of Kupfer and Regier’s
ambition. Their vow to make a “bottoms-up” revision meant that “everything was on the table4.”
The experts on the work groups would have free rein to make changes without
much constraint from their commanders. The task force, he concluded, had put
change over stability, innovation over tradition, and threatened to turn the
process into a runaway train that would pull psychiatry “over the cliff5.” To postpone
publication was therefore the “obviously right thing,” as obvious as putting on
the brakes to slow a speeding car.
Frances wound up his lesson with a
confession of his own failings. “It is surprisingly difficult to write clean,
foolproof criteria items. I know this from frustrating personal experience.
Despite many years of effort and practice, I never mastered this highly
technical writing skill.” (He couldn’t resist adding that “no one working on
DSM-V has had any extensive experience in writing diagnostic criteria”—a
not-so-veiled reference to the expunging of Michael First.) And the DSM-IV’s
text, as opposed to the criteria, the sections within each diagnosis that
described such matters as the familial patterns, biological factors, and
epidemiology of the disorder, was “tired, old . . . in need of exhaustive
revision . . . and fails to convey any of the vividness of actual clinical
practice,” and thus “should be up for grabs.” Anyone who said Frances was
merely trying to protect his own ego, in other words, had it wrong. He just
wanted his successors to change what could be changed and otherwise leave well
enough alone.
Frances never misses an opportunity to
tell you how dumb or dull or insignificant he and his DSM are. He might mean
it. He does seem to subscribe to the conservative notion, made most famous by
Edmund Burke, that modesty, born of education and refinement, is the best check
on power, at least the kind of power he once wielded. But there is also
strategy to his self-effacement. “I take
more blame for DSM-IV6 than we actually deserved,” he told
me once. “I purposely emphasized the mistakes that we made. But I saw it as a
rhetoric that would help them to feel more comfortable hearing, ‘Look. I
screwed up and I don’t want you guys to have the same problems,’ rather than
‘DSM-IV was such a great document but yours produces
crap.’ I’m not criticizing you because I think you are a jerk and I’m smart,
but I’m criticizing you because I’ve been through it and this is my mea culpa.”
Not that Frances thinks that DSM-IV was a great document. It was only what he wanted it to be—a
selective polishing of Spitzer’s work, the best (or the least bad) that could
be done with the tools at his disposal, successful because it was dull and
unambitious. But Regier and Kupfer, with their everything-on-the-table
ambition, were going to produce crap. He may not have thought they were jerks.
But when he semisweetened his advice with faint praise—“The DSM-V task force
and work group members are dedicated people doing their best under very
difficult circumstances”—and then followed it up with condescension—“They
should be given sufficient time to ensure that DSM-V will be a worthwhile
contribution”—it was pretty clear that this was getting personal and that he
was not going to stop being one of those difficult circumstances.
• • •
After defending themselves in
the leading journal and both industry newsletters—and in mainstream outlets
such as The Wall Street Journal, to which Kupfer
confessed that “some of us have gotten7
. . . sick enough about playing defensive ball and being taken out of
context”—the DSM leaders went silent. So did APA president Alan Schatzberg, but
only after he reassured members that they were the real victims.
“The
development process has been so public8,” he told the Psychiatric News, “that anyone can kvetch about one point or
another in a blog.” Schatzberg did welcome “scholars and clinicians” to engage
in “collaborative and collegial interchange” with DSM leaders, but suggested
that critics should quit their kvetching, or at least take heed of the
unintended consequences of their own behavior. “The news media thrive on
controversy,” he warned, “and some of these discussions have . . . provided
ammunition for those who are anti-psychiatry as a science and opposed to
treatment.”
But while the APA was hunkering down in
public, in private it was scrambling. In the spring of 2009, before Frances
began his onslaught, two members of the childhood disorders work group had
resigned. One refused to talk publicly, citing fears that the APA would seek
retribution. But the second, Duke University professor Jane Costello, made her
resignation letter public—“I’m too small a
fish9 for them to bother with,” she told
me—and it was getting widely distributed. As much as she enjoyed “working with
this extraordinary group of people,” she wrote,
I cannot in good conscience10 continue. I am
increasingly uncomfortable with the whole underlying principle of rewriting the
entire psychiatric taxonomy at one time. I am not aware of any other branch of
medicine that does anything like this. There seems to be no good scientific
justification for doing this, and certainly none for doing it in 2012.
The science simply wasn’t available for
fulfilling the APA’s ambitions for DSM-5, Costello wrote. Indeed, in a line she
could have lifted from Harry Frankfurt, she lamented that the more researchers
tried, the more they realized that “the gap between what we need to know in
order to make revisions and what we do know has grown wider and wider, while
the time to fill these gaps is shrinking rapidly.” And at least one attempt to
fill in those gaps—a research project proposed by Costello and a colleague—had,
she said, been rebuffed by Kupfer on the grounds that he needed results sooner
than they could produce them. Even worse, the APA could have had their results
sooner, but they had been unwilling to pay for the research, leaving her no
choice but to turn to the NIMH, whose funding wheels turn slowly—too slowly, it
seemed, for the impatient DSM revisers.
All of this she perhaps could have
tolerated, but then came the “tipping point”: the announcement by Kupfer and
Regier that dimensional assessment would be the major difference between DSM-IV
and DSM-5.
Setting aside the question
of who “decided,” on what grounds, anyone with any experience of instrument
development knows that what they proposed . . . is a huge task, and a very expensive
one. The possibility of doing a . . . careful and responsible job given the
time and resources available is remote, while to do anything less is
irresponsible.
Costello was “shocked” at the
decision. After all, she pointed out, “a drug company that tried to bring a
product to market on the basis of inadequately funded research would rightly be
censured.”
Costello’s letter was addressed to the
head of her work group, but the response
came from Darrel Regier11. He spent two of his six
paragraphs reciting the failures of the DSM-IV and a third describing the
necessity of dimensional measures to remedy them. Costello probably knew all
this, but the DSM-IV’s inadequacies had become part of an origin story that Regier
was already using whenever the revision was criticized. It was as if Costello
had been defending the DSM-IV and questioning the need for dimensional
measures, rather than acknowledging its limitations while wondering whether or
not the revision could possibly meet its goals.
Finally, more than halfway through his
letter, Regier began to address her concerns. “There was certainly some
miscommunication” regarding proposals such as hers. He didn’t say what had been
miscommunicated or by whom, but he did point out that at the time she applied
for the research grant, the APA did not yet know what kind of data it would
need or how it would be analyzed. Since then, he reassured her, the
requirements had become clear. And while the APA was indeed not funding projects
that cost more than $50,000—a pittance—still there was plenty of data out
there. “Billions of dollars” (much of it, Regier didn’t add, government money)
had been spent in the forty years since the current paradigm had been
established. The fruits of this research were available in journals, and some
work group members had even made their work available “as a professional
courtesy.” This data would be the basis for the revision. The APA may have been
strapped, but it was also resourceful. And, he reminded her, it was “the only
entity with the standing, capacity, and willingness” to undertake a
comprehensive revision.
As to the readiness of the dimensional
measures, Costello need not worry. “A good number of us involved with this
process,” Regier wrote, “have extensive experience in supporting the
development of the previously mentioned instruments and would not diminish the
standards used.” Haste will not make waste, he seemed to be saying, because the
matter is safely in the hands of the experts—although, he admitted, it was
possible that not all the tests would be ready when the DSM that required their
use came out. Nor did the APA have, as some had charged, a mercenary intent in
developing a host of new tests. “Our intent is to make all such instruments
freely available for clinical and research use,” Regier wrote, “and to
copyright them to insure their integrity.” So even if the dimensional measures
weren’t fully developed in time for publication, he promised that researchers
would be able to refine them afterward. He didn’t explain how clinicians and
researchers would make diagnoses in the meantime.
Urgency justified haste; the desperation
of psychiatry to meet the scientific demands of the day required desperate, or
at least incompletely developed, measures. Regier was not refuting Costello at
all. Instead, he was agreeing that the dimensional measures were nowhere near
ready while suggesting that this was not the problem she thought it was. A
living document is a messy thing, a lesser evil than a faulty document
inscribed in stone. And anyway, wasn’t it Allen Frances who once said that
psychiatric diagnosis is a sloppy business?
• • •
The APA didn’t make Regier’s
response to Costello public at first. “Since
we considered12 this a private matter, we did not
broadcast this response as her letter was broadcast by some of our critics,”
Regier explained when he provided it to me. But in private, the kvetching—and
the fact that it was coming from people like Costello, Spitzer, and ultimately
Frances, rather than, say, Tom Cruise—was causing unrest at headquarters. The
APA’s board of trustees was growing concerned over the brewing feud. “When there is smoke13,”
trustee (and former APA president) Carolyn Robinowitz told me, “you have to
make sure that you take a really in-depth look.”
In the summer of 2009, the board appointed
Robinowitz to head a DSM oversight committee. The new committee didn’t exactly
find a fire, but they did find smoldering trouble that was clearly not the work
of the APA’s enemies. “The board was hearing from Dr. Regier and Dr. Kupfer
that things were going pretty much on schedule,” she recalled. But then the
committee talked to the work group members and discovered that “there was a
certain amount of conflict,” Robinowitz told me. She was, I thought, straining
to be diplomatic.
“Dr. Kupfer wanted to get a flow of ideas
and issues,” she continued, but the rancor and disorganization within the
groups indicated that this method was backfiring. Not that anyone should have
expected anything but infighting “when you have a bunch of outstanding
researchers strong in their beliefs and strong in their science,” but the
result was that even the work group chairs thought “their stuff wasn’t quite
ready for prime time.” Robinowitz’s panel concluded that “things weren’t moving
as well as they might be. The process allowed for a lot of input, but it hadn’t
begun to coalesce as much as it should have by that time.”
The oversight committee wasn’t only
concerned with how far behind schedule the effort had already fallen, now that
summer had passed and the promised field trials had not materialized. “We were
also looking at the timetable they proposed and everything was tight,”
Robinowitz said. So the committee recommended that the publication be delayed
one year, to May 2013. And, she allowed in fall 2010, the committee might
recommend further postponements, depending on what happened in the field trials
that Regier insisted would be the proving grounds for the changes. “It’s not a
contract that we have to execute or there will never be another DSM. I don’t
think anyone is going to say we’ve got to go forward if we get crappy results.”
In early December, Frances told his
growing Psychiatric Times following that his
“anonymous sources” in the organization were telling him to expect an important
announcement soon. Sure enough, a week later the
APA issued a press release14. The “anticipated” publication
date was now May 2013. Schatzberg explained that “extending the timeline will
allow more time for public review, field trials and revisions. The APA is
committed,” he went on, “to developing a manual that is based on the best science
available and useful to clinicians and researchers.”
The press release didn’t acknowledge that
the APA had taken precisely the course that Frances had recommended. And when I
put the question to Regier, he claimed that the delay was occasioned only by the
“long vetting process15
and startup time of the work groups,” which in turn resulted from the APA’s
requirement that revisers divest themselves of drug company money. Once again,
the APA was claiming to be the victim—not of Frances, but of its own goodness.
Regier also insisted that Frances’s complaints had “added no content to the
discussion,” and indeed had “only served to heighten interest” in the revision.
Frances, in other words, was helping the APA.
Even so, Frances was flirting with danger.
“His major critique,” Regier went on, was that “nothing has changed in the
scientific world since his revision and hence no substantive revision is
possible.” Not only that, he was also asserting “that his judgment on the
pragmatic consequences of revisions should take precedence over any of the
experts in a given diagnostic field.” He was, in other words, trumping up his
personal grievance into a broadside against the institution he once served and
in the bargain calling into question the credibility of the APA. The diagnosis
was clear: Allen Frances, once America’s top psychiatrist, was letting his ego
take him on a kamikaze mission directed at his own colleagues. Blinded by
pride, he had become his own kind of antipsychiatrist and, even worse, a
turncoat.
• • •
In January 2010, Frances took
his show on the road. After a test run at Duke, he went to Columbia
University’s medical school to present grand rounds—a medical school tradition
in which an eminent doctor describes a case to students. Frances’s case was the
ailing DSM. “I’m going to be quite critical16,”
he said at the outset of his forty-five-minute talk, but first he wanted to
address his own “possible biases”—meaning, it turned out, the charges that the
DSM-5 defenders had leveled at him. He was not inherently conservative or
opposed to change, he assured the audience, which included numerous DSM-5 work
group members (along with Michael First); his caution over the DSM revision was
the exception. He wasn’t “trying to save my baby,” he told them. “The DSM-IV is
not something I feel particularly proud of, and I don’t think it was much of a
contribution to the world,” and as for the $10,000 in royalties that the APA had
said was his real motive for agitating for a delay—“Well, it’s conceivable that
that’s why I’m giving this talk,” he said, and shared a laugh with his fellow
high earners over that paltry sum.
The talk was a concentrated version of the
litany he’d been developing over six months of blogging, now for Psychology Today in addition to the Psychiatric
Times. But it was one thing to thumb out a blog on his BlackBerry (or to
give a talk on his own home turf) and another to tell an audience such as this
one that the DSM-5 was very likely to be “crummy” and a “mess,” that the big
question was whether or not it would also be dangerous, and that the revisers
were so blind to their own faults that only public pressure could avert that
disaster.
After the talk, and before he started the
Q&A session, moderator Jeffrey Lieberman, the head of Columbia’s department
of psychiatry and a member of Robinowitz’s oversight committee, tried to
relieve the tension. “Allen,” he said, “I only wish you hadn’t held back, and
told us what you really thought.”
Frances reached over and put his big hand
on Lieberman’s white-coated shoulder. “I did hold back,” he said.
David Shaffer, a member of the childhood
disorders work group, was the first audience member to speak. He certainly
didn’t hold back.
“Congratulations, Allen,” he said. “It was
a daring exercise to list so many strong complaints without having seen what’s
about to be posted.” (The APA had not yet put the promised draft of the DSM on
its website.) Even worse, according to Shaffer, Frances had compounded his
ignorance by setting up a straw man. “You represented a set of overambitious
and vain and silly goals that actually were never stated as such,” he said.
As Frances prepared to respond, Shaffer
reclaimed the microphone. “One personal thing,” he said. He had worked on both
DSM-III and DSM-IV, and agreed with Frances that the new revision’s “style of
management has been completely different.” But far from flirting with disaster,
the “bottom-up process [had] led to some of the most stimulating debate as I
can remember in my career.” It was a double rebuke to Frances: he had not only
jumped the gun with his criticisms; he had also been wrong to conduct his
revision in an autocratic manner, one that had evidently bored Shaffer. It was
as if the DSM-IV’s troubles were the result of Frances’s conservatism. Having
been freed from these restraints, it seemed, the DSM-5’s experts couldn’t help
but come up with a better book, or at least have a more stimulating time in the
process.
• • •
Frances didn’t respond
directly to Shaffer’s complaints, except to agree that “the proof will be in
the pudding.” And a few weeks later, on February 10, the pudding was served. The APA posted a full draft17
of the proposed revisions on its website. The draft maintained the DSM-IV’s
structure, organizing mental disorders into sixteen chapters (“Mood Disorders,”
“Anxiety Disorders,” “Schizophrenia and Other Psychotic Disorders,” etc.), but
it also featured changes to virtually every part of the book, from the
definition of mental disorders at the beginning to the “Listing of Other
Conditions” at the end. Doctors would be able to diagnose and get paid to treat
Psychosis Risk Syndrome and other disorders, such as Minor Neurocognitive
Disorder, that were more harbingers of future trouble than present illnesses.
Kids labeled bipolar by the Biederman protocol would now have Temper
Dysregulation Disorder, and kids diagnosed with Asperger’s Disorder would
suddenly come down with a case of Autistic Spectrum Disorder, if they were
still sick at all. Pathological gambling would no longer be an Impulse Control
Disorder, but instead would become a behavioral addiction, joining Alcohol Use
Disorder and Cannabis Use Disorder in the Substance-Related Disorders section,
which would be renamed “Addiction and Related Disorders.” Pathological gambling
would be the only behavioral addiction for now; Internet Addiction had not made
the cut, and Money Addiction apparently hadn’t been considered. But you would
no longer have to be addicted to or dependent on a drug to warrant a diagnosis;
any kind of troublesome use was enough. Troublesome sex could also be
diagnosed; people who experienced “six or more months of recurrent and intense
sexual fantasies, sexual urges, and sexual behavior,” in which they spent “a
great deal of time . . . planning for and engaging in sexual behavior,” would
have Hypersexual Disorder. If their attraction was to young adolescents, they
would be suffering from Pedohebephilia, and if they got off on forcing people
to have sex, they would qualify for Paraphilic Coercive Disorder. Adults would
get criteria for their own version of Attention Deficit/Hyperactivity Disorder,
and children would need fewer symptoms to qualify for ADHD. The recently
bereaved would lose their exemption from the depression diagnosis and would be
mentally ill after two weeks of grieving. Where there had once been ten
personality disorders, there would now be only five. People who went on Ben and
Jerry’s sprees would now have Binge Eating Disorder, and people who were
worried and sad but didn’t meet criteria for either Generalized Anxiety
Disorder or Major Depressive Disorder would now qualify for Mixed
Anxiety-Depression Disorder. Every patient would get rated for cross-cutting symptoms, and every diagnosis would come with a severity
rating, although it wasn’t exactly clear how this would be done because these
dimensional measures, as Regier had predicted, were still under construction.
Everything was indeed on the table.
The APA would allow the public, kvetchers
and scholars alike, to weigh in on the proposals for two months (although, as
its website cautioned, while “all input we receive will be reviewed . . . we
can not guarantee that your suggestions will be incorporated into any
revisions.” But it didn’t have to wait long to hear from some familiar voices
or work hard to figure out where they stood.
“Anything
you put in that book18, any little change you make, has
huge implications,” Michael First told The New York Times
on the day of the release. Those risk syndromes, for instance, carried their
own risk, at least the one about psychosis did: “that many unusual,
semi-deviant, creative kids could . . . carry this label for the rest of their
lives.”
And the very next day, Allen Frances
listed for Psychiatric Times readers “The 19 Worst Suggestions for DSM519.”
His four-thousand-word evisceration of the draft argued that with its lowered
thresholds for old diagnoses and its brand-new, untested diagnoses, the DSM-5
would be like honey to the drug company flies and like gold to lawyers.
Psychosis Risk Syndrome would be a “catastrophe,” Mixed Anxiety-Depression would
become an “epidemic,” Temper Dysregulation Disorder was a “nonstarter,”
Paraphilic Coercive Disorder would be a boon to prosecutors looking to commit
sex offenders indefinitely to mental hospitals and to defense lawyers seeking
to exculpate their rapist clients, behavioral addictions would provide “a ready
excuse for off-loading personal responsibility,” and Pedohebephilia would
“medicalize criminal behavior.” Dimensional assessments, cross-cutting and
diagnosis-specific, were “ad hoc, unworkably complex, vague, untested, and
premature,” not to mention “bewilderingly inconsistent . . . extremely
complicated and totally impractical.” The proposals confirmed what Frances had
feared: that “the DSM5 has been and remains in serious trouble.”
“How can such smart and scrupulous people
make so many bad suggestions?” Frances wondered toward the end of his diatribe.
His answer was that because experts, no matter how well intentioned, would
always expand their reach, it was up to their leaders to recognize and resist this
“diagnostic imperialism,” and that this seemed the last thing that the “DSM5
leadership,” defensive and secretive, and still committed to their bottom-up
approach, were likely to do. The leaders—he pointedly did not mention Kupfer
and Regier by name—had failed to recognize this duty, so they no longer
deserved the benefit of the doubt.
Chapter 10
Allen
Frances had spoken his piece but no one on the inside had listened, so he
redoubled his attack, turning to the rank-and-file psychiatrists who, he assumed,
were the people reading his blogs. “The rest,” Frances told them, “is up to
you.” In the dozen missives he fired off to the Psychiatric
Times between mid-February and the end of May—with acerbic titles like
“Biting Off More Than It Can Chew,” “Not Ready for Prime Time,” and
“Psychiatric Diagnosis Gone Wild”—he exhorted his readers to “Just Say No,” as
he put it in his blog about the sexual disorders proposals. He reminded them of
the public commentary period. In April he sent another
letter to the trustees1 that added some new charges—that
the field trials (whose design had just been posted) were fundamentally flawed,
that the project still lacked oversight, that despite the one-year delay, the
revision was hopelessly behind schedule—and urged the trustees to use their
“power and responsibility” lest “things drift further over the cliff.” Warning
that “this might be a last chance tipping point to save DSM-5,” he made the
letter public and begged psychiatrists to “influence your leaders to take the
decisive actions to solve them.”
Frances insists he is ill suited, by
temperament and experience, to participate in a rebellion, let alone to lead
one. “I was of age in the ’60s2
and never protested or went to D.C. to hear Martin Luther King. I was at Jones
Beach having a great time,” he once told me. He was responding to an e-mail in
which I suggested that there was something poignant and quixotic about his
battle with the APA. “I am not a quester for truth or a righter of wrongs or a
follower of impossible dreams,” he wrote. “I am Panza.” He implored me to get
this right. “[I] would prefer to be portrayed accurately as the lowly brute I
am than to be ennobled into some version of David and Goliath.”
“I am not battling the DSM-5 leadership in
some romantic crusade,” he went on. “There was no one else in a position to
take on DSM-5 so I was stuck . . . by an unavoidable duty. I started trying to
warn them and now I am trying to shame them. Nothing noble or quixotic or
poignant.”
On the other hand, Allen Frances was once
the most powerful psychiatrist in America. You don’t need a slingshot to smack
your fellow Goliaths in the forehead, and you don’t get to be one of them without
putting some skin in the game and figuring out how to be forceful. For Frances,
or so he says, this came down to one simple tactic. “I never yell3,” he insisted. “I
tease.”
He recalled a kerfuffle in the late days
of the DSM-IV campaign over Self-Defeating Personality Disorder (SDPD)—which,
in what he calls a “nice irony4,”
was the remnant of his own “dumb idea” for Masochistic Personality Disorder.
SDPD had been placed in the Appendix of the DSM-III-R, where it presumably
awaited “further study,” but in the meantime, it had become a magnet for the
kind of controversy Frances disliked—not only among psychiatrists, but in the
rest of the world, where feminists worried that the diagnosis would lead to
laying the blame for domestic violence and sexual assault on the supposed
pathology of the victims.
Frances wanted to kick SDPD out of the DSM
entirely, but psychoanalytically minded psychiatrists opposed him—largely because,
with its insistence that people might be unconsciously motivated to behave
against their own best interests, the diagnosis was one of the last vestiges of
psychoanalysis in the DSM. They started a last-minute rearguard action. To help
quell it, the head of the APA, Melvin Sabshin, suggested that Frances and
Herbert Peyser, an advocate for the diagnosis, stage a series of debates at a
meeting of the APA Assembly, the representative body within the organization.
“This
was the stupidest idea in the world5,” Frances said.
“You don’t debate things like this.” Not only that, but “Herb was going against
the rules. He stubbornly made [SDPD] a political issue.” But Sabshin was the
boss and Frances found himself doing exactly what the rules he’d made with
Pincus had been designed to prevent: bloviating in front of a room full of
pontificators.
“Herb and I would debate for a half hour
for each of these groups,” he told me. “At the end, Herb and I would come out
and I’d give him a big kiss on the cheek and a pinch on both cheeks, and I
would say, ‘Herb, you’re absolutely brilliant, it’s almost impossible to debate
against you. If we were candidates, you’d kill me, because I don’t know what
I’m doing and you’re brilliant.’ And then I’d say, ‘But I’m sorry you’re not
going to win, because it’s just a stupid idea.’”
Bob Spitzer served as Peyser’s cornerman
in the debates. “After the third or fourth6,”
Peyser told me, “Spitzer says, ‘Herb, the best argument in favor of SDPD is if
we keep arguing with Al about it.’” Even if there was a group of people who met
the criteria for the diagnosis, who could be reliably identified, who were
distinct from other groups of troubled people, and who suffered impairment as a
result—even, that is, if the diagnosis qualified in all ways as a mental
disorder—“it was clear from the beginning,” Peyser told me, “Al was going to
win.”
And indeed he did, garnering 60 percent of
the assembly’s votes for his proposal to delete the disorder, without ever
yelling.
• • •
Teasing, perhaps more than
other kinds of joking, only barely conceals the hostility and aggression and
the wish to inflict shame that Freud once
said7 was the function of jokes. It is,
at least psychologically speaking, a lowly and brute tactic, and, compared with
launching a rock at a Goliath, cowardly. But it can work, so long as the
audience, or the butt of the joke, accepts the rules of engagement, as Jeffrey
Lieberman did when he laughed—a little uncomfortably, perhaps—with the rest of
the grand-rounds crowd when Frances laid his hand on his shoulder and joked
with him at Columbia. And Peyser remembers the debates as “delicious,” even if
his cheeks got pinched and he got trounced.
But at least one man doesn’t seem to get
Frances’s jokes: David Shaffer, the Columbia child psychiatrist who shrouded
his hostility toward Frances in gentility rather than humor when he
congratulated him for spouting off on proposals he hadn’t seen. Shaffer thinks
that Frances’s “orderly and democratic
process8” did tame Spitzer’s
rough-and-tumble—“I liken it to a tobacco auction,” he said—but the needling,
even nearly twenty years later, still rankled.
“The worst thing about Allen Frances was
that he would always find some reason to insult Bob,” Shaffer told me. “If Bob
said something, he would say, ‘Well, that’s a typical Spitzerism,’ or he would
find some other ad hominem thing to say. It was childish and embarrassing.”
“David
probably misinterpreted9 what passes as New York Jewish
humor for disrespect,” Frances said.
And, indeed, Shaffer said he never quite
understood the “New York kind of logic” that both Spitzer and Frances seemed to
favor. That’s not hard to believe when you lay eyes on him. He’s as different
as can be from those two swarthy, wisecracking New Yorkers—a pale wisp of a man
who talks with a soft British lilt and demurely turns his head to the side,
looking out his office window toward the Hudson River and the George Washington
Bridge when he’s reaching for his next words. It’s a little hard to imagine a
man so mild being married, as he was for fifteen years, to Vogue
editor Anna Wintour; he’s not even particularly well dressed. But he is
unabashedly pleased to have a different leadership style in place as he works
on DSM-5, and he’s pretty annoyed with Frances—not only for his Columbia talk
(“a real blot on his landscape”), but also for hammering away at Shaffer’s pet
proposal for the revision, Temper Dysregulation Disorder (TDD).
Shaffer thinks he was in part responsible
for Frances’s attacks. “The TDD was my fault,” he said.
He’s not talking about the new diagnosis.
He still believes that was a good idea, and the best way to solve an
embarrassing problem. “Biederman was a crook,” Shaffer told me. “He borrowed a
disease and applied it in a chaotic fashion. He came up with ridiculous data
that none of us believed. It brought child psychiatry into disrepute and was a
terrible burden on the families of the children who got that label.”
It would not be enough simply to put an
end to the childhood bipolar epidemic by, say, changing the DSM to restrict the
diagnosis by age or introducing chronic irritability as an exclusion
criterion—a condition whose presence would contraindicate the diagnosis.
“These kids are terribly ill,” Shaffer said, and if Biederman “hijacked the
diagnosis,” he did it in part to provide them a “diagnostic home.” It was not
enough to rescue the orphans from this pharmacological Fagin. They would need a
new place to go.
When Shaffer and his colleagues started
talking about the rescue effort more than ten years ago, there was one DSM-IV
diagnosis that seemed suitable: Oppositional-Defiant Disorder (ODD), “a pattern
of negativistic, hostile, and defiant behavior lasting at least 6 months” whose
symptoms included “often loses temper,” “often argues with adults,” and “is
often touchy.”
“The truth was that many of these kids
would meet criteria for ODD,” said Shaffer. Without changing the criteria, let
alone introducing a new diagnosis, they could be assigned to this category. But
there was a problem. “ODD had become tarnished,” says Shaffer, by its association
with two other diagnoses: Conduct Disorder, the label given to childhood
bullies and thugs, and Antisocial Personality Disorder, or what is often called
sociopathy. Longitudinal studies did not back up the
hunch that ODD belonged in the same neighborhood as these diagnoses; kids with
ODD did not go on to become thieves, rapists, or hedge fund managers in greater
numbers than other kids. But the bad reputation was impossible to shed, or so
Shaffer and his colleagues thought.
“So we had this problem: the criteria of
ODD would fit most of the kids who were being diagnosed as bipolar, but we
couldn’t call it ODD because it was a stigmatized name,” he explained. “It
sounded like you were heading to be a crook, and people wouldn’t go for it.” By
people, Shaffer said he meant not only the doctors who would be reluctant to
deliver that verdict, but also, and more important, parents—who, even if they
might want their kids to head for medical school, wouldn’t want them to come
out like Joseph Biederman. And parents were likely to be unhappy when they
discovered that insurance companies tended not to be as generous with treatment
dollars for ODD as they were for Bipolar Disorder, which, perversely, has the
better reputation of the two because it is a worse disease.
“Our real audience must be the parents,”
Shaffer said he told his colleagues when they were deliberating over the name
for the new disorder. And the name they came up with is what Shaffer thought
was his fault. It’s not that his proposal didn’t make sense, especially for his
main audience. “It’s an area with a big parent movement,” he said. “What they
see are kids with terrible tempers. So, I thought, let’s give it a nontechnical
name. Couldn’t we just call it Temper Dysregulation Disorder?”
Shaffer says he couldn’t have known that
by using such a common word as temper, he would be
walking into Allen Frances’s arguments about “psychiatrizing normal behavior.”
But it’s not as if he didn’t have warning. He didn’t exactly focus-group the
new label, but he did run it by his colleagues. At least one of them objected
vehemently. “Ellen said, ‘Oh, God, what a terrible name!’”
Ellen was Ellen Leibenluft, a psychiatrist
at NIMH. In 2003, she and a group of colleagues tried to tease out the manic
from the irritable among kids who were getting snared in Biederman’s expanded
net. They looked for ways (other than the mania/irritability distinction) in
which the two populations differed and proposed a “broad phenotype” that
described the nonmanic patients. They called this phenotype “severe mood and
behavioral dysregulation” and proposed “multisite clinical trials” to test
whether the category was valid—whether, that is, the children would differ from
one another not only according to their symptoms but also according to their
family histories, the course of their troubles, and their response to
treatment. There was already some suggestive, if preliminary, evidence on this
last question: “that children with the broad
phenotype10 may respond well to stimulants”—to
the old standbys Ritalin and Adderall, in other words, rather than to
Biederman’s pet drug Risperdal and the other antipsychotics.
Leibenluft later wrote that her intention
was not to “claim to define a new diagnosis11.
She didn’t mean to establish a new territory in the landscape of mental
illness, but rather to strengthen the boundaries of the one that already
existed—Bipolar Disorder—and to make sure that certain patients remained
outside them. Still, the description of severe mood dysregulation, with its
criteria list and its parameters—“markedly increased” and “at least half of the
day most days” and its “symptoms have been present for at least 12
months”—looked an awful lot like something that would appear in the DSM. And
sure enough, when the DSM-5 proposals hit the Web in February 2010, the
disorder, with Shaffer’s terrible name attached, had been nominated for the big
show.
The work group on childhood and adolescent
disorders acknowledged the doubts their proposal raised. In the paper “Justification for Temper Dysregulation Disorder
with Dysphoria12,” it questioned whether it was
“premature to suggest the addition of the TDD diagnosis, since . . . many
questions remain unanswered.” Most of the research they relied on had been
conducted before the idea of TDD had even been advanced, so researchers had had
to render “proxy definitions,” mining old data for information that, had those
researchers been interested in TDD, would have been relevant. And although some
clinical trials had been conducted using the research criteria, they hadn’t yet
addressed the question of which drugs the kids should get, which meant that
clinicians might well render the diagnosis and still reach for the Risperdal.
The group also acknowledged that the
research had not really demonstrated that TDD was a better-fitting diagnosis
than ODD. To the contrary, it had shown that nearly all TDD patients could also
be seen as suffering a particularly bad case of ODD, so they could be diagnosed
that way, using a severity specifier that would indicate that the kid had the
TDD form of ODD—a move that would avoid the uncertainties and wrangling
involved in manufacturing a brand-new diagnosis.
In addition, they confessed, “the work has
been done predominately by one research group in a select research setting.”
This was important because the whole point of criterion-based diagnosis is to
allow real-life clinicians—as opposed to elite researchers who know what they
are looking for and get to look for it in patients preselected for the
purpose—to reach the new diagnosis strictly by applying the criteria. The
possibility existed, in other words, that TDD would not be a reliable diagnosis
and would only add to the confusion about these patients.
Finally, the fact that this one team had
generated “relatively little research” also created the potential for the
disorder to be “prematurely reified.” The work group didn’t explain this cryptic
comment. Were they worried that doctors (or parents) would make the common
error, the one that Hyman and Mirin and every other DSM expert warned about, of
thinking that a disease listed in the official manual of mental disorders and
used as the basis for research, treatment, and reimbursement actually existed?
Or were they only worried that the disorder, with its scant research record,
didn’t yet deserve to be reified, or, to put it
another way, that TDD wasn’t even ready to provide fodder for the error that,
no matter how regrettable, was indispensable to the industry?
What the justification didn’t mention was
that the work group was headed by one of those researchers and that Ellen
Leibenluft was one of its eight members. Which may or may not explain why the
group dismissed its doubts almost as quickly as it raised them. Even if “the
scientific data may suggest defining TDD as a specifier to ODD,” clinicians
“would be unlikely” to use it—not only because it takes a few extra minutes to
assess and note severity, but also for the reason David Shaffer noted: ODD’s
bad reputation. “Indeed,” the work group argued, “it is plausible that
clinicians assign the diagnosis of BD . . . in part because the BD diagnosis
justifies access to a higher level of resources.”
Their license to go beyond the science in
this fashion, the work group explained, came right from the top, from a task
force that had specifically instructed them to weigh “clinical considerations
in the decision as to whether to propose a new diagnosis.” Questions of
clinician time and insurance reimbursement, not to mention any tarnish on the
diagnosis, were significant in the clinic. And there were benefits beyond
insurance payments: once the diagnosis was established, if not reified, it
would jump-start researchers’ efforts to fill in the gaps in the data,
attracting money to study the new disorder.
If, in their zeal to make sure that
children (and, of course, their doctors) had access to resources, it occurred
to the work group that their efforts might amount to swallowing a spider to
kill a fly, or that there were other, simpler ways to repudiate Biederman (such
as adding an exclusion criterion or just calling the cops on the crook, if
indeed that’s what he was), or if they understood that manufacturing a new mood
disorder was like throwing fresh meat to the pharmaceutical industry, or if
they noticed that by advancing a diagnosis that wasn’t even ready to be
reified, they were suggesting a long-term public health experiment whose
subjects (children and doctors both) would be unaware of their participation,
they didn’t say. But then again, hadn’t Kupfer and Regier said that this DSM
would be a living document?
• • •
Indeed they had, and on March
9, the APA made this official when it
announced a new “naming convention13.” The upcoming
revision would be known as DSM-5, not DSM-V, and henceforward all new DSMs
would likewise be identified with Arabic, rather than Roman, numerals. The new
name, like Shaffer’s TDD, replaced the arcane with the familiar, but for
reasons different from his. “Knowledge of neurobiology will continue to
advance,” APA president Alan Schatzberg said in the press release. The purpose
of the change was not to capture hearts and minds, but to make room for the
scientific advances that hadn’t happened yet, by turning the DSM into “a
document that can respond more quickly when a preponderance of research
supports a change.” The APA hadn’t quite figured out the details, whether, say,
it would grant purchasers of the new book a license to download updates as new
research developed or just turn the whole business over to Amazon, but one
thing was certain: after DSM-5 came “DSM-5.1, DSM 5.2, etc., until a new
edition is required.” DSM-5, evidently, was going to be beta-tested.
David Kupfer seemed to anticipate the
problem hidden in the new convention—that it more or less announced that the
foundational text of his profession, the one that provided certainty about
matters of vital importance to insurers and regulators and drug companies and
patients, was provisional—when he reassured the public that “our primary
commitment will continue to be to create a manual that is based on science and
is useful in diagnosing and treating patients.”
Darrel Regier also telegraphed comfort,
first to his colleagues—“By making the DSM-5 a living document, we will ensure
that the DSM will remain a common language in the field”—and then to the rest
of us: “It will hasten our response to breakthroughs in research.” What exactly
we were supposed to do before those breakthroughs could occur, he didn’t
exactly say. The framers of the DSM-5 may have been replacing the Bible with a
living document, but they were still asking us to take them on faith.
• • •
Naming conventions were
definitely on Alan Schatzberg’s mind when he delivered his outgoing
presidential address to the May 2010 APA annual convention in New Orleans.
Schatzberg reminded his troops that they
were still at war. Our “detractors” may be hypocritical—they don’t criticize
neurologists for talking about minor cognitive impairment, after all, and they
don’t seem to understand that they are stigmatizing psychiatry out of fear and
ignorance and “antipsychiatry sentiment” rather than for anything psychiatry
has done wrong. And, Schatzberg continued, psychiatrists themselves were making
it far too easy for their enemies by using a “distinctly
unmedical14” language to name their diseases.
“The proposed temper dysregulation disorder . . . does not convey” the
seriousness of the condition, and, unlike the cardiologists’ recasting of heart attack as myocardial infarction,
it had no “parallel and more medical terminology.” Psychiatrists were the
victims once again, this time of their own just-folks language.
“Some
of the attacks15 have been by English and history
professors,” Schatzberg said. “My friends, this does present a problem we need
to think about. Everyone feels emotions; everyone reads pop psychology articles
or watches pop psychologists on TV; and many come to believe they are experts
in psychiatry.” It was time to draw the line between the civilians who had
those emotions and the experts who knew what they really meant, and the best
way to do this might be to shroud nosology in the “Latin and Greek terms” used
by other specialties.
“We need to be more medical to be taken
seriously,” Schatzberg concluded.
Schatzberg had some other bad tidings for
his membership. After noting that New
Orleans had “risen as the Phoenix16 from the horrors
of Katrina to rebuild itself” (with the help of psychiatrists, he added) and
that the theme of the convention was “Pride and Promise: Toward a New Psychiatry,”
he told them that their finances were turning to ashes. Revenues had shrunk by
$10 million, to $55 million, largely because of a recession-related drop-off in
drug company advertising in the APA’s journals.
Another pool of drug company money had also
dried up, thanks to the decision to stop letting the industry fund the APA’s
education programs. In Schatzberg’s reading, this renunciation wasn’t quite as
noble as Jay Scully had made it out to be, or as unilateral. In fact,
Schatzberg said, “the negative attacks on
industry17 have made them gun shy of
supporting such programs.”
As perhaps befits a man who had made Chuck
Grassley’s hit parade, Schatzberg regretted this development. “There are a number of new drugs18
that have been recently released that many of us know little about,” he said,
“and that cannot be good for either us or our patients.” (Apparently,
Schatzberg couldn’t imagine another way for doctors to learn about new drugs
other than from the sales forces of the companies that make them; perhaps he
also buys his cars based on what his dealer tells him.) “The strident debate
and attacks have obfuscated the negative impact of eliminating industry from
our offices,” he complained.
As unjust as it might have been, however,
the drug company purge seemed irreversible. The APA was going to have to make
up that $10 million deficit somehow. The organization won’t say how much
revenue it anticipates from a new DSM, but you don’t have to run a
meta-analysis to figure out that a new book would be worth far more at its
outset than the $6 million the DSM-IV generated in 2010. Leaders of the APA
would not confirm the old suspicion that money was a driving force behind the
revision (although one trustee did tell me that “it would be disastrous not to
get that income”), but that looming bonanza had to be looking pretty good—if
only they could get their hands on it.
Chapter 11
Allen
Frances wasn’t limiting himself to his blogs, which by mid-2010 were appearing
on three different websites and broadcasting a steady tocsin of impending doom.
He also published articles in medical journals and on newspaper websites, and
gave interviews to all the journalists attracted to the spectacle of a leader
of the orthodoxy accusing his fellow priests of heresy. He may not have been a
Quixote, but he was surely less a Sancho Panza than a Paul Revere, shouting
warnings into the night: the DSM-5 was coming!
In August, Frances sounded his alarm from
the op-ed page of The New York Times, where he
declaimed against the proposal to remove the bereavement exclusion from the
depression diagnosis. “Turning bereavement
into major depression1,” he wrote, “would substitute a
shallow, Johnny-come-lately medical ritual for the sacred mourning rites that
have survived for millenniums.” An appointment with a psychiatrist, at least
according to this prominent practitioner, was no simple office visit. It was a
ritual, and it wasn’t even the best ritual available for at least one common
form of suffering.
Frances understood by then that his views
could be exploited by psychiatry’s enemies and that the higher his profile
became, the greater the risk that people would get the wrong message. Already
some critics of psychiatry had been quick to use him to further their own idea
that DSM diagnoses were just-so stories. But that is not what he meant, he
said. “Sure, there’s a reality out there2,
but we have an incomplete perception of it. We see through a glass darkly, but
that doesn’t mean we don’t see at all.” Uncertainty was inescapable, but it
could be reduced—and inevitably would be, he thought. As neuroscience comes into
its own, he told me, and “the complexity begins to clarify out of the mist,
diagnoses will become better and better constructs, ever closer to a reality
that will always be elusive to our limited powers of apprehension.”
At stake, Frances insisted, was something
more immediate and urgent than intellectual controversy or internecine warfare:
the care of patients, particularly those who might be “wavering about treatment
and attracted to an antipsychiatry point of view.”
“They would not be able to do the calculation,”
he told me, to say, “‘Well, maybe this isn’t perfect, but it’s still the best
way available, and we shouldn’t just throw it out.’” Every blog and interview
drew back the curtain on psychiatry’s inner workings a little further,
threatening to make the whole field look like humbug. “I’m reluctant to reveal
all the Wizard of Oz stuff,” he said, “because I don’t
want people who need help to get disillusioned and stop taking their medicine.”
From Plato to Saint Paul to Heisenberg to
Baum—it was a typical Allen Frances ramble. And it ended right back in Plato’s Republic. “The full truth3
is usually best,” Frances said, “but sometimes we may need a noble lie.”
• • •
Beneficence—the doctor’s obligation to act in the best interests of his or her
patients—has long been considered a core value of medicine. In its name,
doctors have routinely lied to patients, or at least stretched the truth,
withholding terrible prognoses from terminally ill people, for instance, or
overstating the effectiveness of a treatment. In recent years, another core
value has come to the forefront: autonomy, the right
of the patient to determine the course of his or her treatment. To uphold this
principle, at least according to some medical ethicists, doctors need to
curtail their beneficence, or at least not use it as a reason to be less than
transparent with their patients, so they can make fully informed decisions. And
the Internet, much to many doctors’ dismay, has opened curtains that they would
like to keep completely shut. The two principles continue to vie for primacy,
and some of that tension can be seen in Frances’s concerns about what the
public should know about the nature of psychiatric nosology.
It’s easy enough to see this as
self-serving, to say that lying can’t be noble, at least not when it is used to
maintain an authority that might not survive a full disclosure. Plato might
well have been appalled to see how the control of information would be used by
Machiavelli or Dostoevsky’s Grand Inquisitor or Dick Cheney. But you can’t
really blame Plato for being naive about the attractions of power or for not
seeing how useful noble lies could be to people who want to hold on to it. He
lived before autonomy and equality were expectations for a good life, before
universal justice was the hallmark of a good society, and before a couple
thousand years of history had revealed what can happen when people with
power—even virtuous people—act in the supposed interests of those with none.
Not that Frances’s concern about the
effect of diagnostic squabbling on patients was less than beneficent or only
about maintaining psychiatry’s dominion over our inner lives. “Like most medical specialties4,
our field depends heavily on placebo effects,” he pointed out. And pills aren’t
the only way to deliver the placebo effect. Even if “the diagnostic label is
just a description, and not really an explanation for what has gone wrong,”
Frances says, still it is crucial to treatment. Delivering a diagnosis gives us
solace: that we are not making it up, that the doctor understands, that there
are others like us, that there is hope for a cure.
“If you puncture that noble lie,” Frances
warned me, “you’ll be doing a disservice to our patients.”
But indiscreet writers aren’t the only
people who pose a danger. “A doctor saying you have depression, that’s part of
the treatment—so long as you don’t go overboard in promising that everything
can be explained through chemical reactions and it doesn’t have anything to do
with the fact that your wife died last week.” This was the risk Frances saw in
removing the bereavement exclusion: that doctors would feel free to deliver
that verdict to grieving patients, that indeed the DSM would more or less
oblige them to do so. And given what Frances calls “the ignorance of philosophy
of the average practitioner,” not to mention the pressures on him or her to be
efficient and to provide relief, doctors might not even know how careful they
needed to be about exercising their diagnostic power, how easily it could be
ignobly—and globally—deployed. Psychiatric diagnosis, it seems, is more
sophisticated than most clinicians realize. Getting rid of the bereavement
exclusion would invite not only the overtreatment of patients but, after the
inevitable backlash, yet another credibility crisis for the profession.
• • •
On the other hand, you have
to appreciate the problem that the bereavement exclusion presented to the
shapers of the DSM-5.
Some people who weren’t enemies of
psychiatry thought they smelled a rat even if it wasn’t the one that
antipsychiatrists smelled. To New York University professor of social work
Jerome Wakefield, for instance, the bereavement exclusion itself wasn’t such a
bad idea. It prevented a person who had all the symptoms of an illness, but who
wasn’t really sick, from getting mistakenly diagnosed. The exclusion, he wrote,
protected patients from “stigmatization
[and] inappropriate care5” and psychiatry from “inflated
epidemiological prevalence rates that undermine the credibility of the
diagnostic system.” And its caveats—that people who were suicidal or otherwise
dysfunctional, or whose symptoms persisted beyond two months of the death
should not be excluded—prevented doctors from dismissing severe symptoms as
normal reactions and thus ensured that patients who needed treatment could get
it.
So far, so good. But Wakefield thought
there was a deeper problem. Why, he wondered, did the book “ignore the many other kinds6
of serious losses that can cause intense symptoms of normal sadness”? Was it
possible that not enough people were protected from the potential harms of
diagnosis?
Wakefield and a team of researchers that
included Michael First designed an experiment to find out. They mined the
National Comorbidity Survey (NCS), the NIMH project that demonstrated that 60
percent of mentally disordered people qualified for more than one diagnosis. As
it happened, the NCS researchers had asked subjects not only about recent
bereavement, but about whether there was “anything else going on” that might
have caused them to “feel sad or blue.” This created an opportunity for a
researcher who, like Wakefield, was curious about whether there was a
difference between the bereaved and people who had suffered other losses.
Of the 1,308 NCS subjects with major
depression, 157 reported that their symptoms had been set off by a bereavement
and 710 said that a different kind of loss had triggered them. Wakefield then
examined to what extent those two groups differed along two dimensions: disorder indicators, such as how many symptoms of depression
they had or how long they lasted; and symptom group,
which of the nine depression symptoms they reported. It turned out that there
was virtually no difference between the two groups in either dimension.
Divorce, death of a loved one, financial setback—each was as likely as the
others to leave a person sad or apathetic or insomniac, as likely as the others
to send a person to a therapist or a doctor for an antidepressant.
Wakefield further divided his subjects
into uncomplicated and complicated
groups. Complicated subjects were those with the severe symptoms, such as suicidal
thoughts or the inability to function, that would have disqualified them from
the bereavement exclusion, and uncomplicated subjects . . . well, you figure it
out. Not surprisingly, people in each group resembled one another more than
they resembled people in the other group who had suffered the same kind of
setback. Loss is loss, in other words. What differs is how we respond to it,
not what we are responding to.
Taken together, these two findings—that no
matter what the precipitating event is, it has the same effects, and that the
main difference is in the intensity of response—indicated that there was no
scientific reason to treat the death of a loved one differently from other
losses. The experiment was simple, elegant, and conclusive. The bereavement
exclusion was arbitrary and incoherent, and if that was so, then the MDD
criteria were not able to sort the well from the sick.
In The Loss of Sadness,
Wakefield and his coauthor, sociologist Allan Horwitz, made it clear that more
was at stake than the bereavement exclusion. Even if we accept the inescapable
fuzziness of psychiatric diagnoses, they argued, still a nosology must have
some kind of integrity, lest the DSM “define
every undesirable consequence7 of sadness as a
disorder.”
“Psychiatry
has made immense strides8 in recent decades,” they wrote, but
one thing it had not figured out was how to limit its tendency to “engulf all
the problems that life poses.” The solution was not to abandon the depression
diagnosis, even if the bereavement exclusion constituted a “compelling, clear
and major violation of validity.” Instead, they wrote, the diagnosis “should be
fixed.” And the best way to do that was to expand the exclusion beyond
bereavement to “other major life stressors” so that clinicians could
distinguish between disorder and distress,
and diagnose and treat people accordingly. Forcing clinicians to consider the
actual life experience of their patients would limit the damage that their
diagnoses could do even as it maintained their ability to help patients.
“There
are few signs9 that changes in the MDD criteria
are a high priority for the . . . DSM-V,” Wakefield and Horwitz concluded. But
that was in 2007, before their book became a minor sensation, and just as a
spate of other books and articles complained that depression was getting
overdiagnosed and, not coincidentally, antidepressants alarmingly overprescribed.
And as the DSM-5 revision geared up, it became clear that researchers concerned
about psychiatry’s overstepping weren’t the only people disturbed by the
bereavement exclusion.
“It
just doesn’t make any sense to me whatsoever10,” psychiatrist
Sidney Zisook told me on the phone. “Maybe it did when I first got into the
field, but not anymore.”
But Zisook’s objection was different from
Wakefield’s. It wasn’t the double standard—the fact that only the grieving were
eligible for a reprieve from diagnosis—that bothered him. It was the assumption
that bereavement-related depression (BRD), as he called the suffering covered
by the exclusion, was somehow different from standard
major depression (SMD). If the two were not different in nature, if, in other
words, the only difference between BRD and SMD was in their cause, then there
really was no difference between them, no reason to distinguish patients
according to their recent experience.
In 2007, working with Ken Kendler, Zisook did some data mining of his own11.
He extracted information from about fifty studies conducted over three decades
and comprising more than eight thousand depressed subjects, only some of whom
met the exclusion criterion. They looked at the Robins and Guze
validators—family history and other demographics, overall health (mental and
otherwise), lab tests, response to treatment, and the course and outcome of the
patients’ troubles. And while some of the evidence was inconclusive—it wasn’t
clear whether BRD ran in families, for instance—most of the results showed that
BRD was no different from SMD. Bereaved people who had the symptoms of
depression were no different from other patients who had the symptoms.
Wakefield had proved that loss was loss; now Zisook and Kendler had shown that
depression was depression, regardless of its cause.
Zisook and Kendler were careful with their
conclusions, at least at first. Their analysis only “provides some support12,
although indirect and limited,” they wrote, “that excluding recently bereaved
individuals from the diagnosis of MDE [Major Depressive Episode] . . . may not
be justified.” And pending further research, “the most propitious conclusion
may be that, on average, these two syndromes [BRD and SMD] appear to be closely
related.”
Six months later, however, Zisook and
Kendler, along with a third collaborator, published another paper on the same
topic. Its data and findings were nearly identical to the earlier report’s. But
there was something new in the second article. “Because
work toward the DSM-V13 has begun,” they wrote, “it is
timely to re-examine the DSM’s bereavement exclusion.”
Reframed as a discussion of what should be
done now that the revision was under way, the questions about the bereavement
exclusion took on a new urgency and the authors demonstrated a new certainty.
First, they pointed out, research had shown that the earlier depression is
treated the better, and that antidepressant medication is particularly
effective in the earliest stages of a depressive episode. Which means, they
said, that the “validity of the bereavement
exclusion14 . . . is not an academic issue.”
Indeed, Zisook told me, we should also worry about what happens to people who
don’t get diagnosed.
“I don’t think we’re doing patients a
service by avoiding the label if they meet the criteria,” he said. “I think if
we say that in addition to their bereavement they are also depressed, we might
intervene more aggressively and sooner and save people a lot of pain,
discomfort and, who knows, maybe even lives.”
“Why
should bereavement be singled out15 as the only
stressful life event that excludes the diagnosis of MDE?” they asked. It was a
rhetorical question, of course. To Wakefield and Horwitz, psychiatric diagnosis
was a potential harm against which we need protection. To Kendler and Zisook,
it was a benefit that we should not be denied.
“Idiotic16,”
said Jerry Wakefield, when I asked him what he thought of the proposal to
remove the exclusion. “But clever in its own diabolical way—they used my
evidence against me!”
Wakefield was not on the mood disorders
work group for the DSM-5. Neither was Michael First or Allan Horwitz. Ken
Kendler, on the other hand, was, and Sid Zisook was a special consultant to it.
Which may or may not explain why the work group decided, even in the
acknowledged absence of direct evidence and despite the tentativeness of the
conclusions—not to mention the obvious public relations problem—to eliminate
the bereavement exclusion. At the very least, the proposal seems to confirm the
notion that experts, given the charter to implement their pet theories as
diagnostic changes, will tinker, and that their tinkering is likely to be in
the direction of more rather than fewer diagnoses.
Experts like Zisook are not unaware of the
possibility of overdiagnosis. They’re just less worried about what they call false positives than about false negatives.
Leaving an illness untreated is more dangerous, in their view, than making
illness out of everyday life. And Zisook may be on the National Advisory Board
of GlaxoSmithKline, for whom he once ran a
study showing that GSK’s Wellbutrin17 was effective
for grieving people, but that doesn’t necessarily mean he’s shilling for the
company by proposing the expansion of the diagnostic net, or even that he will
hawk their products to more patients once the exclusion is lifted. “I don’t
think everyone with major depression needs meds or formal therapy,” said
Zisook. “I think sometimes watchful waiting is appropriate. Sometimes support
and education is appropriate. Sometimes decreasing stress is appropriate.” A
good clinician knows when to do which. Expertise is what guarantees that a
doctor’s power is used beneficently.
Zisook places great stock in expertise—and
not just when it comes to treatment. “The DSM criteria don’t allow for judgment
on symptoms,” he told me. “I think a really astute clinician will make
decisions as to whether a behavior is a symptom of depression or not.” Removing
the bereavement exclusion won’t stop a good doctor from withholding a diagnosis
from a grieving patient even if she meets the criteria.
Consider, Zisook said, a patient who is
recently widowed and not only sad and withdrawn but also guilt-ridden over all
he should have done to prevent the loss of his wife. “That guilt would count
toward depression,” Zisook acknowledged, but “when I have this patient in front
of me, I don’t count that as a symptom of depression.” Expertise can be relied
upon to determine whether guilt is a symptom or just guilt, and whether the
criteria add up to a disorder. Astute clinicians, like the crackerjack doctors
who staff Zisook’s elite university medical center, don’t need bereavement
exclusions to limit their diagnostic powers. They don’t need to slave away at
checklists like common clerks.
But Zisook evidently does not want to
extend this same latitude to the rank-and-file clinicians, the ones who spend
their days seeing patients with a range of psychiatric disorders—not to mention
the general practitioners who do most of the prescribing of antidepressants—and
who aren’t supported by research grants and generous faculty salaries, who
don’t have an hour or so to spend talking with their patients or administering
carefully calibrated diagnostic tests that can be scored by assistants or
worrying over the fine points of what it means to say that the miserable person
in front of them actually has a mental disorder. Run-of-the-mill doctors, it
seems, can’t be trusted with a bereavement exclusion, any more than the layman
can be trusted with all that Wizard of Oz stuff. They
must remain loyal to the fundamental tenet of the DSM: that, as Zisook put it,
the “criteria are the same regardless of context. If someone meets them, I
should give them the label of major depression because that’s what they
have”—although evidently only so long as the “I” in question is not Zisook or
any other clinician too astute to take the DSM too seriously.
• • •
“The DSM-IV position is not logically defensible18,”
Ken Kendler wrote in a statement the APA posted on the DSM-5 website shortly
after Frances’s Times op-ed appeared and a public
furor broke out.
Kendler wasn’t talking about the
incoherence of saying that depression is depression unless an elite clinician
determines that it is not. He was talking about the way the exclusion
contradicted the basic idea of the DSM—that mental disorders can (and, for now
anyway, must) be known by their symptoms alone. “The grief exclusion criterion
needs to be [either] eliminated or extended so that no depression that arises
in the setting of adversity would be diagnosable.” And, since “the majority of
individuals” who get the diagnosis develop it “in the setting of psychosocial
adversity,” he added, this curtailing of the diagnosis would “represent a major
shift . . . in the nature of our concept of depression.”
It’s not clear where Kendler got the idea
that the only alternative to eliminating the exclusion was to make it impossible
to diagnose depression in the presence of a stressor. It couldn’t have been
from Wakefield, who never said that depression kindled by adversity should go
undiagnosed. To the contrary, he was trying to lay the groundwork for a return
to a traditional, pre-DSM-III idea of depression: “that sadness in response to loss19
is natural and normal, and that the indication of disorder lies in the sadness
being without sufficient cause in given environmental contexts or being
disproportional to actual loss.” Depression, according to this abandoned
notion, was sick only to the extent that it occurred without regard to a
person’s life circumstances.
Wakefield was proposing, in other words,
that if you want to know if a person is really sick rather than simply reacting
to a loss, you have to look at the relationship between the stressor and the
person’s reaction. You have to try to understand what the loss means to the
patient. And if it is out of proportion, then you have to figure that you are
in the presence of a genuine illness—something gone wrong in the body (in this
case, the brain)—rather than normal sorrow. Indeed, Wakefield was only
suggesting that the prerogative Zisook reserved for the astute (but would deny to
everyone else by removing the exclusion) was actually an obligation for all
clinicians: to pay attention not only to diagnostic checklists but also to the
patient in front of them.
Right now, if you are not a psychiatrist
or any other kind of mental health worker, or maybe even if you are, you are
probably thinking, “Duh!” You’re probably wondering how it is possible that
something as obvious as this even needs to be said, let alone argued about. But
that’s only because you have decided to make your living in some other fashion,
one that does not require you to satisfy an insurance company or your
colleagues in other specialties or yourself—if you take seriously your
involvement in the medical-industrial complex—that you are treating “real
illnesses.” You haven’t signed on for a profession whose badly tarnished
reputation was once restored by applying the thinnest veneer of scientific
rhetoric and polishing it vigorously, and which now has to protect itself from
the sullying effects of a proposal like Wakefield’s, even if it means taking
the absurd position that there is no essential difference between a depression
kindled by the loss of a child or parent and a depression brought on by the
cancellation of a favorite television show or the death of a pet hamster—or
between any of those and a depression that seems to come on out of nowhere.
Good for you, I say. Because if even a man
of integrity like Sid Zisook, who is as affable and humane and charming a guy
as you might like to meet, and surely the kind of psychiatrist—empathic,
articulate, knowledgeable—whom, if you needed one, you’d want to see, if such a
man finds himself, in the space of two minutes, totally contradicting himself,
talking out of both sides of his mouth, and unwittingly becoming the best evidence
of the incoherence of his own position merely by acknowledging that he pays
attention to his patients, when smart and compassionate doctors spill buckets
of ink over the question of whether or not they should consider what we are
going through before they tell us what we are suffering from and what we should
do about it, and when the proposal to do so moves Bob Spitzer to say to me, “If
we did that, then the whole system falls apart,” then you know that you are
knee-deep in a setting of psychosocial adversity.
And, indeed, all of us in the mental
health industry know this, from the APA trustee who shook his head and told me
in a mournful voice, “We’re just so stuck,” to Allen Frances to Steve Hyman to
lunchbucket therapists like me who hold our noses when we put those codes onto
the bill. We may not be sophisticated enough to grasp the nobility of the lie
that sustains the DSM or to be trusted as its keepers. We may not be astute
enough to distinguish between depression and grief. But we all know that the
DSM is at its best a clumsy and imperfect field guide to our foibles and at its
worst a compendium of expert opinions masquerading as scientific truths, a book
whose credibility surpasses its integrity, whose usefulness is primarily
commercial, and whose most ardent defenders are reduced to arguing that it
should be taken less seriously even as all of us—clinicians, researchers, and
copyright holders alike—cash in on the fact that it is not.
Chapter 12
On
December 17, 2010, instead of the usual Friday grand rounds, the department of
psychiatry at Columbia University honored Bob Spitzer on the occasion of his
retirement. Colleagues from past and present paid tribute with recollections
and praise. A historian put Spitzer’s forty-nine-year career into historical
perspective. Allen Frances spoke from the same lectern from which he had railed
against DSM-5 eleven months earlier. This time he really did hold back. He
scarcely mentioned the revision. He didn’t tease Spitzer. He just talked about
his contribution, about how he was one of the most important psychiatrists who
had ever lived, placing him in the company of Freud and Kraepelin. He couldn’t
resist reminding the audience about the limitations of the descriptive method,
but still, he said, it is “the best we can
do1, and Bob has been and will remain our master
describer.”
Like many such celebrations, the
proceedings were more than a little funereal—a tone deepened by Spitzer’s
halting, unsteady ascent to the stage, his quavering voice, his obvious
frailty. After warning the audience that his Parkinson’s disease had worsened
his tendency to burst into tears, he did exactly that. He didn’t get everything
said that he intended to say. He had a little trouble remembering exactly how
many children he had. But between gusts of weeping he told stories and
recounted arguments in a way that conveyed both the charisma and the toughness
that had allowed him to become the man who saved psychiatry.
That night Spitzer joined some of his
colleagues and collaborators and their wives for dinner at a downtown
restaurant. Harold Pincus, Michael First, Jerry Wakefield, and Allen Frances
were there. The DSM was far from the main topic of the loud and lively
conversation. When the subject did come up, it was in a dense shorthand, the
code that signals deep agreement, words such as “field trials” and “polythetic
criteria” and “prevalence rates” that carried a world of meaning impenetrable
to outsiders. Theirs was a shared, private language, much as they thought the
DSM’s should be.
But when it came to revising that
language, they were now the outsiders. Spitzer and Frances had been placed on
the enemies’ list. First had been pushed aside. Pincus had never been involved.
Wakefield (who, as a nonpsychiatrist, was never as inside as the rest) had had
his evidence used against him. They were still shouting at one another, still
teasing, enjoying conversation as if it were a contact sport. But their shared
love of argument, their common language, and the DSM they had fashioned—the one
that, in true Talmudic fashion (and it was hard not to notice that these men
were all Jews by birth), they were both proud and skeptical of—was now the
language of opposition, of resentment, and, increasingly, of powerlessness and
cynicism. The event they’d all come together to commemorate signaled not just
the end of a career, but the passing of an era.
There was one word in the discussion with
deeper meanings that an outsider might have grasped, if only by the seething
anger with which it was uttered: “Darrel.”
Darrel Regier is not a shouter or a teaser
(or, as it happens, a Jew). He is a mild-mannered man, a Midwest-educated bean
counter whose time in New York had begun and ended with his medical internship
at Montefiore Medical Center in the Bronx, who has no apparent use for irony,
and whose ability to insulate his sentences from objection with thick layers of
bureaucratese was probably more useful in his ascent to the rank of vice
admiral in the U.S. Public Health Service than shouting and teasing ever would
have been. After all, it’s pretty tough to argue with a sentence like this one,
taken from an article he wrote.
Moving forward2, I believe the more critical issue
for work group members is how to avoid mind-body dualism in which mental
disorders are moved in neurological classifications as more precise
pathophysiological, neuroimaging, genetic, nutritional, infectious, traumatic
or other etiological characteristics are discovered.
Not that Regier lacks the ability to
fight. “Darrel knows how to throw an elbow,” one psychiatrist told me. Indeed,
just a month or so before the gathering for Spitzer, Regier’s pugilistic skills
had been on full display at a conference on psychiatric nosology held in
Copenhagen and sponsored by the Danish National Research Foundation’s Center
for Subjectivity Research—a gathering originally scheduled for April, but
delayed when a volcanic eruption in Iceland closed European airports.
Regier’s talk was in many ways a career
retrospective. He told his colleagues that he had entered the profession in the
early 1970s, in the bad old days when the Midtown Manhattan Study and other
pre-DSM-III efforts were turning up inordinate rates of mental illness in the
population, and when “the clinical judgment
of a psychiatrist3 was the gold standard of
psychiatric diagnosis.” The DSM-III had made matters a little better, but not
much, he said—the 50 percent lifetime prevalence rates reached in some analyses
of his ECA project were still too high and the
National Comorbidity Survey4, the one that had
shown that 27 percent of diagnosable people had more than one DSM-III disorder,
were a blot on the nosological record. Diagnosticians may have gotten more
scientific, but their methods still yielded results that flew in the face of
common sense.
Regier recounted the two epidemiological
studies from the 1950s that had yielded much lower (and, Regier thought,
realistic) prevalence rates. These projects shared one important
characteristic: they relied on doctors to identify the cases in a community.
Ask doctors who under their care is sick, it seemed, and you get a much lower
number than if you ask randomly selected people about their symptoms. “We had much greater confidence5
in the clinical assessments of physicians with some longitudinal knowledge of
all persons requesting care,” Regier said.
So perhaps that old gold standard,
clinical judgment, had been too hastily discarded in the name of reliability.
Intimate knowledge of a patient’s history and circumstances, coupled with sound
medical knowledge, seemed to provide a check on diagnostic exuberance,
identifying within the group that met the criteria those individuals who were
truly ill. But how to incorporate that into a reliable nosology? Or to put it
another way, how could epidemiologists cut the vagaries of physician judgment
out of the loop while still maintaining doctors as the gatekeepers to diagnosis
and treatment?
Regier’s solution was to try to establish
when a person has crossed the threshold from healthy to sick. In their
introductions, Spitzer and Frances had instructed users of the DSM that if the
symptoms weren’t clinically significant, there was no diagnosis to make; no
matter how many symptoms you had, you weren’t mentally ill unless your
suffering was clinically significant. But that term had never really been defined;
establishing the threshold had been left up to the astute clinician. To find a
definition that could be consistently and reliably applied to individual cases
was to answer this question, or so Regier proposed. It would allow doctors to
specify when the criteria signified the presence of illness. And since those
cases were sure to be only a subset of all the people who met the criteria, the
prevalence estimates would come down from the stratosphere.
Regier thought the answer was hiding in
plain sight—in data collected, but lying dormant, in the ECA and NCS studies.
Researchers in both had asked subjects about how much their symptoms had
interfered with their lives, and especially whether or not they had been so bad
that they had gone to see a doctor about them. The answers had not been used to
determine whether or not the people were mentally disordered, but in the late
1990s, Regier’s team began to dig them out6.
They fashioned an algorithm, applied it to the data, and presto! Prevalence
rates came in at 18 percent—still higher than where Regier thought they should
be, but still as much as two-thirds lower than the original findings.
Regier was sure he’d threaded the needle,
but others disagreed, sometimes loudly. “To
put it mildly7,” he told the Copenhagen crowd,
“howls of protest arose from Spitzer, and later from Jerome Wakefield and
others.” The first skirmish was at a meeting of the American Psychopathological
Association in 2002, and two years later, when Regier published the results, a
fight broke out in the pages of Archives of General
Psychiatry. Wakefield and Spitzer
pointed out8 that of the nine questions used to
generate Regier’s data, seven were about whether people had sought treatment;
only two were about how debilitating the symptoms were. But plenty of sick
people never saw a doctor, and plenty of people who saw doctors weren’t sick.
Regier had confused treatment seeking with clinical significance, they said, which meant he had reduced
prevalence by gerrymandering the patient population rather than actually
specifying who was sick and who simply met the criteria.
“What
is striking about this debate9,” Regier
continued, “is that it became even more personal” when Ronald Kessler, who
headed the NCS study, warned in a 2003 Archives
article that it would be a mistake to use Regier’s methods to remove mild
disorders from the DSM-5—an agenda Kessler thought he had sniffed out in
Regier’s research. Kessler wrote that disorders falling short of the threshold
Regier was proposing could and often did lead to more severe disorders. A
person who confessed to anxiety or depression symptoms on a survey, but wasn’t
distressed enough to go to a doctor today, might well end up in the emergency
room next month with a panic attack or after a suicide attempt. Here again, the
problem was a kind of gerrymandering. The way to solve high prevalence rates,
Kessler concluded, was not “to define the
problem out of existence10” by suggesting that mild illness
wasn’t illness.
It is a little hard to discern what
exactly was personal about Kessler’s or Wakefield and Spitzer’s papers. They
are workaday journal articles, all charts and graphs and eye-glazing details
leading to careful conclusions. But there’s no question that the articles got
Regier’s goat, at least to judge from his response, which he recalled for the
audience in Copenhagen.
In response to this scientific critique11,
we thought it would be helpful to highlight the central issue in DSM-5
revisions very clearly and chose the James Carville approach by responding with
a letter to the editor in Archives entitled, “For
DSM-5, It’s the ‘Disorder Threshold,’ Stupid!”
Now that’s
personal.
“Bob did put up quite a fuss at that
conference [in 2000],” Jerry Wakefield told me. “But Darrel never forgave him.”
And ten years later Regier was still settling old scores, or at least revealing
scores he’d been keeping for a long time. “I
wasn’t aware that he had interpreted12 my remarks that
way,” Ronald Kessler said when I relayed Regier’s comments to him. “I honestly
don’t know what he means about it being personal.” But, he added, it wasn’t
entirely surprising. “Darrel reacts very strongly to people who disagree with
him.”
And by the time Regier got to Copenhagen, Allen
Frances was on the top of that list.
Certainly some of the loudest concerns13 in the blogs and
print media are that we will unleash a wave of false epidemics—with the past
editor of the DSM-IV claiming credit for creating false epidemics of pediatric
bipolar disorder, ADHD, and autism . . . He also proclaims little confidence
that the current editors can fix this problem or do better in the next edition.
Regier went on to denounce
Frances in a way that seemed more inspired by Joseph Biederman than James
Carville. Just look at the history of
“progress14 in the calibration and validation
of scientific constructs in astronomy, biology, and psychiatry,” he said. “Defenders
of the current construct do not yield easily to suggested changes in
paradigms.”
These debates were not going to end with a
pinch on the cheek and a kiss.
• • •
But if Frances was playing
the pope to Regier’s Galileo, did that mean that the paradigm shift was back
on? It is possible the DSM-5 leaders couldn’t make up their minds, that the
APA, like a squirrel in the road, knew enough to know it was in trouble, but
not enough to know what to do about it.
There was one way in which a paradigm
shift was in the making. It was not the sweeping change to a brain-based
nosology for which they so devoutly wished, but it was nonetheless far more
than a small technical matter. And it was the subject, beneath the vitriol, of
Regier’s talk in Copenhagen.
Regier’s argument with Wakefield and
Kessler was, as his Carvillian title pointed out, about the disorder threshold,
about how a doctor determines that a person has become a patient. And here was
one place that Regier agreed with Frances. Not that he would use barnyard
epithets, or epithets of any kind, but he did not think the solution was to
fabricate a definition of mental disorder. “It
may be of interest15 to this audience,” he said, after
reading aloud the DSM-IV definition, “that almost none of the DSM-V Task Force
or Work Group Meetings struggled with these definitional issues as they
evaluated the research literature to determine the evidentiary basis for
revisions.” The committees weren’t wasting time on philosophy. “Our plans for
DSM-V are to provide a range of cross-cutting measures that will identify
continuous measures of emotional, cognitive, addictive, and other domains,” he
said. “Most of our efforts will focus on the individual diagnostic measurements
that permit better assessments of the thresholds between normal and
pathological states.”
Regier was confirming his intent to forge
ahead with the new paradigm. (Don’t feel bad if you missed it. If Galileo could
have buried his meaning so deeply, his heresy might have been lost on the
bishops.) “Since the broad definition16
[of mental disorder is] almost impossible to test,” he said, “most of our
efforts will focus on the individual diagnostic criteria and dimensional
measurements that permit better assessment of the thresholds between normal and
pathological states.” The DSM-5 was going to abandon the attempt to define
mental illness or to derive clinical significance by proxy measures like
treatment seeking. Instead, it would work to overcome “one of the clearest
limitations of our current diagnostic criteria . . . the lack of quantitative
measures.” It would provide the means to “set diagnostic thresholds for
disorders.” Indeed, it would require clinicians to do so
by administering tests that would assess the severity of the disorder, as well
as the presence of symptoms—anxiety, sadness, obsessiveness, and so on—that
might not fit the diagnosis but were nonetheless relevant to treatment.
Numbers, not words, were going to guard the gates to the land of mental
illness.
• • •
Not every psychiatrist
believes it’s necessary to keep such a tight watch on those gates. Roger Peele,
APA trustee and DSM-5 task force member, for example, acknowledged that the “DSM-IV has a label for everyone you might want
to treat17.” But, he added, “ENTs [ear, nose,
and throat doctors] don’t worry about the fact that everyone is going to have a
cold.” Peele wished the “APA would get over their hang-up” and stop trying so
hard to “avoid implying that everyone has had or will have a mental illness.”
Peele is eighty years old. He’s tall and
handsome and has a sure, long stride and a regal bearing. He’s wearing an ascot
tucked into an open-collar shirt that matches his blue eyes. But maybe it’s his
low-cut, old-school sneakers, or his humble office with its government-issue
furniture and less-than-commanding views of the Rockville, Maryland, strip
malls, or the fact that he works for a county government, but somehow his
suggestion that the APA’s nosological restraint is a neurotic symptom doesn’t
seem designed to enhance his power or give the APA permission to unleash its id
in unrestrained pursuit of financial satisfaction. Rather, it seems in service of
the truth, at least as he sees it: that we all suffer psychological setbacks,
that we could all at some point benefit from some time spent with a
headshrinker, that the DSM-IV’s universal appeal, and its implicit provision
for universal treatment (at least for the insured), are good for all of us,
doctor and patient alike.
On the other hand, Peele ran for APA
president in 2000 and 2009 and lost. The organization might not be ready for
this kind of candor or to give up once and for all on the quest for a way to
distinguish the sick from the merely suffering.
Darrel Regier certainly isn’t. “That’s the
problem I went into the field to address,” he told me at the outset of our
interview. To a numbers guy like Regier, concern over the findings of the
Midtown Manhattan Study—the infamous 85 percent—is no mere hang-up. The result
is a statistical impossibility. We can’t all be abnormal any more than everyone
who lives in Lake Wobegon can be above average. And if most of those people
never seek treatment, then how sick could they be? Moreover, as Regier likes to
point out when people accuse the APA of disease mongering, there is no way that
the current mental health treatment system, with its 45,000 psychiatrists and
half a million psychologists, social workers, and counselors could possibly
keep up with all that demand. Bad as it is that the numbers are likely
inaccurate, it would be worse if they were not, because then we would truly be
awash in mental illness, our treatment resources swamped.
Regier, a lifelong public health doctor,
has to think about planning and policies and other unglamorous concerns that
cannot be met without knowing how many people are sick and what diseases they
have. That’s reason enough to devote a career to finding the elusive threshold,
or so it seemed when I asked him to tell me exactly what the problem was with
overdiagnosis. I wondered how an elite psychiatrist viewed the question,
exactly what kind of harm he thought his profession could cause by labeling us.
I wanted to know if he thought that a doctor who tells a widower that his grief
is an illness is potentially not only labeling, stigmatizing, and medicating
him, but also shaping the patient’s understanding of his loss, of himself, of
the meaning of his life.
But Regier didn’t seem to comprehend my
question. He seemed to think I wanted him to explain what false
positive meant. He might not be the philosophical sort or, after a
lifetime of cultivating bureaucratic habits, he might have lost sight of
philosophy. He might have only wanted to not get so far away from his talking
points with me. Or maybe he thought the answer was self-evident: sky-high
prevalence rates are an affront to reason, to everything that scientific
medicine, with its aspiration to carve nature at its joints, stands for.
Jay Scully was not so reticent.
We went through the usual reasons that
psychiatrists give when they worry about the overdiagnosis problem:
overtreatment, stigmatization, the credibility of the profession. But I wanted
more from him. I wanted him to tell me why, from a psychiatrist’s point of
view, it was a bad thing to, as he had just put it, “overpathologize the human
experience.”
“Because it limits the other potential
ways to fix things. It limits the whole spectrum of the human experience,” he said.
“I mean really bad things happen that are not necessarily psychopathological.
You’d have to be crazy to kill your family. Well, do you? Maybe not, but how do
we know? Where are the sharp dividing lines? Maybe we never really know.”
It was the first time in our half hour
together that Scully seemed genuinely interested, reflective, even spontaneous.
“So,” I asked him, “the false positive problem is the problem of where
psychiatry’s limits are?”
“Yes,” he said. “You know, we always need
to be humble.”
As I sat with the CEO of American
psychiatry, with his $600,000-per-year
salary18 and his large office with its
bird’s-eye view of the Potomac River and the Capitol, it was good to hear that
word. It was good to know he thought that humility was important and to have
heard him say, “Our treatment and ability to relieve suffering need work.” But
he got quickly back on message, and the PR flack was looking at her watch and
telling us our time was up, so I couldn’t ask him exactly what psychiatrists
need to be humble about—whether it’s only the gap between suffering and their
ability to relieve it, or if he was aware of that other, deeper chasm, the one
between opportunity and knowledge, the one that gives psychiatrists the power
to say what that dividing line is, and to cash in on saying it, even though
they themselves don’t really know. Still, I was glad to hear this much.
Because as Montesquieu once said, “The spirit of moderation19
is what we call virtue in an aristocracy. It supplies the place of the spirit
of equality in a popular state.” Perhaps medicine is inescapably an
aristocracy, and self-imposed moderation the only check on power, the only way
to prevent beneficence from becoming oppression. Surely medicine can’t be a
democracy; we can’t vote on whether or not we are sick or elect which illness
we have. If we can’t depend on definitions of mental disorder or on statistical
measures of clinical significance to prevent the DSM from cataloging the entire
spectrum of human experience, from turning all mental suffering into illness,
then perhaps we are dependent on the sophistication, the restraint, the
discretion—in short, the virtue—of our psychiatrists.
• • •
This is not a comforting
thought. And not only because of the Biedermans and the Schatzbergs and the
Nemeroffs out there, whose lack of restraint well exceeds the industry norm.
But even for psychiatrists who see no need to supplement their $200,000 annual
incomes with drug money, treatment options are deeply circumscribed—not only by
the imperfect state of knowledge described by Scully, but also by a for-profit
health care system that, with its focus on efficiencies, drives them inexorably
toward the drugs about which they have been carefully educated by the makers.
Because Darrel Regier may be the kind of
guy who would call his colleagues stupid in public and then complain that the
debate had gotten personal, but he has spent an entire career as a public
servant hacking away at one of the most daunting problems ever to come down the
pike. It is impossible to come away from a conversation with him without
believing that he really wants to solve that problem, and for a virtuous
reason: to fashion a treatment system that effectively and efficiently relieves
suffering. He wants a DSM that can help him and his colleagues to do this. He
may be hard to like, but he is not evil.
But he also doesn’t seem to understand the
spirit of moderation, or why it is incumbent upon an aristocrat to develop
it—at least not to judge from what he said at the end of his talk in
Copenhagen. Amid his circumlocutions and score settling, Regier had managed to
convey one fact: he intended the DSM-5 to move psychiatry decisively in the
direction of defining the thresholds of mental illness with numbers.
This alone was not news. But Regier was
well aware that people like Michael First and Allen Frances were wondering in
public how he could possibly pull this off, how he could, in the little time remaining,
create, debug, and standardize measures that would be sufficient to the task.
It was a question that made him even testier than usual, or at least it did
when I e-mailed him to ask it just a couple of months before he went to
Copenhagen. His proposal called for dimensional measures for every diagnosis, I
wrote, but in our interview he had mentioned only a small number of tests for a
few diagnoses and the information on the DSM-5 website was sketchy. Were there
more details that he could give me?
“They
[the dimensional measures] will continue to evolve20
over time,” he assured me. When I pressed him for more information, he wrote,
“I don’t think it will be useful to get into this level of detail on every
diagnostic severity measure that we will be considering prior to the
publication of DSM-5.” Still, he reiterated, even if they weren’t quite ready,
“these scales will be input for a final clinical judgment about the severity
level.” But Regier knew, and he knew that his colleagues in Copenhagen knew,
that with less than three years to go before publication, dimensional measures
were not going to evolve fast enough to be finalized for the DSM-5. Because he
was doubling down and staking the DSM-5’s claim to a new paradigm on them, he
had to explain himself—even if he still didn’t have the details.
Regier started by damning his predecessors
with faint praise. “It is most remarkable that the simple advance of having
some more reliable, explicit diagnostic criteria . . . has made it possible for
our research enterprise to advance as far as it has,” he said. But those same
checklists and categories had been an invitation to the much-lamented
reification of mental disorders. Spitzer and Frances had presented the criteria
as “essential components of an underlying pathophysiological and
psychopathological process.” No wonder they had been taken too seriously!
If only the DSM’s diagnostic categories
had been treated as hypotheses to be proved, rather than as diseases that had
been discovered, Regier seemed to be saying, then scientists would have been
free to validate them, to measure their severity and establish their
thresholds, to find out whether they were really discrete entities or if they
merged into one another on one or more spectrums of psychopathology. They
wouldn’t be saddled with diagnoses that didn’t map well onto clinical
experience or response to treatment or genetic research or molecular
neuroscience, and they wouldn’t be cleaning the egg off their faces as those
mismatches became evident or as those treatments failed.
Regier was not going to make the same
mistakes with DSM-5. His book would not try to freeze mental disorders in
amber, leaving a generation of scientists to regret its reifications and yet
have no choice but to use them. It wouldn’t bury the fact that, as Scully told
me, “the DSM will always be provisional” in disclaimers that no one would read.
Instead, Regier told his colleagues, they would be built right into the part of
the book to which everyone turned first: the categories and criteria. “Advances
. . . will only occur,” he said, “if the definitions and diagnostic criteria
for these disorders are constructed to facilitate their testing as scientific
hypotheses.” And once the new book comes out, “the syndrome categories and
quantitative thresholds can be tested.”
This is evidently what it meant to call
the DSM-5 a living document. If the process seemed chaotic, this was only the
inescapable ferment of innovation, and if the dimensional assessments weren’t
quite ready for prime time, or if some of the proposals seemed a little
sketchy, or if they ended up leading doctors to diagnose and treat patients who
weren’t really ill, then that was because they were only hypotheses. If it
turned out to be a mistake to, say, remove the bereavement exclusion or to
introduce Temper Dysregulation Disorder, or to propose a particular test to
measure the severity of a disorder, or to evaluate symptoms that don’t have
anything to do with a patient’s diagnosis, then the troublesome section of the
DSM-5 would be scrapped or revised in DSM-5.1. How this would affect patients
whose diagnoses came and went, and with them their treatments, their own
understanding of their troubles, and whatever identities their diagnoses had
bestowed upon them—on this subject Regier didn’t obfuscate. Neither did he
deflect the question with complaints about its unfairness. He just said nothing
at all.
Chapter 13
If Regier
was silent about the potential effects of diagnostic caprice, the patients were
not. By the end of the summer of 2010, more
than eight thousand comments1 had poured into
the DSM-5 website. According to the Psychiatric News,
10 percent of them expressed concern that the APA would drop Gender Identity
Disorder, and nearly a quarter implored the organization not to delete
Asperger’s syndrome in favor of an Autistic Spectrum Disorder that may or may
not include those currently diagnosed with Asperger’s. Four decades after homosexuals
demanded to be released from their diagnostic chains, groups of patients were
pleading with the APA not to set them free.
Regier promised readers more
details about the kvetchers, along with an official response, but in the
meantime, the News offered one explanation for their
complaints. Diagnoses, the paper wrote, provided “easy access to health
services” like hormone treatments and sex-change surgery and special education
programs, as well as therapy and medications.
People who have had to fight with
insurance companies or school systems might have disagreed with the “easy”
part, but then again, at least for the two thousand people who wrote in about
Asperger’s, money wasn’t the main thing on their mind. As APA president Carol
Bernstein wrote in the News, since they had been
diagnosed, these patients had “developed a
strong sense of uniqueness and belonging2.” They even, she
reported, had christened themselves “Aspies.” To delete the diagnosis might be
to “deprive them of their identity.” Even worse, Bernstein acknowledged, those
Asperger’s patients who were lucky enough to qualify for the new Autistic
Spectrum Disorder would suddenly have a diagnosis that would be “more
stigmatizing.”
The APA seemed caught off guard by the
fact that some people liked their diagnoses just fine. “While the work group
members conducted a thorough review of the existing data and research
literature,” Bernstein wrote, the fact that the diagnoses had bestowed an
identity on the patients had come as an “additional piece of evidence.”
It’s easy to see why the work group was
surprised. After forty years of fending off their antipsychiatric enemies,
after three decades of a diagnostic regime meant to reassure the public that
psychiatrists didn’t mean to exert control over people’s identities any more
than doctors parsing leukemia from lymphoma did, the APA had lost sight of what
was obvious to Asperger’s patients and transgendered people and to anyone who
has gotten diagnosed: that a psychiatric diagnosis is a judgment about more
than the way your organs are functioning. Once you start to think of your
troubles as a disease, your idea of yourself, which is to say who you are,
changes.
• • •
If anyone from the APA had
asked Nomi Kaim about this, they would have discovered not only that it was
true, but that it could be a really good thing.
Nomi is twenty-seven. Her wire-rim glasses
slip down her nose frequently. She moves her bulky body gingerly, as if she is
afraid she will knock something over as she leads me to her favorite spot in
the Boston bookstore where we have met. When she describes how much she once
disliked herself, it is easy to see why. Not because she is unlikable—indeed,
she seems sweet and considerate and acutely concerned for me, asking if my
chair is comfortable and our conversation nook quiet enough for my voice
recorder, whether my coffee is sufficiently hot—but because she was once
exactly the kind of girl whom children will taunt relentlessly: smart and
hyperarticulate, but overweight and ungainly and unfashionable, as untalented
of body as she is talented of mind.
“I
fought to get myself comfortable in high school3
and before that I fought to get myself comfortable at elementary school,” Nomi
told me. She saw therapists, took drugs for her depression and anxiety, and
finally, mercifully, graduated. She’d been accepted to Bryn Mawr but decided to
take time off before she went, hoping that maturity would grant her some more
social ease.
The college, she told me, “was exactly
what I wanted”—at least when it came to academics. “In classes, I was where I
belonged and I felt very fulfilled. But then I had to go back to the
dormitory.” In the dorm, in the dining room, out on the campus, she felt out of
place, overwhelmed by the noise and commotion of a couple thousand students,
their loud music and their drinking, their impenetrable cliques. “I hated the
whole campus life,” she said.
This time around, though, “the fight
didn’t feel worth it. I was tired of that.” She went to the student health
service and the doctors arranged for her to move into the school’s infirmary,
where she lived out her first semester, attending classes but avoiding the
parties and the friendships and even the dining hall. When she returned home
for her winter break, she pondered her options. “I chose not to go back and
fight some more.”
Going to college had always been Nomi’s
plan. “I had only had one path in my head and it was Bryn Mawr,” she told me.
“I didn’t have any other picture of what to do. So I got very depressed.”
Her parents placed her in McLean Hospital,
a mental hospital associated with Harvard. There she was treated for depression
and anxiety with drugs and cognitive-behavioral therapy. She also took part in
therapy groups, but the intense contact with her fellow patients traumatized
her. “I was just so emotionally flooded and didn’t know what to do with it,”
she said. “I would ask to be excused and take a break and the therapists would
say, ‘I want you to try to stay with it.’ They didn’t really get what was going
on, either.”
What was going on didn’t become clear
until Nomi’s mother, sure that Nomi’s lifelong struggles to negotiate the
social world were the cause, not the effect, of her mood and anxiety disorders,
arranged for her to be tested by a neuropsychologist at McLean. For two days
Nomi answered questions and filled out forms and drew figures and solved
puzzles. At the end, the psychologist told Nomi she had Asperger’s syndrome.
Nomi’s mother was glad to finally have an
explanation for her daughter’s troubles. “She said, ‘Well, now we know. Thank
God.’”
But not Nomi. “I was like, ‘That’s not
what I was looking for. I don’t agree with this.’ I mean, it was just so not
what I wanted.” Bad enough that “it sounded like ass burger,” she said; she
could only imagine what a bully would do with that name. Even worse, the
diagnosis seemed like a pronouncement on the one capacity of which she’d always
been most sure: her intelligence. No matter how much the doctors reassured her
that Asperger’s had nothing to do with her intelligence, still it seemed
obvious that “I had this cluster of selective stupidity—social stupidity and
practical stupidity,” she said. “And stupid was always the biggest insult for
me. Kids use it as a weapon. It’s something I’ve always feared.”
But that wasn’t the worst of it. “All
along, I’d been thinking my problems with feeling stupid were connected to
mental illness,” Nomi recalled. “I was hoping it was a mental illness.” With
mental illness, “there’s always this hope that if I can just conquer this, I’ll
become normal. But nobody talks about conquering Asperger’s. The diagnosis
undid all those hopes.”
That was before Nomi’s mother persuaded
her to join the Asperger’s Association of New England (AANE), an advocacy group
located just outside Boston. It took her a while to figure out that there was a
difference between AANE and McLean Hospital. They weren’t going to make her
stay in the groups if she felt overwhelmed, for instance. They weren’t going to
make her go to groups at all or ridicule her for her peculiarities or force her
to try to fit in. Everyone at AANE had the same kind of troubles, or at least
understood what those troubles were. (Many of the group’s leaders and staff are
parents of children with Asperger’s.) Her diagnosis was not a cause for
exclusion, but a key into a world where, for the first time in her life, she
didn’t have to fight to feel welcome.
Nomi thrived at AANE, volunteering in the
office and becoming a mainstay of its speakers’ bureau. Before we met, I had
watched her lead a workshop designed to help people with Asperger’s figure out
how to live independently. She was a dynamic speaker, reassuring and
sympathetic by turns, as she described the way she had learned to organize her
life, to maintain a schedule, to stay in touch with family. She gave pointers
on how to get disability status from Social Security, to find an affordable
apartment, to go to school—all of which she had done after receiving her
diagnosis.
Now she’s telling me about a benefit she
did not mention in her talk: the way the Asperger’s label changed her sense of
herself. “Spending time in an environment where the diagnosis is embraced as a
difference, I started to see my diagnosis differently.” The fact that it wasn’t
a “mental illness,” at least not by her definition, had become good news, a
“gift” even. There were advantages to not being neurotypical,
as people with Asperger’s sometimes describe the rest of us.
“There are certain things that
neurotypical women in particular are obsessed with, shoes and clothes and
makeup, that I’m very glad I’m not,” she said, adding that it isn’t just the
girly preoccupations she was pleased to be relieved of. “In general, I’m very
content with being completely outside of the popular culture fray.” Her
diagnosis had helped her to do what is demanded of all of us but comes easier
to some than others: to build a self out of the raw materials of nature and
nurture.
“If I had to give up my Asperger’s,” says
Nomi, “that would be hard.”
• • •
Nomi—like everyone thought to
have Asperger’s—almost didn’t have a diagnosis to lose. Asperger’s syndrome
didn’t exist until 1994, at least not officially, and even then it came close
to not making it into the DSM-IV. “It was a
total add-on4,” said Fred Volkmar, the Yale
psychiatrist who spearheaded the move to include it in the manual.
Less than twenty years ago, Asperger’s was
not familiar to most American psychiatrists—or to anyone else for that matter. The disorder was first described by an Austrian
pediatrician5, Hans Asperger, in a 1944 paper
outlining a cluster of symptoms that he had observed in some of his patients,
mostly boys: abnormal, often pedantic speech; physical clumsiness; difficulty
understanding gestures and other nonverbal communication; impaired social
interaction; and inflexible interests, often in one narrow subject, such as
train timetables. He called the syndrome autistischen
Psychopathen, or autistic psychopathy.
Asperger’s work languished in an academic
netherworld, his paper untranslated and mostly unknown until 1981. But then
Lorna Wing, a British psychiatrist who had encountered Asperger’s work as part
of her quest to understand her own daughter’s autism, wrote up thirty-four
cases that she thought met Asperger’s description. They weren’t exact matches.
Some were adults (the oldest was thirty-five), and many of them, contrary to
what Asperger had described, had walked before they talked. And while Asperger
wrote that his patients had “an especially
intimate relationship6 with language and highly
sophisticated linguistic skills,” and were in general more creative (at least
in their field of specific interest) and smarter than most people, Wing didn’t
think her patients were all that sophisticated or creative or intelligent.
Their language “gives the impression of being learned by rote,” she noted, and
“their thought processes are confined to a narrow, pedantic, literal, but
logical chain of reasoning.” They may have used big words, but they didn’t
necessarily understand what they meant. They may have been able to tell you the
make and model and number of every locomotive on the tracks, but that didn’t
mean they understood what a train was for. They may have been smarter than the
average kid, but, she said, they were “conspicuously lacking in common sense.”
Still, however, Wing thought she had only
refined Asperger’s observations. Her patients and his belonged in the same
category, and there seemed to be enough patients who fit the description to
warrant further investigation. Among the questions that Wing thought needed to
be answered was how patients like hers were related to another group of
socially unsuccessful children who had been described by another Austrian
doctor. His name was Leo Kanner, and in 1924 he had emigrated to the South
Dakota hinterlands, where he got a job as an assistant psychiatrist in an asylum.
From there, he worked his way to Johns Hopkins, where he started the country’s
first dedicated child psychiatry unit. In 1943, just a year before Asperger’s
paper came out, he published an article describing children much more severely
impaired than Asperger’s—unable to talk, mentally retarded, prone to rocking
and other repetitive activities, and distressed when their rituals were
disrupted. But like Asperger’s patients, Kanner’s were hard-pressed to
negotiate the world of others, and he, too, called these patients autistic.
The two doctors were probably unaware of
each other, at least at the beginning. They likely both borrowed the term from
the same source: Eugen Bleuler, a Swiss psychiatrist who drew on the Greek root
for self to describe the imperviousness to the outside
world characteristic of schizophrenia. (This was the label most likely to be
applied to Kanner’s patients.) But Kanner’s definition, perhaps because it
described a much larger group (or maybe because he wrote in English), prevailed,
and by the time Wing wrote her paper, it had become the industry standard. The
Infantile Autism that made its way into the DSM-III was much more like Kanner’s
description than like Asperger’s: a “pervasive
lack of responsiveness7 to other people,” “gross deficits
in language development,” and “bizarre responses to various aspects of the
environment.”
On balance, Wing concluded, “the syndromes are more alike than unalike8.”
Both comprised impairments in three dimensions: language, interaction, and
play. But where Kanner’s kids tended to be unable to talk, withdrawn from or
even unaware of the social world, and absorbed in repetitive activities such as
rocking, Asperger’s tended to be plenty talkative and engaged with the outside
world, but in a strange and inept way. Like awkward teens at a prom, they
wanted to dance, they even selected a partner, but they just didn’t know how to
do the steps. This cluelessness, Wing suggested, was only a milder form of the
deficits that characterized Kanner’s autism.
But, Wing said, this didn’t mean that
Asperger’s syndrome should go unrecognized. A child who talks endlessly about
the interstate highway system and nothing else, whose striving to attract
people only drives them away, who is tone deaf to the music of human
interaction and yet wishes to sing along: this is not someone who should be
overlooked or simply dismissed as a little bit eccentric, especially not when
there are a lot of such children. For them, Wing wrote, “the term is helpful9.”
It can be used with parents and teachers and bosses “who often cannot believe
in a diagnosis of autism, which they equate with muteness and total social
withdrawal.” It can “help to convince the people concerned that there is a real
problem . . . needing careful management and education.” Even if Asperger’s was
only a high-functioning variant of autism, Wing suggested, and even if it was,
strictly speaking, not a separate disorder, still it
deserved its own label.
The argument that pragmatics should trump
principle proved persuasive to the psychiatrists fashioning the International
Classification of Diseases. When the ICD-10 came out in 1992, it included
Asperger’s syndrome among the pervasive developmental disorders. This forced
the APA’s hand: to achieve the goal of harmonization with the ICD, the DSM-IV
task force had to at least consider Asperger’s for inclusion. “We knew the
question was there,” said Volkmar, “so we were going to look.”
Seventeen years later Volkmar now heads
the Child Study Center at Yale. He’s a friendly man with a gentle voice and a
brushy moustache on a jolly rubber face that makes people of a certain age
remember Captain Kangaroo. He’s wearing two pairs of glasses—one on his nose,
one on his pate at the ready for reading. It’s not clear if he does this for
efficiency’s sake, or just so he won’t lose track of their whereabouts.
Volkmar says he started out uncertain
about Asperger’s. “I had seen a couple of cases that corresponded with the
description, but I was not pro or con,” he told me. A literature review and a
meta-analysis carried the diagnosis across the bar Frances and Pincus had
erected, and the next step was to draft criteria and try them out in field
trials. Volkmar recruited 125 clinicians at five sites. They started with
patients who seemed likely to get an autism diagnosis and sorted them according
to the proposed criteria. Of the nearly one
thousand subjects10 tested, fifty-one turned out to
qualify for the Asperger’s diagnosis.
“This was totally unanticipated on my
part,” says Volkmar. But, especially because each diagnosis was confirmed by a
second rater, the unexpectedly high number convinced him that it was possible
to tell these kids apart reliably—or, in other words, that they were suffering
from something distinct from Pervasive Developmental Disorder NOS and Infantile
Autism, the labels that would most likely be applied. Even if it was possible
that this was only another line in the sand, the statistics were there to prove
that it could be drawn accurately and that these kids needed their own section
of the beach. Volkmar pushed for Asperger’s to be anointed as an official
disorder.
Volkmar had to fight for his proposal. He
had to overcome the DSM-IV conservatism, which he describes, only half joking,
as a “tendency [among work group members] to be on the autism spectrum and not
like change.” As he put it, “the APA would like not to even have a child
section, so they weren’t eager to make it bigger by even one diagnosis.” He had
to flog his evidence—fifty-one cases may have been “the biggest sample that
anyone since Asperger had ever pulled together,” but it was still a small
number. He kept hearing that it would be consigned to the Appendix, or, as he
calls it, the “elephant burial ground,” and he kept pushing for it to be spared
that fate.
There was one last obstacle—one that had
nothing to do with the evidence, and of which he was unaware until “someone
took me aside and explained”: the name of the proposed disorder. The APA was
opposed to eponyms, favoring instead plain descriptive language, and this
particular name presented a thorny problem. “There were rumors that Asperger
had been a Nazi,” Volkmar said. People were wary of a diagnosis named for (and
first proposed by) a man who sorted children in Nazi Germany according to their
pathologies.
Volkmar called Lorna Wing. “Oh my God,
no,” she told him. “He was a religious man.” The reassurance was only
secondhand, and it didn’t entirely make sense, but when he passed it along, the
worries about the name were forgotten. Asperger’s syndrome was one of only two
entirely new diagnoses—out of ninety-four that were proposed for DSM-IV—to make
the cut.
• • •
Six years later, in June
2000, The New York Times Magazine ran “The Little Professor Syndrome11,”
a long feature by Lawrence Osborne about Asperger’s syndrome. Experts described
the symptoms. A school director told Osborne that “they simply don’t understand
social games.” A parent called them “perfect counterfeit bills,” convincing
facsimiles of normal children until they tried to engage others. Fred Volkmar
weighed in, saying that “their social interactions are a disaster.”
But Osborne had some good news to report.
Although, as the school director said, “everything has to be taught to them,”
it was proving possible to do that. In classrooms, support groups, and doctors’
offices, Asperger’s patients were learning how to negotiate the neurotypical
world. A teacher demonstrated how her students had memorized facial expressions
so they could read other people’s signals. With techniques like this, according
to Osborne, “Asperger’s children can at least learn to imitate social behavior
that other kids learn intuitively.” Like Frankenstein’s monster observing human
life through a window, they were forced to watch the rest of us from a
distance. But unlike the monster, and as Hans Asperger had predicted, they
could learn how to approximate what normal people do.
One of Osborne’s readers was Barbara
Wiechmann, a Brooklyn office manager and playwright. She’d been worried about
her son, who was then four, for at least two years. He’d been slow to talk and
walk, and, even for his age, seemed terribly clumsy. He didn’t exactly play
with his toys. He arranged them instead, sorting rather than manipulating them
in imaginative scenarios. He lined up his blocks neatly on his windowsill,
arranged by color, and stacked dog food cans into a neat, perfect pyramid. For
bedtime reading, he rejected Goodnight Moon or any of
the other standbys, insisting instead on the Smithsonian’s field guide to
mushrooms, which he’d memorized by the time he was four.
Wiechmann showed Osborne’s article to her
husband, Michael Carley, and told him she thought their son was one of the
little professors. Carley wasn’t so sure. “Some
things made sense12, others didn’t,” he said. But he
agreed to have their son tested and continued to read up on the subject. Before
the appointment, he went to Cabo San Lucas for a quick surfing vacation from
his job with an NGO that was implementing a United Nations drinking water
development project in Iraq. “I . . . have
yet to stand successfully13 on a surfboard,” Carley later
wrote in a memoir, “but I’ve never cared. Water is the only arena where I have
felt physically graceful.”
His ungainliness wasn’t the only
limitation Carley was aware of on his trip. After a day of not surfing, he
stopped in at a disco. He’s no more a dancer than a surfer, and in the crowd of
tourists, he wrote later, he felt “like a ghost that no one saw.” That feeling
was familiar enough, but, in the light of what he’d learned about Asperger’s
since he read the New York Times Magazine
article, it took on a new meaning.
As I watched the
dictionaries of nonverbal communication flowing back and forth, I was hit
fully, finally, that what separated me from them wasn’t cultural. It never had
been. It wasn’t intellectual. It never had been. It was bigger than that.
At that
moment, one month before the confirmation of a formal diagnosis, I knew.
Staring into that sea of abandon . . . I knew. I realized I had Asperger’s
syndrome.
A month after his return, and a week after
his son received his diagnosis, Carley’s psychiatrist confirmed his revelation.
With the official diagnosis came relief. “It meant I’m not an asshole. I’m just
wired differently,” he says. “This is just how I process thoughts and
experiences and emotions.”
Carley is sitting with his legs crossed
under him on the bare wood floor of his sparsely furnished living room,
free-associating about his nineteen-year-old single mother, his father who was
killed in Vietnam, his “crazy dumb” gallivanting youth, his misadventures with
cops on different continents, and the people he’s met along the way, who, he
says, have been evenly divided on whether he’s a “tell-it-like-it-is guy” or a
jerk. He talks fast, snapping his fingers for emphasis, and it’s easy to
believe he had once wanted to be a playwright. He sure has a flair for drama.
That’s a skill Carley has put to a
different use since he got his diagnosis. Shortly after his visit with the
psychiatrist, he took over a loose network of Asperger’s support groups in New
York, and in 2003, he used his NGO savvy and his forceful personality to wangle
money from the Fund for Social Change and turn the network into GRASP, the
Global and Regional Asperger Syndrome Partnership, the largest organization for
adolescents and adults with Asperger’s. Like AANE, Nomi Kaim’s group, GRASP
works to provide patients and their families with information and resources.
But Carley has a larger agenda, captured in GRASP’s mission statement.
At GRASP we envision a world14 where all
individuals on the autism spectrum are respected, valued, and fairly
represented; where appropriate supports and services are readily available to
those in need; and where people on the spectrum are empowered to participate in
policy and personal decisions that affect their lives.
Asperger’s syndrome,
according to Carley, isn’t just a diagnostic label or a psychiatric disorder.
It is a fundamental part of identity, not unlike race or sexual orientation.
His is a civil rights crusade, a quest for cognitive pluralism.
Carley often slips into the language of
identity politics as he describes his odyssey from getting his diagnosis to
attending his first support group to becoming leader of GRASP. “Knowing that I
had the same genes running through my veins as they did,” he says, remembering
the first groups, “gave me the guts to open up and share that experience. And
what’s the response? A room full of people saying, ‘I’ve been there, too.’
That’s biblical.”
As important as that experience was to
him, his mission now is to make it unnecessary for others to go through it.
“This is about us creating a more diverse atmosphere,” he told me. “Eventually,
Asperger’s and autism are going to be thought of as natural extensions of the
human condition and not illnesses. We won’t even need to separate them.”
That’s what GRASP is for. “We want to get
rid of the shame,” he says, “so we’ve made a very concerted effort to change
the iconography of Asperger’s”—from an affliction to a gift. And, he thinks,
the proposal to eliminate the Asperger’s diagnosis in favor of a spectrum
disorder is an opportunity to extend what Asperger’s patients have secured for
themselves to the rest of the autism spectrum—including those much more
severely impaired than he. This is an adventure he is eager to undertake, which
is why he, along with about half the members of GRASP, is in favor of the
change.
“I’m going to butt in here,” says his son,
who has been sitting quietly beside me on the couch. He’s wearing a Minnesota
Twins baseball cap, although he swears he’s a Red Sox fan. He has his father’s
squat nose and downturned eyes as well as his diagnosis, but right now he wants
to tell me about a way in which they are really not the same kind of person at
all. “I’m sorry, but the way we’ve taken Asperger’s has been very different.”
Like many fifteen-year-olds, the younger
Carley finds his father’s passions embarrassing. When his friends ask what his
father does, he says, “I don’t want to be, like, ‘He works with Asperger’s.’”
He looks at his father across the room. “I want the answer to be something like
your old UN job.” He tells his father how mortifying it was when Carley took
his son’s school principal to task over her policy of not disclosing students’
diagnoses. “I don’t want to be affiliated with it,” he says. “I’m running
around with my friends. I don’t want to bring up that subject.” He turns to me.
“It’s something for home. It’s something for me and my dad.” That, he explains,
is why he wants me to call him CC instead of his real name.
Not that the diagnosis hadn’t helped CC.
“If I didn’t have a diagnosis, I’d be totally clueless,” he says. He went to
special schools; hung out with fellow Aspies; even had a little counseling; and
learned, as his father likes to put it, to play the cards he was dealt.
“In seventh grade, I got the worst grades
possible, and I was off the charts in eighth grade”—because, he says, his
diagnosis gave him a motive for trying harder. “I have this thing on my
back—Asperger’s syndrome. It’s like getting a high score on a video game. Like,
let’s see how high I can go.”
But that’s all behind him now, CC says.
His problems have been “ironed out.” He is in a mainstream school, where his
friends don’t know about his diagnosis. His Asperger’s is in the background—a
“huge achievement,” he tells me—and he wants to keep it there.
CC turns back to his father. “I know you
hate this, and I would love it if everyone would accept it. But you know there
are idiots in this world. They don’t look at how other people think. They don’t
acknowledge any evidence. They just put it down.”
And this, he thinks, is only going to get
worse if the diagnosis disappears in the DSM-5, and kids like him are suddenly
considered autistic. “When you hear the word autism,
you think of institutionalization, speech delay, diapers. It’s a scary word,”
he says. “It’s going to make me want to be even more concealed.” CC turns to
me. “Would you rather say you have Asperger’s or
autism?”
The difference between father and son may
only reflect a difference in their temperaments, whatever their similarities
when it comes to Asperger’s. On the other hand, Michael knows what it is like
to live without an explanation and the acceptance that comes with it, while CC
doesn’t remember a time when he didn’t have the diagnosis. The disorder is so
thoroughly intertwined with his sense of who he is that it is invisible to him.
He has the luxury to forget about it, to carry on as if it weren’t there. He
can see that he and others could lose this freedom if the DSM-5 proposal goes
through, but he also doesn’t want to take to the streets to fight about it.
Their argument reminds me of the clash
between young women and their feminist mothers, the kids cringing at their
parents’ stridency, the grown-ups appalled by their children’s complacency (and
their ingratitude). It’s an argument Hans Asperger, writing in a time and place
perilous to people singled out for their pathology, probably wouldn’t have
dreamt of when he noted how many of his child patients had fathers just like
them. It’s surely not an outcome that the DSM-IV experts would have predicted:
that their diagnosis would go far beyond facilitating services, that it would
create a whole new brand of identity politics, and that a strange little boy
who might have foundered on the same shoals that once snared Nomi Kaim would
grow into this impressive, articulate, self-possessed teenage boy.
But, as Fred Volkmar says, when it comes
to new psychiatric diagnoses, “one can always be surprised at the outcome.”
• • •
Not all the surprises were
political. Some were statistical. “You never know what is going to take off and
what isn’t,” Volkmar told me, but it wasn’t long before Asperger’s took off
like no other psychiatric disorder ever had, at least not since hysteria had
swept across the salons of Europe in the time of Freud.
When Lorna Wing wrote her paper on
Asperger’s in 1981, figures on the prevalence of autism were scant. She ballparked it15
at about 4 or 5 per 10,000, and guessed that maybe half of those were the kind
of patient described by Asperger. When Volkmar’s team conducted their field
trials, there were no better statistics for Asperger’s because, of course, the
disorder didn’t yet exist to be counted. But even if Volkmar’s group was
impressed enough by those fifty-one cases to push for inclusion, and even if
they knew that adding Asperger’s would likely add patients to the sick rolls,
they certainly didn’t think they’d stumbled on an epidemic. At best, they had
identified a small if significant number of cases that could be carved out of
another small number.
So imagine their (and everyone else’s)
surprise when Eric Fombonne, an
epidemiologist working in England, reviewed16 twenty-three
surveys of autism prevalence conducted between 1966 and 1999, and concluded
that the rates were on the rise. Estimates varied wildly—from 0.7 percent in a
1970 study to 21 percent in 1996, but one factor alone seemed to affect the
overall trend. Prior to 1989, the average study turned up 4.3 cases in 10,000
people; after that year, the rate was 7.2 in 10,000. Even accounting for all
other factors—age, gender, severity, IQ, and so on—the relationship between
year of study and rate of autism was statistically significant. Time alone, in
other words, was making autism rates rise—and not, so the epidemiologists said,
simply because the clock was ticking or because there was what Fombonne called
a “secular increase17
in the incidence of the disorder.” Instead, he thought, the increase was the
result of “improved recognition and detection . . . together with a broadening
of the diagnostic concept and definitions.”
People like Volkmar might have thought the
territory they had established with the Asperger’s diagnosis was sparsely
populated, but epidemiologists were reaching a different conclusion. Using the
DSM-IV criteria, one group reviewed the medical and educational records of
schoolchildren in Atlanta and turned up a
rate of 34 per 10,00018, a tenfold increase over the few
comparable studies that had been conducted in the United States.
Fombonne, in an editorial accompanying the
Atlanta study, speculated that even these
results were “an underestimate19.” And subsequent
studies proved him right. As of 2002, the
CDC reported20, 1 in 150 children had an autistic
spectrum disorder, a rate that by 2006 had reached 1 in 110, or just over 90
per 10,000. It was around this time that Lorna Wing started referring to the
publication of her original paper as “opening
Pandora’s Box21.”
The numbers just kept going up. By 2008,
the CDC said, the rate was 1 in 88, and in May 2011, researchers writing in the
American Journal of Psychiatry announced they had
found a prevalence rate in a city in Korea22
of 2.64 percent. For those of you keeping score, that’s 264 per 10,000—and 374
for every 10,000 boys—a greater than fiftyfold increase since 1981.
And people were keeping score—including
the people at Autism Speaks. “The world’s largest autism science and advocacy
organization,” according to its website, it sponsored the Korean study and,
soon after its publication, blitzed the
media23 with the claim that 1 in 38
children was autistic. This, the group said, indicated “the need for improved and wider autism
screening24 among the general population”—a
move that, to judge from the last twenty years, could only increase prevalence
rates, and with them public attention, sympathy, and, of course, money for
their cause.
Opinions varied on what was causing this
increase. To those who held mercury-based preservatives in common childhood
vaccines responsible, the increasing rates were further proof that vaccination
policies were ruining kids’ brains. Most explanations, however, focused on the
old and elusive question of whether epidemiologists were getting better at
detecting a disease that was already there, or if they were charting the rise
of an epidemic.
But the researchers in the Korean study
offered an interesting alternative explanation. They noted that only 63 percent
of the people they had solicited had agreed to participate in the study—a
disappointingly low number, far lower than the 80 percent considered optimal,
and often achieved, in community surveys. But, they argued, if you consider the
tendency among Koreans to think of autism as “a
stigmatizing hereditary disorder25” that “impugns
the child’s lineage on both sides and threatens the marriage prospects of
unaffected relatives,” then this level of participation seems not so bad. In
fact, it’s remarkable: something had inspired nearly two-thirds of the parents
in a Korean city to risk having their families marked as members of a defective
gene pool.
The researchers focused their speculation
on Korea’s “highly structured” educational system, with its emphasis on
“behavioral regulation” in twelve-hour-long classes that meet six days a week.
Some children’s problems would be impossible to conceal in such a setting, but
“for quiet, high functioning children with ASDs,” they wrote, “this environment
may reduce the likelihood of referrals to special education programs.” Still,
even if they remained invisible at school, these children’s problems might have
been obvious at home, and the survey “may have provided welcome opportunities”
for parents caught between their concern for their kids and their fears for
their families’ reputation to get information and maybe even treatment. “It
could be argued that in this cultural context,” the researchers wrote, “parents
of children with serious but unrecognized developmental problems would be more
likely to participate in research than parents of unaffected children.”
This wasn’t the first time a researcher
attributed increasing prevalence to motivated parents seizing an opportunity.
The Atlanta study’s authors had been disturbed by a finding that the likelihood
that a child would qualify for a diagnosis increased with age—but only until
they got to the oldest group of children, who were nine and ten. Did this mean
that younger children were developing autistic disorders at an increasing rate?
Had they found the leading edge of the epidemic?
The scientists didn’t think so. “Lower rates in 9- and 10-year-olds26
may reflect the use of narrower diagnostic criteria for autism before the
publication of DSM-IV,” they wrote, “and the increased availability of
educational, health and social services for children with autism.” Perhaps the
older children hadn’t escaped an epidemic, but rather had been born too late to
benefit from the DSM-IV’s relaxed criteria and their intersection with the 1991
mandate issued by the U.S. Department of Education to provide special education
services to children with autistic disorders. This, the researchers allowed,
was “possibly leading to increases in the number of children classified with
autism because of the availability of services.”
“Diagnosis
of ASDs27 [autistic spectrum disorders] is
an uncertain art,” wrote autism expert Tony Charman in an editorial
accompanying the Korean study, “and in the end one has to make a clinical
judgment of whether the number, quality, severity, and accompanying impairment
of symptoms are sufficient to fulfill DSM criteria.” As in any diagnosis, the
need for judgment about ASDs increases when the disorder is milder; a kid who
rocks in the corner and can’t talk is much easier to diagnose than someone like
Nomi or CC. But milder cases like theirs account for nearly two-thirds of the
diagnoses that make up the prevalence rates.
It’s no mystery why parents would seek out
a diagnosis, as Nomi’s and CC’s parents did—and, like them, to feel relief when
the doctor issues it. After all, it’s not as if parents have to be encouraged
to worry about how their children are faring socially, or to wonder if they will
ever learn to negotiate all the complex and unspoken rules of their little
societies, or to think that disaster awaits when they cannot. Even if they
haven’t read Lord of the Flies, parents know just how
brutal those politics are, and how ill suited some children are to them. In a
marketplace of worried parents searching for resources, a diagnosis like
Asperger’s syndrome is bound to be a hot commodity.
And really, how hard is it to sell people
on a disorder whose “symptoms” can bestow what Lawrence Osborne called
“extraordinary gifts”? Osborne wasn’t talking about special education dollars,
but about Glenn Gould and Vladimir Nabokov and Ludwig Wittgenstein, all
diagnosed—posthumously, of course—into a Hall of Fame that, depending on which
website you consult, also includes Isaac Newton, Emily Dickinson, and Albert
Einstein.
Even for those who will fall short of
greatness, the diagnosis has its appeal. And its charms are on the increase, at
least according to the Aspie who predicted to Osborne that “society will
actually become more and more dependent on people with Asperger’s to usher it
through the difficulties ahead.” That was more than a decade ago, and since
then, interaction has come to rely less and less on the nonverbal cues that
Aspies are so bad at decoding and more and more on the tablets and handhelds,
the binaries of emoticons and tweets, that they are more suited to. While the
neurotypical among us grow more and more bewildered by the barrage of
information fed to us by our devices, the burdens of Asperger’s, at least in
the view of some of the diagnosed, increasingly become a gift. Even for those
who think this is an ominous sign—like the novelist Jonathan Lethem, who
speculated that people with Asperger’s are “canaries
[who] sensed before anyone else28 that we’d
entered a coal mine”—the fit between disease and society is striking, the
temptation to claim the label obvious.
This may be the real surprise of the
Asperger’s outbreak: that it is neither a “secular increase” nor an artifact of
counting, but rather a supply-side epidemic. Unlike the childhood bipolar
outbreak, this one was not set off by a drug company and its shills, exploiting
loopholes in the DSM for profit. This one came right from the authors of the
book, who wanted nothing more than to help kids help themselves to social
resources. They had built a diagnosis, and the patients had come.
• • •
Volkmar thinks that the rush
to get Asperger’s into the DSM-IV might have had something to do with the
outcome. “Had we had a little more time, we would have been able to have a
better definition and criteria for Asperger’s,” he told me, which might have
made the diagnostic threshold a little harder to cross. But even so, Volkmar is
glad Asperger’s made the cut. “I don’t regret getting it in,” he said. “You
need to have a label to get services, and this is a population that needs
them.”
Michael First also thinks it was “premature to add Asperger’s29,
given the limited amount of data,” he told me. “You could argue that this was a
deviation from DSM-IV’s conservative approach.”
That’s an assessment with which Allen
Frances agrees. “We probably were premature30
in introducing Asperger’s,” he acknowledged. Childhood disorders, he said, were
outside his expertise. “Had a comparable situation arisen on the adult side, I
would have been more insistent on the strict application of the DSM-IV rules.”
It’s a lapse that he now regrets. “Had I been smart enough to predict that the
diagnosis would be made so loosely, that parents would panic and stop
vaccinating their kids, and that school services would be based just on the
presence or absence of the diagnosis, then I definitely would have insisted on
a stricter application of the rules.”
Regret over the Asperger’s diagnosis, or
at least over the way it had become ubiquitous, was one thing that Frances and
the DSM-5 leadership agreed on. David Kupfer told The New
York Times that the swelling ranks of Asperger’s patients were getting
to be a problem. “It involves a use of
treatment resources31,” he said. “It becomes a cost
issue.” You don’t want to reify your diagnoses, but on the other hand, if a
diagnosis is nothing more than a label that gets services . . . well, there is
such a thing as too much success, especially when resources are scarce, costs
are high, and public credibility is slipping.
The DSM-5 proposal sure looked like a way
to raise the bar for entry. DSM-IV’s Autistic Disorder had listed twelve
criteria under three main headings and required that patients meet only six of
them, with at least two coming from the first category and at least one each
from the remaining two; the Asperger’s diagnosis required two from Criterion
A’s four symptoms and one from the four listed under Criterion B. (One
math-minded psychiatrist calculated that there were 1,256 combinations of
symptoms that would meet the criteria.) DSM-5, on the other hand, required all
three Criterion A symptoms to be met and two of four in Criterion B. But even
if it seemed like a no-brainer that moving from a Chinese menu to prix fixe
would reduce the numbers of diagnoses, the APA insisted this was not the purpose
of the change. “The goal was not to change
prevalence32,” work group member Catherine Lord
told me. After all, gerrymandering a diagnosis to solve a public policy, or a
public relations, problem—that would be cheating.
Besides, Lord told me, “we think these
prevalence rates are accurate.” There was a problem with accuracy—not with the
numbers of diagnoses, but with what doctors meant when they rendered them. “We
want to make the criteria match up better with what clinicians are seeing when
they make the diagnosis,” she said. The problem with criteria that were too
vague and broad was not that doctors could use them too liberally—say, to make
sure a kid who was a little odd got special services in school. Rather, Lord
said, when they rendered their diagnoses, it wasn’t clear exactly what, if
anything, the criteria had to do with the conclusion. In fact, the most important factor in determining which
diagnosis33 a kid got, at least according to a
study Lord had conducted, was the hospital that did the evaluation. Doctors had
reverted to the old pre-DSM-III way: deciding which illness a patient had
through some combination of local custom and intuition, rather than by systematically
applying the criteria.
But only astute clinicians could be
trusted with this uncertain art. The rest of us—the parents who want their kids
to qualify, the geeks who want to inherit the earth from the neurotypicals, the
people who would prefer having a mental disorder over being a jerk—needed to
have their leash yanked. “People use ‘Asperger’s’ and ‘autism’ colloquially,”
Lord told me. Tightening the criteria would give the masses “who don’t know
much about autism less of a feeling that everyone who’s socially awkward has
autism.”
On the other hand, if those people want to
call themselves Aspies, that’s fine by Lord. “We’re not trying to take away
that identity,” she said. “It’s very helpful to some people. It’s just not a
medical diagnosis.” Still, it was clear that the APA could take away what it
had given—not the name, but the rights and privileges it had inadvertently
granted by enshrining Asperger’s in the DSM. And, evidently, when the diagnosis
got out of hand, that is exactly what it would do.
Lord reassured me that this wasn’t the
problem it seemed to be. First of all, she said, “people with Asperger’s
vacillate between wanting to describe themselves as having a disorder or not.”
So deleting the diagnosis would actually help people like Nomi Kaim and CC
Carley by providing the privileges without the burden and by removing the stink
of pathology from their identity. As for those privileges, kids in special
education have to get reevaluated every three years, so they are always at risk
of losing their diagnoses. Of course, generally that would be because their
condition has changed, not because it has disappeared from the DSM. But Lord
was quite certain that the only problem patients would face was having to move
from one diagnostic home to another. The overall prevalence rates, she said,
were very unlikely to come down.
That was a question that would have to
wait for field trials of the new diagnoses. But as the APA geared up for its
annual meeting in May 2011, it was becoming evident that the field trials were
in disarray, and even as their significance was increasing, they might not be
able to shed much light on questions like these—even to the very few people
from whom the results would not be kept a secret.
Chapter 14
In early
May 2011, the APA posted its revised draft of the DSM-5. Asperger’s syndrome
was still slated for removal, as was the bereavement exclusion. But Psychosis
Risk Syndrome (PRS) and Temper Dysregulation Disorder were gone. In their place
were two new diagnoses—Attenuated Psychosis Symptoms Syndrome (APSS) and
Disruptive Mood Dysregulation Disorder. The ingredients of the new disorders
were exactly the same as the old ones. Only the labels had changed.
The renaming strategy had its obvious
advantages. It got David Shaffer off the hook for suggesting a name that seemed
to medicalize ill temper, even as the criteria continued to medicalize
ill-tempered kids. It also allowed Will Carpenter to deflect attention from the
research showing that kids whose illness consisted of being on the verge of
psychosis rarely went on to get psychotic. On further consideration, he told
me, his work group had realized that PRS really wasn’t a “prevention concept”
at all, but rather “a diagnostic concept,” not an illness about to happen, but
one in progress right now.
That explanation raised the question of
why, if PRS was a disorder in its own right, the work group hadn’t proposed it
as a “diagnostic concept” in the first place. It also didn’t explain why,
according to the website, the rationale for introducing the diagnosis was that
“young people at risk for later manifestation of a psychotic disorder can be
identified,” or why APSS was still described as “a risk syndrome for
psychosis.” Perhaps the APA’s marketing department and editorial department
weren’t talking to each other.
“People
say, ‘What’s in a name1?’” Dilip Jeste, the future
president of the APA, told three hundred of his colleagues the week after the
changes were posted. “But it seems the name means a lot to lots of people.”
Jeste was talking about Mild Neurocognitive Disorder, a disorder once known as
Minor Neurocognitive Disorder. He explained that many people who wrote into the
website had complained to his neurocognitive disorders work group that minor was a “trivializing” word. “The people pointed out
that if you call something minor, insurance companies will not reimburse,” he
said.
Jeste wasn’t entirely happy with the
committee’s solution. “It really doesn’t make any sense,” he said. He wasn’t
talking about the way that the diagnosis, as he acknowledged a few sentences
later, is only an exaggerated version of the normal cognitive decline that sets
in after age fifty. But he pointed out that if there was going to be a Major
Neurocognitive Disorder, “it should be minor versus major, not mild.” He
solicited better suggestions from the audience. None was forthcoming.
But there is more than money in a name.
Neurocognitive Disorder, however you qualified it, was a reworking of a DSM-IV
label that was itself pretty tarnished, and getting more so as baby boomers
aged: Dementia. “It’s a pejorative term,” Jeste said, because it came from the
Greek for “losing one’s mind.” And no matter how much those of us over fifty
might grouse privately that we’re losing our minds along with our memories, we
really don’t want our doctors to agree with us, at least not officially, and
surely not on our permanent medical dossier, not while the problem is still
mild (or minor). Even in the later stages of Alzheimer’s, an undeniably major
cognitive disorder, dementia might carry too much
stigma, Jeste added. On the other hand, most people with major neurocognitive
disorders eventually did lose their minds. So the work group decided to name
the new diagnosis Major Neurocognitive Disorder (Dementia), and then, once the
DSM-5 came out, to “let the marketplace decide.”
That’s probably not how Darrel Regier
would have put it. He probably would have said, “Let the hypotheses be tested.”
Still, the relabeling tactics helped to fill in the blank Regier had left when
he didn’t get back to the Psychiatric News about the
fate of the public suggestions. The kvetchers had been turned into a focus
group, and, evidently, the diagnoses that didn’t meet with market approval
would be rebranded.
• • •
Jeste’s talk was part of the
APA’s 2011 annual meeting, held in Honolulu. “Attire
is ‘aloha business/casual2.’ No suits, ties or fancy dresses,”
the website proclaimed, and many of the ten thousand psychiatrists in the
soaring open-air atrium of the Hawaii Conference Center dutifully sported
muumuus and Hawaiian shirts. The theme of the convention was “Transforming
Mental Health Through Leadership, Discovery, and Collaboration,” but the APA
leadership had discovered the necessity of keeping their most prominent
collaborator at a distance. The conference’s printed program began with a
sixteen-page disclosure index in which every speaker divulged whether he or she
had taken remuneration from any drug companies (although not how much),
information that was repeated at the start of every talk.
Not that the organization thought ties to
the drug industry were really a problem anymore. “The APA has a management of
conflict process for all [educational] activities,” read the manual. “This
process ensures that all conflicts of interest are identified, managed, and
resolved prior to the educational activity.” Even so, disclosure before the
lecture remained important because an audience that knew “which relevant
financial relationships . . . were present and resolved” could assess “the
potential for bias” that might have somehow slipped past the conflict managers.
The disclosures weren’t the only way in
which the proceedings had been sanitized for our protection. There wasn’t a
Prozac pen or a Depakote dealy-bob or any other Pharma swag to be seen in the
lobbies or lecture rooms, sponsored lectures were not listed in the main
program, and overall industry funding of the meeting was less than $2 million,
down from its high in 2006 of more than $6 million. The drug companies had been
relegated to the basement exhibition hall, where they competed for the busy
psychiatrist’s attention with the mental hospitals and the booksellers and the
job recruiters and the shiny-faced men and women hawking neurofeedback gadgets
and even a “physical fitness” kiosk where doctors could sharpen their Wii golf
skills.
The APA’s attempt to clean up its act had
not persuaded its enemies to stand down. The Citizens Commission on Human Rights,
the Scientology cadre devoted to tormenting the APA, maintained a steady
presence on the curb outside the conference center, handing out flyers that
touted an exhibition—Psychiatry: An Industry of Death—it
was staging elsewhere in Honolulu. On the flyer’s other side was a rogue’s
gallery, complete with photos of Alan Schatzberg, Nada Stotland, Dilip Jeste,
David Kupfer, and other industry collaborators. The Honolulu police, when they
weren’t enforcing the jaywalking laws, made sure the protesters did not harass
the guests.
The opposition wasn’t all behind the
barricades. Psychiatrists outside the ten or so sessions related to the DSM
could be heard grumbling about rearranged deck chairs, and anyone who stumbled
into the “Clinicians’ Impressions of the DSM-5 Personality Disorders” symposium
would have heard psychologist Thomas Widiger excoriate the personality
disorders work group for courting ridicule and chaos by proposing to wipe out
in one stroke five of the DSM-IV’s ten personality disorders and, as if that
weren’t bad enough, “invent[ing] out of thin
air3” a model of personality pathology that ignored
decades of research and then, even more embarrassing, changing its mind
repeatedly about how many facets made up a personality and what exactly they
were and how they related to one another, before finally advancing a proposal
that inspired a virtual mutiny among personality researchers, which in turn
persuaded the task force to compel the work group to pull it from the website
in favor of a notice to check back later. And, Widiger lamented, even if the
particulars weren’t yet worked out and even if this was the stupidest idea to
come down the pike in a long time, maybe ever, still it was clear that nothing was
going to stop this juggernaut, that when the new version was posted it would be
just as bad as the old, thus proving, as Widiger put it, that “like with the
Borg, resistance is futile.”
But overall, the protest was nothing like
the chaos that had engulfed the meetings in the early 1970s, when gay activists
launched their fusillades against the homosexuality diagnosis, or at the end of
the decade, when Robert Spitzer and psychoanalysts squared off over the
DSM-III. Whatever dissent the DSM-5 might have been sowing scattered quickly in
the tropical breezes, which, combined with the Waikiki surf and the palm trees
and the dress code, made the open-air atrium feel more like the lobby at a
Jimmy Buffet concert than the site of trenchant debates about the nature of
human suffering.
If there was any sign of trouble in
Margaritaville, it was in the reminders, repeated by Regier and Kupfer at every
opportunity, that all was well. The two DSM leaders hadn’t gone the full aloha,
settling for open-necked Oxford shirts rather than floral prints on rayon, and
they seemed at least a little relaxed. But their stump speeches, with their
reminders of all that was wrong with the DSM-IV, their recital of the long
effort to fix it, and their reassurances that the revision was “very much on
target” for May 2013 had, like the APA’s protestations that it was Pharma-free,
more than a faint whiff of defensiveness, as if they felt some urgency to
bolster the confidence of the rank and file. Among the loyal, only David
Shaffer directly addressed the controversy, and then only fleetingly. “I do sense a reactionary element4
penetrating DSM-5,” he said, “and I hope it goes away.”
• • •
Allen Frances wasn’t in
Honolulu, but he hadn’t gone away. In the past few months, his blogs had
increasingly addressed the APA leadership directly, imploring them to change
course. Privately, he was sending e-mails directly to the few people inside he
thought might listen to him. But, at least to judge by his rising stridency and
the frustration creeping into his tone, he was pretty sure they weren’t
listening.
Michael First, however, didn’t have the
luxury of being retired. “I still have to work with these guys,” he said. “And
I’ll have to work with them after the DSM-5 comes out.” So he was there,
working to maintain what he described as “cordial” relations with Regier and
Kupfer and others in the DSM leadership as he continued in his role on the WHO
panel formulating the new ICD.
First isn’t exactly a firebrand by
temperament. Where Frances shoots from the hip and peppers his salvos with
literary and historical references, First sticks to data and the narrowest
possible understanding of whatever question is in front of him. Ask him about a
diagnostic controversy, and he’ll drill deeply into the research, the specifics
of which he will recall nearly perfectly, or he’ll go on about the fine points
of establishing reliability, or he will talk about the clinical utility of the
diagnosis. If the subject were baseball, he’d be talking about on-base
percentage versus run production, while Frances would be wondering if the
designated hitter rule violated the pastoral origins of the game and tracing
the origins of the question back to Thucydides.
As much as he has devoted his career to
all things DSM, First doesn’t think the book has as much social impact as
Frances thinks it does. “Allen and I have a
big disagreement5 about these epidemics he always
talks about,” he told me. “I tend to think he greatly overstates the role of
the DSM.” Take ADHD, for example, he said. Frances is sure that simplifying the
criteria led directly to the increase in diagnosis and prescription of
stimulants to kids. “I completely disagree that what we did in DSM-IV was
really responsible for the huge overdiagnosis and overuse of medication. There
are all these social factors, and all kinds of reasons why people use
diagnoses. The DSM is a very small component.”
But whatever disagreements First had with
either side, they weren’t going to be rehearsed at the annual meeting, at least
not in the scheduled sessions, which paid scant attention to the brewing
controversies. There was a place, however, where conceptual issues were in
play: at a Hilton on the other end of Waikiki, where the Association for the
Advancement of Philosophy and Psychiatry was holding a confab, “The Future of
Psychiatric Nosology,” and where First could be found for the first two days of
the meeting. The room’s low ceiling and dingy carpet, its stale, stuffy
atmosphere, the balky sound system that at random moments broadcast the signal
of a local radio station—all contrasted starkly with the towering grandeur of
the convention center. As you wound your way down the short, narrow staircase that
connected the room to the elevator stop above, you couldn’t help but think of
the film Being John Malkovich and wonder if you had
happened upon a real-life 8½th floor.
The thirty or forty people gathered seemed
unfazed by their surroundings as they dug into questions such as “What Is It to
Be Diagnosed?” and “What Would a Scientific and Valid DSM Look Like?” The group
was not without its own rifts—one presenter fired back at his questioner, “If I
could be permitted just one ad hominem response, do you treat Posttraumatic
Stress Disorder or just cause it?”—but all the participants seemed at home with
the apocalyptic tone Jim Phillips, the keynote speaker, conjured in the title
of his talk: “Slouching Toward DSM-5.” If the mood up the road at the convention
center was breezily optimistic, at the Hilton it was angry, worried, even
despairing—not least because of the way concerns about the meaning of
diagnosis, its impact on identity, and the seeming impossibility of grafting
psychological suffering onto the medical model of disease had been relegated to
this dingy outpost, as if the APA didn’t even understand the conceptual
complexity, the profound and far-reaching implications of its own product. By
the end of the conference, two psychiatrists in the group announced their
intentions to leave the field, largely, they said, because they had come to
realize that all other forms of resistance were indeed futile. Whatever future
psychiatric nosology might have, it seems, they didn’t want any part of it.
Amid all these sweeping critiques and
meaty topics—“Metaethics and Mental Illness,” for example, or “Epistemic and
Nonepistemic Values in Psychiatry”—First
stuck to small ball6. He described how the APA
originally justified undertaking the DSM-5 in order to keep in harmony with the
World Health Organization’s planned ICD-11, but then the ICD-11 had been
delayed, and the U.S. put off implementing the ICD-10, which had come out in
1992 and was the original justification for the DSM-IV, which was therefore
still using codes from the ICD-9, but the ICD-10 would finally go into effect
in October 2013, which had become the new justification for the DSM-5, but
since the DSM-IV had been keyed to the ICD-10, it was not really necessary to
revise the manual, only to “crosswalk” the codes. “You might be scratching your
head about this,” he said. “You might go, ‘Huh, I’m totally confused here.’”
He was right about that.
But, First continued, a problem much more
important and easier to grasp could be seen in the unevenness of the APA’s
proposed changes. Take Intermittent Explosive Disorder, for example. “It’s one
of the few disorders for which there are no changes proposed,” he said. “Is
that because the criteria for IED are so sound that there is no need to change
them?” (IED, which got its initials before the war in Iraq made them piquant,
is pretty much what it sounds like—a propensity, mostly among children and
adolescents, to become quickly and unpredictably enraged, and then quickly
return to normal.) He pointed out that IED is one of those “socially
constructed, I-don’t-know-what-it-means” diagnoses, one that you would think
any major revision would reconsider. But, he explained, no one on the work
group seemed interested in IED (or, he added, in two other impulse-control
disorders—kleptomania and pyromania). It wasn’t anyone’s pet project, so the
criteria had been left unmolested.*
On the other hand, he continued, consider
Specific Phobia, described in the DSM-IV as a “marked and persistent fear cued
by . . . a specific object.” There was apparently no shortage of experts
interested in this one, with the predictable result. First flashed a PowerPoint
slide on which he had highlighted the differences between the existing and the
proposed criteria. The text was a jumble of cross-outs and underlines. “Marked
and persistent fear that is excessive or unreasonable, cued by the presence or
anticipation of a specific object” had become “marked fear or anxiety about a
specific object or situation.” An entire criterion—that the patient recognize
the fear as excessive or unreasonable—had been deleted in favor of a
requirement that the clinician determine if it is out of proportion to the
actual danger (but only after taking into consideration the “sociocultural
context”). “Avoidance, anxious anticipation, or distress” had become “fear,
anxiety, or avoidance.”
An expert flaps his mouth in New York or
Washington, and chaos breaks out in Peoria—an outcome made more vexing, First
pointed out, by the fact that these changes seem to be made for the sake of
change, to fix diagnoses that aren’t broken. “Why did this happen?” he asked.
The answer lies not in science, but in sociology, in what he called the work group effect. “If you get a
group of people doing weekly conference calls for three years, you are going to
get lots and lots of changes,” he said. “We’re dealing with human nature here.
Why would someone clamor for a position where they spend five years of their
lives doing a lot of work for nothing? The reward is to get your view of the
world embedded in the DSM.”
• • •
It’s Monday, the third day of
the annual meeting, and the AAPP conference is over. First has settled into a
seat to watch Kupfer and Regier demonstrate7
how they expect clinicians to use the DSM-5 to reach diagnoses, or at least how
they will do it in the field trials. This will also be their first opportunity
to show off their long-anticipated dimensional assessment methods and perhaps
answer some of the questions about proposals such as the move to eliminate
Asperger’s.
The room is set up for a couple hundred
people. About twenty-five have straggled in. If Regier is disappointed by the
turnout, he’s not saying. Neither is he waiting for latecomers, although he
might privately be cursing the scheduler who put this workshop on at noon, the
hour at which drug companies like to put on shows while psychiatrists enjoy
their box lunches.
You can’t blame him for wanting to get
started. For nearly two years, he has been responding to worries about the
unreadiness of the new criteria and the unwieldiness of the dimensional
assessments with some version of the response he gave me in September 2010 when
I repeated those charges: “That’s why we are
doing a field test8,” he said, and he added that the
trials would begin soon.
A month after that conversation, on
October 5, the APA sent out a press release. The field trials had started, it
declared, and it described “two rigorous
study designs9.” In one, to be conducted at eleven
medical centers across North America, two different clinicians would use the
new criteria and the dimensional measures to independently evaluate the same
patient. To the extent that they agreed, the diagnoses would be seen as
reliable. Videotapes of their work would be reviewed by a third clinician, this
one considered an expert, to see if either or both of them had come up with a
valid diagnosis. The participants would then rate the usefulness of the new
procedures. In the second design, called the Routine Clinical Practice (RCP)
trial, 3,900 mental health professionals in private offices would evaluate two
patients, also using the new criteria and dimensions. They would repeat the
procedure with the same patients a couple of weeks or so later, and the results
would be compared. The information generated from the two studies would be fed
back to the work groups, who would tweak the criteria accordingly and return
them to the field trialists for a second round of testing. “Field trials will
give us the information we need to ensure the diagnostic criteria are useful
and accurate,” Regier said.
The release didn’t mention that the field
trials were already five months late. But that’s not all it left out. It also
failed to say what Regier had to admit when I asked him directly the next day:
that they really hadn’t begun at all. What had started was only a pilot study
designed to shake the bugs out of the protocols for the medical center trials.
This research had to be finished, its data analyzed, the methodology modified
according to the findings, and the clinicians trained before the field trial
itself could begin in earnest. He couldn’t say when this would happen or, for
that matter, when the 3,900 practitioners—a number that would soon go up
without explanation to 5,000—in the routine practice study would get their
marching orders.
In that October conversation, Regier also told
me he didn’t understand what all the fuss was about. “I’m surprised10 that the . . .
statement would be considered news. Perhaps we should have a daily tweet.” It
was as if he didn’t know that it was his people who had called it a “news
release” or that just the previous day, they had quoted him calling the field
trials a “critical phase” in an “important process.”
The field trials did eventually get under
way. Or at least the academic center studies did, with the first opening for
business just before Christmas 2010, and the last coming on line in March
2011—nearly a full year past their scheduled start. But even as we convened in
Hawaii, the RCP trial had yet to start, and no one was saying when it would. Allen
Frances had made the predictable hay of the slipping schedule, adding it to the
litany of what he called disarray and disorganization, his tone—“Missed
Deadlines Have Troubling Consequences,” in case that wasn’t obvious—becoming
increasingly high-handed. In the meantime, it was safe to say that the field
trials had not yet won over a single heart or mind.
So no wonder Regier is eager to strut the
APA’s stuff. I’m sure he’d like us to go back and talk them up to our
colleagues, maybe even tweet the virtues of the new criteria and the
dimensional measures. I am also eager, as I have signed up to be one of the RCP
trialists, and this session will be my first chance to see what I’ve gotten
myself into.
“Of particular value to us is feedback
from clinicians about how useful these [assessments] would be in your
practices,” Regier is saying. And the feedback starts right now, he tells us,
thanks to the electronic keypads, about the size of a television remote
control, on the tables in front of us. “Let’s try these out with a question,
and you’ll see how they work when an entire audience uses them.”
The entire audience, which by now has
swelled to at least thirty-five, grab their clickers. The question comes into
view on the PowerPoint screen.
Which of the following
productions was not filmed in Hawaii?
A.
Hawaii Five-O
B.
Baywatch
C.
Jurassic Park
D.
Indiana Jones and the Raiders of the Lost Ark
“There’s supposed to be music,” Regier
says, and looks at the tech guy, who flips a switch. A steel drum song breaks out
on the speakers. Which seems a little more “Hey, mon,” than “Aloha,” but Regier
doesn’t seem to mind.
We cast our ballots, and as soon as the
calypso stops, percentages for each answer pop up on the screen. Baywatch leads the way. “Fifty percent of you know your TV
series,” Regier says.
Regier explains what is about to happen.
Emily Kuhl, an APA staffer, and William Narrow, the psychiatrist in charge of
research for DSM-5, will be reenacting a session that occurred some weeks ago.
Kuhl will “channel” the patient, Regier explains, while Narrow conducts his
“regular clinical interview.”
Narrow begins by telling us that the
patient’s name is Virginia Hamm. The lame joke falls flat in the empty room.
Bearded and balding, Narrow is laconic, even shy, and not a natural showman; he
looks like he’d rather be almost anywhere else than on this, or any, stage.
Virginia, he continues, had come to the clinic and been assigned to a computer.
She’d typed in her demographics and described her chief complaint as Obsessive-Compulsive Disorder and depression. She had
filled out the Cross-Cutting Measures, Levels 1 and 2—the dimensional measures
designed to assess symptoms that are not necessarily part of the diagnosis. She
had indicated how regularly she felt “irritated, grouchy, or angry” or
“nervous, anxious, frightened, worried, or on edge,” how often she heard voices
or thought of hurting herself, whether she sniffed glue or drank alcohol, or if
she had ever found herself “not knowing who you really are or what you want out
of life.” She’d clicked through the items on the Altman Self-Rating Mania Scale
and the Patient Health Questionnaire—Somatic Symptom Short Form, and the PROMIS
(Patient Reported Outcomes Measurement Information System) scales for anxiety
and depression. She had confided in the computer about her “getting along with
people and participation in society,” about her “communicating/understanding,”
her “getting around and self-care and life activities.” After about a half hour
of pointing and clicking, she had pushed the last button, sending the
information to another computer, this one at Vanderbilt University, home of the
REDCap (Research Electronic Data Capture) system, which had tabulated the
answers and generated a report, returning it at the speed of light to her
clinician. We are holding a printout of the results in our hands, a thick sheaf
of papers telling us what is wrong with Virginia Hamm, if not how to cure her.
Narrow is going through the results out
loud. “Two point nine on the depression measure, anxiety score is in the
moderate range, somatic symptoms score is zero, suicidality is one,” he reads
from the laptop sitting on the table between him and the fake Virginia. “No
reported problems with cognition or memory. Emotionality above average, antagonism
is above average, disinhibition is below average, schizotypy is below average.”
Narrow seems a little tentative about what
to do with this information. He tells us that it isn’t exactly diagnostic,
because it doesn’t correspond to DSM categories, and it isn’t exactly a
screening device; it is only supposed to help direct the clinician’s attention
to certain DSM categories. But he is short on the details. It might be that his
regular clinical interview, like mine and that of most of the therapists I know,
doesn’t usually involve a laptop and a fake patient and an audience and a
computer printout. Still, he seems more uncertain about what to do next than
you’d expect from the guy who is in charge of the research.
He seems particularly unsure about how long
this is going to take. “If I start running out of time,” he says, “we’ll just
need to cut this short, but I will try and do as much as I can of the high
points of the interview.” He looks at a cluster of four or five women in the
front row, APA apparatchiks apparently. They seem to know something, and if it
had to do with the possibility that a ninety-minute session is not sufficient
to demonstrate the clinical trial, I realize that I might have made a
mistake—not by coming here instead of going to lunch, but by signing up to do
four of these interviews and thus committing six or more nonbillable hours to
the DSM-5 cause. I wonder what is going to happen when my 4,999 fellow
trialists, most of whom, or so I imagine, are busier and charge more money than
I, do this math.
“Okay, Miss Hamm,” Narrow says. “I’m glad
you’ve consented to do this study for us. It’s a very important study and will
help us to develop a new DSM.” He asks what has brought her to the clinic, and
she tells him what she has already told the computer about her OCD and
depression. “Why don’t we start with the OCD?” he asks. She tells him about how
she couldn’t throw anything away, especially not newspapers, how years and
years of them have at times accumulated in her apartment.
“Were most of the rooms filled with
things?
“Yeah.”
“Filled filled?”
She assures him that she left paths
between the piles, but even so, one day her brothers showed up at her apartment
and tossed her stash into a dumpster they had rented.
He wants to know what that was like
“emotionally.”
“I was shocked,” she replies. “It’s
stressful, you know, watching them take my stuff out. But we decided it’s
better to throw away two good things than to leave ninety-eight things that
aren’t so good.” And indeed, she added, while the brothers had to repeat the
purge a number of times, she had gotten used to it.
“So you had to go through some real
thought to part with these things?” Narrow asks.
Virginia doesn’t respond.
Narrow tries more questions about her OCD,
but Virginia, at least the way Kuhl is playing her, keeps her cards close to
her vest. She is not terribly insightful, or interesting, or engaging.
“So let’s talk about the depression now,”
Narrow says.
It started in college, Virginia tells him,
when she was “finding out that I’m gay” and worrying about what her parents
would think, but it wasn’t terrible, and she was never suicidal, and she was on
meds now, and, especially since two of her brothers had come out in the
meantime, her depression was really not much of a problem.
Narrow’s regular clinical interview
doesn’t seem to include taking a swing at any of these hanging curveballs.
Instead he delivers a volley of questions about whether she has ever been manic
or terrified of germs, or had “worries that go around and around in your mind”
(no, no, and no). He inquires into her smoking habits (a pack a day), her drug
use (LSD once or twice a year, and marijuana if someone offers it to her), and
her drinking (none).
“So what kind of person do you think you
are?” he asks. “Shy? Withdrawn?”
“Well, I’m not outgoing,” Virginia says.
Nearly a half hour has gone by since we
met Virginia Hamm. Somewhere paint has dried and grass has grown, and I’m
beginning to think that back at APA HQ, where Virginia is Emily and Dr. Narrow
is Bill, there is some trouble between them. Because she is not helping him at
all. Her monosyllabic answers are draining his monotone questions of whatever
vitality they might have had. She might be illustrating a clinical point with
her reticence, but Narrow’s interrogation isn’t exploring it. Nor is it clear
what use he’s making of the Cross-Cutting Measures or the PROMIS or anything
else from the heap of REDCap data, or just how these vaunted dimensional
measures are supposed to work. Neither does he seem intent on establishing
trust by turning the bits of information he is extracting into the first
tendrils of intimacy or, for that matter, on achieving any other therapeutic
goal. In fact, for the life of me, I can’t figure out what he is up to.
But then again, I’m not a psychiatrist,
let alone a psychiatrist at the top of my profession’s food chain, and it is
the nature of the mental health professions that they are practiced in their
own little silos, which means that even after nearly thirty years in the
business, I might still not know how a regular clinical interview is supposed
to go.
My BlackBerry buzzes. It’s a message from
Michael First, who has the row behind me all to himself, and who is a psychiatrist at the top of his profession. “I’m not
sure what the point of this exercise is,” it says. I am reassured, if no less
mystified.
As if he has read our thoughts (or heard
the BlackBerry and realized he’s losing his audience), Narrow suddenly stops
the Q&A. “I think I’m going to go onto the computer now,” he says. “I’ll be
quick.” He turns toward it and taps away. It’s not clear whether he’s
reassuring us or the patient or the women in the front row.
We are looking at a giant version of his
monitor on an overhead screen. To the left is a list of clickable diagnostic
classifications. He tells us he is going to open the module for Hoarding
Disorder—“the most dramatic example that we have,” he says, although this was
surely damnation with faint praise. (It also happens to be a diagnosis proposed
for DSM-5; they’ve smuggled in an advertisement for one of their new products.)
We’re looking at questions keyed to the proposed diagnostic criteria for
Hoarding Disorder. Narrow clicks on the items that, based on the interview so
far, he thinks Virginia meets. The computer asks him if he wants to enter a
diagnosis of Hoarding Disorder. He clicks yes and then clicks another box. The
page disappears before I can read it.
There is a sudden commotion from the front
row; the women are waving their hands and stage-whispering to Narrow. I’m
thinking that maybe they’re going to remind him that he has left out something
important, something that will allow us to see what innovation this rigmarole
brings to diagnostics or, for that matter, how it does anything other than
provide a near-perfect, if unintended, example of the circles in which
psychiatric nosology runs, the way he got to the diagnosis through the symptoms
and the symptoms through the diagnosis, how Hoarding Disorder is another line
carved in sand, a diagnosis that will no doubt be the object of scorn for the
leaders of DSM-6 or DSM-7, fodder for their paradigm-busting cannons, an
opportunity for them to justify the new book by decrying the old one’s
reifications. Perhaps, I think, they’re going to stand up and say, “But Bill, you
didn’t even pretend to be in doubt for a moment about the outcome—which, after
all, let’s face it, you knew all along, since you watched the videotape of the
real Virginia—so you couldn’t demonstrate how to get to the diagnosis or what
it has to do with emotionality or schizotypy or antagonism or with the PHQ and
the ASRM or anything we’ve seen other than the story about the brothers and the
dumpster and the piles of papers, which didn’t require a computer to figure
out, which indeed may have come to you despite the computer,” and then add,
sotto voce, how it might not be such a good idea to put all this unreadiness
and ineffectiveness on such naked display, not even here in front of this crowd
whose sparseness must seem to him, and to Kupfer and Regier, like a blessing.
But it’s none of that. “You didn’t save
it!” one of them exclaims. Narrow has missed a click and lost all the data he’s
spent the last twenty minutes entering.
Flop sweat breaks out on his brow. “I’m
sorry,” he says. “This is only the second time I’ve done this.” He sounds more
sheepish than petulant, like a batter returning to the dugout after whiffing in
the clutch, explaining to his teammates that he’d faced this pitcher only twice
before.
“Should I cut this short?” Narrow asks the
women. He’s also looking across the stage, where Kupfer has replaced Regier.
It’s pretty clear Narrow has had enough; he’s begging for the hook. But none is
offered, so he takes matters into his own hands announcing that he will skip
over the modules for other diagnoses and will now turn to the severity
measures.
These turn out to be quite simple and,
unlike the other ratings, clear in their application, if not terribly
revealing. He goes through the criteria proposed for Hoarding Disorder and asks
Virginia to rate their intensity and the distress they cause her on a scale of
one to five. Then, “because we don’t want total dependence on all these forms,”
he gives his own rating, as we field trial clinicians will be expected to do.
“I don’t have a lot of experience with this disorder”—and how could he, since
it doesn’t yet exist, at least not officially?—“but I would say it’s moderate.
It could be a lot worse. I mean, there’s no dead animals in there.”
Narrow looks back at the front row.
“Anything else?”
“Save it,” someone replies.
He’s clicking through that procedure when
Kupfer takes the lectern. There’s little mercy in his move. He doesn’t even
thank Narrow (or Kuhl) for his efforts. Instead, he tells us to pick up our
clickers. “Given the fact that we’ve spent a reasonable amount of time on the
interview,” he begins (and I don’t hear any irony in his voice), we ought to be
able to come up with a diagnosis. A list of choices flashes on the board. The
steel drums play. The percentages are revealed. Sixty-seven percent of us have
voted for Hoarding Disorder.
It is a regular landslide, unless you are
in, say, Turkmenistan. Which, evidently, Kupfer wishes we were. He wants to
know why a full third of the room—about a dozen of us—have not voted for the
party-endorsed candidate. (I’m wondering the same thing. Assuming the five APA
functionaries—15 percent of the electorate—voted the right way, only half of
the rest of us voted for Hoarding Disorder, and I had cast votes for Hoarding
Disorder on the four clickers I could easily reach.) He thinks the next
question might help to provide an answer. How useful were the new criteria in
reaching our conclusion? When 65 percent of us answer either moderately
or extremely, he observes that this is pretty
much the same percentage of the crowd who voted for Hoarding Disorder, as if
this somehow strengthened the credibility of the criteria, as if it did more
than indicate how circular diagnostic logic is. Of course they were useful in
making the diagnosis; there was no other way to reach it and, pace that dissenting 33 or 35 percent, no other diagnosis to
reach. (I’m feeling a little guilty about that two-point discrepancy; I cast a
vote for moderately on one less clicker than in the
first poll.)
When 31 percent of voters say they think
Virginia had Mixed Anxiety-Depression—a proposed diagnosis that has so little
to do with Virginia that I figure it was thrown in just to fill out the
multiple choices—I begin to wonder if someone is intentionally committing
mayhem. Ten people who want to embarrass Kupfer? A terrorist cell sent in by
the proponents of MAD to blow up HD? Acting out by the terminally bored?
Kupfer must be wondering, too, because he
invites people to come forward and explain their votes. No one does. He moves
on. He asks how useful we found the Cross-Cutting Measures and whether the
forms were too long (50 percent) or too short (4 percent; he’s lost even the
front row). When 53 percent say that the DSM-IV criteria are superior (a
meaningless question because the DSM-IV doesn’t list Hoarding Disorder), Kupfer
is quick to call the result a “nice split.” When 30 percent say the new
approach is superior to DSM-IV’s, and 20 percent say it’s equivalent, he points
out that this means half of us thought it was the same or better. But this turd
cannot be easily polished, and when Narrow ends the presentation by saying, “Of
those who said this is worse or much worse, we’d like to hear why,” it is hard
to imagine that he means it or that either man ever wants to hear about field
trials again.
• • •
When the session is turned
over to the audience for questions, Michael First stands up. He waits in line
at the audience mic while a man takes Narrow to task for not asking more about
Virginia’s substance abuse. “I hope you weren’t rating my interview, as opposed
to the general approach,” Narrow responds.
First doesn’t attack Narrow for being
unprepared or criticize his technique or ask him just exactly what the point of
that exercise was. Instead, he says that as he watched the demonstration, he was
wondering how he would have asked the questions and how every other clinician
would have asked them; and, realizing that there are as many regular clinical
interviews as there are clinicians, he was also wondering how Narrow, in his
role as the head of research for DSM-5, was going to deal with that. How will
he know, in the likely event of diagnostic discrepancies among clinicians, that
they are the result of the criteria rather than the way each clinician asks the
questions? How, in other words, will the field trials do the job they are
supposed to do—evaluate the reliability of the new DSM?
“Well, that’s a very complex question,”
Narrow replies, and proceeds not to answer it, except to say that they had
tried to figure it out in a pilot study and it hadn’t worked out.
But First asks the question again. Narrow
acknowledges that not only are they not requiring a structured interview, they
are not even training the study clinicians on the new diagnoses or “telling
them how they should be interpreting these measures.” They are simply asking
them to familiarize themselves with the website. But, he assures us, this is
not a weakness in the design but a strength: the field trials will mirror how
clinicians practice in the real world and thus yield more realistic results
than the DSM-III and DSM-IV field trials did. Those old numbers, the ones that
did so much to restore psychiatry’s respectability, Narrow is saying, were
overstated, inflated by the pristine conditions under which they were
conducted. But now that the APA has cleverly dirtied up the trials, Narrow
tells us, he can almost guarantee that reliability will be worse than it was in
earlier DSMs.
I have underestimated First. He has
managed to unearth the point of the exercise after all: to prepare us all for
the lousy outcomes the field trials were evidently designed to yield. As we
file out of the room, I ask him what it’s like to be a bystander to the
proceedings. “Oh, it’s absolutely excruciating,” he answers, as if that were
obvious. Which, come to think of it, it is.
• • •
Narrow was correct about at
least one thing. As Helena Kraemer, the chief statistician on the DSM-5 task
force, told a much larger crowd the next day, “People’s
expectations of what reliability should be11 have been
grossly inflated.” She left no question about who was responsible for this: Bob
Spitzer.
Spitzer knew it was not enough to ask two
doctors to diagnose a patient, compare their answers, and use the results to
pronounce judgment on whether the diagnosis was reliable. That approach
wouldn’t account for the possibility that the clinicians agreed by chance—by,
say, flipping a coin or tossing a dart or just plain guessing—rather than
because the diagnostic criteria were well written. Fortunately for Spitzer, in
1960 a statistician named Jacob Cohen had invented a method for calculating the
extent to which agreement between two people using the same rating scale is the
result of factors other than chance. The statistic had come to be known as Cohen’s kappa, and Spitzer, working with Cohen, had adapted
it for use in evaluating the reliability of diagnoses.
Spitzer and Cohen introduced kappa to
psychiatrists in 1967, promoting it as a way out of the reliability mess. At
first, they used it primarily to quantify just how bad things were, and this
agenda shaped the way they addressed a problem built into the statistic. A
kappa of 0 indicates that any agreement is by chance alone; a kappa of 1
indicates that researchers have come to the same conclusion for nonrandom
reasons (presumably because the criteria work). But what do the numbers in
between mean? How much agreement is sufficient to call a diagnosis reliable (or
not)? After all, even a low kappa means that clinicians outperformed coin tossers
or monkeys at typewriters.
This has turned out to be a hotly
contested question, or at least as hot as anything in statistics gets. In 1974,
Spitzer proposed an answer. Kappas of around .40, he said, indicated “poor”
agreement, .55 was “no better than fair,” .70 was “only satisfactory,” and more
than .80 would be “uniformly high.” But as California professors Stuart Kirk
and Herb Kutchins noted, Spitzer “could have
employed12 very good, good, not so good, and bad,” and they pointed out that there was a reason he
didn’t. Spitzer’s 1974 paper was an attempt to put numbers to the widely noted
poor reliability of DSM-II diagnoses, “belittling the reliability of the past,”
as Kirk and Kutchins put it, in order to set the stage for the transition to a
criterion-based future.
Having established kappa as the arbiter of
reliability and having promised success for his new diagnostic approach,
Spitzer then had to show that descriptive diagnosis would achieve high kappas.
And the DSM-III field trials did exactly that, in no small part because the
patients were preselected for the likelihood that they would qualify for the
diagnosis and the researchers were drilled on the criteria—and on a clinical
interview that left little to chance or imagination. Now that his ox was in
danger of being gored, Spitzer had also come up with some new ways to evaluate
kappa—no longer was .70 “only satisfactory”; now it was a “high kappa [that]
indicates good agreement.” And by this standard, the DSM-III field trials were
a success, far outpacing results using the earlier manuals and, in many cases,
well exceeding the .70 threshold.
If psychiatrists noticed that the fix had
been in from the start, they didn’t say so—most likely because the numbers gave
the profession exactly what it had been looking for. But just as Spitzer once
denigrated the past to clear the way for the DSM-III, Kraemer was now claiming
that Spitzer’s results were patently ridiculous. “I think it will be a miracle
if we get a kappa of .80,” she said. “In fact, if someone comes to me and tells
me we’ve got one, I’m going to tell her to go back and make sure there hasn’t
been some kind of screwup.”
Kraemer didn’t seem worried about the
implications of repudiating the very same statistics that the APA had been
using for thirty years to stake its claim to scientific respectability or, for
that matter, of calling Bob Spitzer a screwup. But she was telling us what
numbers we could expect and what they would mean—and she was singing a much
different tune from Spitzer’s.
Most of the kappas, Kraemer predicted,
would come in somewhere between .40 and .60—the same reliability Spitzer
characterized as “no better than fair.” But doctors in other fields were
satisfied with reliability like this, she said. There didn’t seem to be any of
those doctors around to object to this—say, an endocrinologist who could
testify as to whether it would truly be a miracle if he and a random colleague
agreed most of the time on whether a patient with high blood sugar had
diabetes—but Kraemer seemed to anticipate the danger, and she tacked. “Until
you can do X-rays, until you can do scans, until you can do tissue samples,”
she said, psychiatric diagnoses could only “aspire to be as good as medical
diagnosis.” In the meantime, she added, even if the kappa was only between .20
and .40—numbers that Spitzer didn’t even deign to characterize—“it will be
acceptable.”
First was back at the audience microphone.
I knew better than to think he would ask exactly how (and to whom) these
numbers were acceptable or whether lowering expectations was really such a good
idea, given how central reliability had been to reestablishing psychiatry’s
credibility, or how the APA was going to convince the public that sharply
reduced reliability was actually an improvement over the earlier product.
Still, his question, a version of the one
he had asked Narrow, was plenty barbed. Let’s say you end up with a kappa of
.10 on the field trial, he said—a result that wouldn’t clear even Kraemer’s
very low bar. “Presumably they are going to use this information to make the
DSM-5 better before it is released.” But, he continued, given the impossibility
of sorting out the way clinicians used the criteria from the criteria
themselves, “how can people find out where the problem is, and how do you know
how to fix it? How will they even know where to look?”
“This is why I use the analogy of field
testing and airplanes,” Kraemer replied. “The airplane crashes, the question is
why did it crash and what are you going to do about it? There’s a lot of
information they”—I think she meant the APA, not the National Transportation
Safety Board—“can look at, but it’s not a matter of analyzing the data to find
out exactly what’s wrong.” Kraemer seemed to be saying that the point wasn’t to
sift through the wreckage and try to prevent another catastrophe but,
evidently, to crash the plane and then announce that the destruction could have
been a lot worse.
To be honest, however, I wasn’t sure. She
was not making all that much sense, or maybe I just didn’t grasp the
complexities of statistical modeling. And besides, I was distracted by a memory
of something Steve Hyman once wrote. Fixing the DSM, finding another paradigm,
getting away from its reifications—this, he said, was like “repairing a plane
while it is flying.” It was a suggestive analogy, I thought at the time, one
that recognized the near impossibility of the task even as it indicated its
high stakes—and the necessity of keeping the mechanics from swearing and banging
too loudly, lest the passengers start asking for a quick landing and a voucher
on another airline. But whatever Hyman meant, I was now pretty certain that he
wasn’t thinking that the solution was to fly the plane into the ground on
purpose, to put the wounded craft out of its misery before it plummeted to
earth of its own accord.
First yielded the mic and went back to the
end of the line for another round. The next questioner wanted to know why
dimensional assessments (an earlier topic of the panel) hadn’t been in DSM-IV.
“Actually, you can turn around and ask Michael,” Kraemer said.
“The answer is that there are dimensional measures,” First said. He named them: the
severity scales for various disorders, the one-hundred-point scale to rate
overall functioning, and a numerical scale to rate the psychosocial stressors a
patient was facing. “But the reception among clinicians has been a resounding
‘We’re not interested.’”
His answer was game, and accurate, but it
didn’t really matter. He had lost the match. As Kraemer had just made all too
clear, she was up there with Regier and Kupfer and he was down on the floor,
just another guy in line—and one who, she had just implied, was responsible for
the mess they had spent the last ten years trying to clean up.
• • •
“We’d better get smart about measuring13
what we do and proving its value,” psychiatrist Lawson Wulsin told another
audience at the annual meeting, “or we are going to lose.” Wulsin was the
liaison between the DSM-5 task force and other medical specialties, so even if
the APA’s plane-crash logic made any sense to him, he had to know that his
nonpsychiatrist colleagues weren’t going to fall for this strategy, especially
not if it hinged on claiming that, at least when it came to diagnosis, the rest
of medicine was just as unreliable as psychiatry.
But it was too late to change course.
Spitzer had chosen kappa as the pole star and used it to steer psychiatry off
the shoals. He gave his profession numbers to cite as evidence that it was
sailing in the same seas as the rest of medicine. So the proof of the DSM-5’s
success would also have to be in numbers. With the field trials only just under
way, it remained to be seen if the leaders of the APA had really gotten smart
about proving they could measure what they do and sell us on its value.
Chapter 15
You have
to understand1,” Allen Frances is telling me.
“What Bob Spitzer was interested in, no one else was. I certainly wasn’t.
Because we were all discovering the meaning of life in every patient.”
It’s July 2011. I’ve known Frances for
nearly a year, a year in which I’ve had no luck getting him to explain to me
how a man comes to scorch the earth he once strode, how, for that matter, he
came to walk it in the first place, how you get to be America’s top
psychiatrist without just a smidgen of ambition—and, while he’s at it, to help
me understand how he can simultaneously believe that DSM disorders are not real
but that the book nonetheless deserves its authority, how he can both prize the
truth and champion the noble lie, and how these contradictions can fit in one
life. We’ve exchanged hundreds of e-mails and sent each other books in the real
mail. We’ve spent four or five days together, the last two with his wife, Donna
Manning, and his two teenage grandchildren. I’ve slept on his living room
floor, watched Gunsmoke on his bedroom TV, eaten at
his table, sat squeezed between the grandkids in the backseat of his convertible,
buffeted by the wind on an excursion down to Big Sur. He’s ribbed me
mercilessly about, among other things, my “naiveté” in thinking that the
unfolding debacle of the DSM-5 is about anything more than the rank
incompetence of its architects, that in insisting that deep historical forces
are at work, I am playing Abbott to the APA’s Costello. He has even given me
the Herb Peyser treatment, leaning across the table and pinching my cheek (he
spared me the kiss) when I tried to explain to him the dance between editor and
writer that had landed his “bullshit” comment in the lead of my Wired story—a pinch affectionate and hostile in equal parts
and, most of all, devastatingly effective in stopping my explanation cold, the
sudden silence thick with rebuke.
For a year he has evaded the question.
He’s demurred on tactical grounds—“If it
seems like this is coming2 from a personality quirk,” he told
me, “then the message will get lost.” He’s protested that he’s “just no good at
introspection,” and when floating like a butterfly has failed him, he’s stung
me with the accusation that I care about all the wrong things, that these
questions are worthy of People and not a serious book
about the DSM. But as we wind through the California hills early on a July
morning, top up, no grandkids, he poses my question perfectly: “You mean, how
could a person be interested in the drama of human emotions and psychology and
at the same time spend seven years of his life trying to be precise about
things at the descriptive surface?” This gets him to reminiscing about the old
days with Spitzer at Columbia, and I’m thinking that maybe this year of getting
teased and scolded and lectured has all been a prolonged hazing, that I have
passed some kind of test, that he is finally going to untangle some of these
contradictions.
“The meaning of life,” I repeat. “And what
was that?”
“That I’m an even bigger schmuck than I
think I am.”
It’s all a little hard to swallow, this
brilliant, erudite, effortlessly dominating man insisting that he is stupid and
feckless, and evading an account of his own motivation in the bargain. But then
again, this is the man who put a disclaimer at the front of the DSM as a
prophylaxis against people taking the book too seriously, who thinks that
insisting mental disorders don’t actually exist even as you enumerate them will
somehow make people stop acting as if the disorders are real. He might really
think that humility is enough to erase power, that what Montesquieu really
meant was that when aristocrats exercised modesty, it somehow stopped them from
having more money than everyone else.
“The least important person on the field
is the general,” Frances is saying. “The battle is won by an individual soldier
deciding to stand, and having his buddies follow him.” He’s wrested the
conversation back to the subject he wants to talk about the most: the small but
determined claque of DSM-5 resisters that has recently coalesced around him,
attracted, it seems, to his irresistible combination of gravitas and dissent.
The soldier in question is a Floridian named Dayle Jones. She’s a counselor, a
blogger for the American Counseling Association (ACA), and a member of the
committee revising the ICD, and she has been assembling her own case against
the DSM-5, trying to warn the 115,000 members of her organization that the new
manual will be a disaster for them. “She could be, when all is said and done,
the most influential person in all of DSM-5,” Frances says. The APA may be free
to ignore him, he explains, but Dayle Jones has been telling the ACA members
that they can get the ICD at no cost, and the APA is surely “going to listen to
115,000 buyers.”
The general might be unimportant (and
reluctant), but that doesn’t mean he isn’t leading the battle. “I’m doing
several things to help [Jones],” he told me, but “it’s better that they’re not
seen as coming from me.” He thinks the APA is more likely to listen to Jones
and her organization, and to the other dissenters, if they are not seen as affiliated
with him. Or with me, evidently. “She will be an important character in your
book,” he says. But I should steer clear for a while. “It won’t look good if
she’s doing this from your press box. This should just be a concerned lady from
Florida. I don’t want anything to happen to queer what I’m trying to do.”
For a guy who has no interest in power, he
sure knows how to use it.
Still, when he says, “My narcissism couldn’t survive the teenage
insight3 that we are all insignificant and
transient worms, that no one has much stuff to strut,” it’s impossible to
dismiss that as just another facile gloss from Machiavelli or Sun Tzu. And even
if he has copped to exaggerating the flaws in DSM-IV for rhetorical purposes,
there doesn’t seem to be anything tactical in his acknowledgment of the error
that launched the mission we are on today, the one that has gotten Frances
dressed in his Sunday best, and both of us up and out of the house by six.
“This was one royal fuckup,” he says, and he’s on his way to try to set it
straight.
• • •
Our destination is a meeting
of lawyers. The royal fuckup was the kind that only they could love, an
opportunity buried deep in the interstices of the DSM text, ready to be
excavated and exploited—in this case by prosecutors who, aided by
psychiatrists, can use it to keep certain sex offenders locked up well beyond
the end of their sentences, indefinitely or maybe even forever.
That wasn’t what Frances and the rest of
the DSM-IV crew had in mind when they decided that meeting Criterion A for
Pedophilia—“over a period of at least 6
months4, recurrent, intense sexually
arousing fantasies, sexual urges or behaviors involving sexual activity with a
prepubescent child”—was not enough to diagnose a patient with a mental
disorder. The offender also needed to meet Criterion B: “The fantasies, sexual
urges, or behaviors cause clinically significant distress or impairment in
social, occupational, or other important areas of functioning.” This was only
the boilerplate clinical significance criterion that had been added to many
diagnoses in DSM-IV, and all Frances and First had intended by it, as they
wrote in a 2008 American Journal of Psychiatry
editorial, was to remind clinicians that, as they put it in the DSM-IV, “the symptom criteria alone5
are insufficient to define mental disorder.”
But that’s not how Linda Bowles, a
contributor to the conservative Christian news site WorldNetDaily, took it. To
her, it was just more evidence of the secular humanist conspiracy to further
the gay agenda. “While we have been
preoccupied6 with the dangers posed to our
children by inanimate objects, namely guns,” she wrote in the summer of 1999,
“they were under a much more dangerous assault from animate objects, namely
psychologists and psychiatrists.” The blitz had begun with the deletion of
homosexuality from the DSM, she continued, and had gotten worse with Criterion
B, which she read to mean that “no matter how heinous the sexual perversion, if
the pervert does not feel shame or remorse, he does not have a psychiatric
problem.”
Bowles’s accusations rocketed around the
right-wing blogosphere, picking up endorsements from the head of the National
Association for Research and Therapy of Homosexuality, the medical wing of the
pray-the-gay-away movement, and Charles Socarides, the psychiatrist who had led
the opposition to the deletion in 1973, along with radio scold Laura
Schlessinger. It also made its way to the APA, whose lawyers wrote to Bowles
demanding that she “acknowledge the ‘APA’s
clear opposition7 to pedophilia.’” The APA also
issued a press release reiterating its stance that “an adult who engages in
sexual activity with a child is performing a criminal and immoral act which
never can be considered normal or socially acceptable behavior.”
But as any scandal-scarred politician will
tell you, vigorous defenses against charges of turpitude are mostly
self-defeating. If you run an organization of helping professionals, you don’t
want to have to prove that your members aren’t really human missiles intent on
blasting us all into a secular humanist hell. To forestall the necessity of
further defenses, Frances and First recalled in their editorial, they removed
the clinical significance clause from the diagnosis when the DSM-IV-TR came out
in 2000. In its place was the old DSM-III-R version of Criterion B, according
to which if someone “has acted on these
urges8 or is markedly distressed by them,”
he qualifies for the diagnosis.
This was the royal fuckup: the offender no
longer had to be “impaired” to warrant the diagnosis. All he had to do was act.
In the original DSM-IV version, the offender also had to have children as his
primary sexual object. The attraction was the “impairment,” the thing that made
his behavior disordered rather than simply repellent or unusual. But in the
DSM-IV-TR, this requirement was gone, and since, according to Criterion A,
“fantasies, sexual urges, or behaviors” were symptoms of Pedophilia, all the
offender had to do to warrant the diagnosis was to commit the offense. This
meant that, starting in 2000, a person who had sex with a child was ipso facto
mentally ill.
Now, that may seem obvious to you. But
that’s only because of how reflexively we attribute all our peccadilloes and
quirks (or, more likely, those of other people) to mental rather than moral
defect. The DSM, with its reach into daily life, has given us an ample
vocabulary for expressing this intuition. But in fact, technically speaking
anyway, this is not the case. Or at least it’s not supposed to be. It is surely
not what First and Frances believe.
“Fewer
than half of child molesters9 have Pedophilia,”
First told me. “Often the child is a victim of convenience for an antisocial
person.” Without “an underlying pattern of arousal,” as he put it, there is no
mental disorder, at least not in the sex department; there is only criminality.
That’s what First and Frances meant the DSM-IV-TR to say, in any event—that
having sex with a kid was always criminal, but not always a symptom of
Pedophilia, or of any psychiatric diagnosis for that matter.
But to a lawyer, or at least to a
prosecutor in a state with sexually violent predator (SVP) laws, which allow
diagnosed sex offenders to be kept in “treatment units” even after they have
served out their sentences, a diagnosis based on behavior alone is an
opportunity to protect (and score political points with) a public disgusted and
frightened by sex offenders. The DSM-IV-TR diagnosis had turned into a
different kind of opportunity for mental health experts, spawning a cottage
industry of doctors ready to testify that the offender has indeed offended, and
that this behavior is the symptom of a mental illness. Their practice is not
limited to pedophiles. Because Sexual Sadism, Exhibitionism, Voyeurism, and
Frotteurism all have the same behavior-only criterion as Pedophilia, rapists,
flashers, peepers, and humpers all can be put away until they are “cured”—which
may well mean forever. (And if the behavior in question doesn’t meet the criteria
for one of those diagnoses, the forensic psychiatrist can always resort to
Paraphilia NOS.)
“I don’t care about the rapist being in
jail,” Frances said. “Most of them deserve to be there.” But they also deserve
to get out once they have paid the prescribed penalty. Some rapists—the
sadists, for instance, who can’t get aroused without inflicting pain on a
nonconsenting person—might be suffering from a mental disorder that requires
involuntary commitment, but indefinite incarceration based on behavior alone,
in Frances’s view, “is preventive detention and double jeopardy. It’s a
violation of due process. It’s unconstitutional.” (The Supreme Court disagrees.
It has ruled that so long as the state can show that they are not punishing
mere criminality but treating a mental defect ascertained by an expert, they
can keep the offender locked up.) That’s what he cares about, that and the fact
that this “colossal swindle”—forensic experts teaming up with prosecutors to
deprive people of their civil rights—was made possible by his DSM. “I hate the
fact that we’ve made this mistake,” he said. “We didn’t understand the SVP
laws. We blew it.”
“I don’t wallow in my own guilt,” he
added, “but I do like to clean up my own messes.”
Which is why he testifies in civil commitment
hearings, trying to explain that sexual behavior without that underlying
pattern cannot be a symptom of a mental disorder, and that the convict might
only be a criminal. And it is why we are on our way to this meeting, where he
will reiterate that distinction to defense lawyers to help them figure out how
to convince judges and juries that mental illness is one thing and evil quite
another.
The mess he’s trying to clean up was
caused by two tiny words: and and or.
Had Criterion A read “fantasies, urges, and
behaviors,” he points out, it would be much harder for those enterprising
psychiatrists and prosecutors to detach behavior from psychology and condemn
prisoners to endless detention. This was exactly the kind of unforeseen
consequence of which the DSM-5 crew seemed heedless. “If an or
for an and could create mayhem,” he says, “what
unintended harm could be wrought by the paradigm shifters?”
• • •
The paradigm shifters had
long ago stopped responding to Frances. But he was no longer their only
nemesis.
His fellow critics included at least one
person who was as surprised as anyone to find herself on the same side as
Frances. Paula Caplan, a psychologist affiliated with Harvard, had been a
consultant to the DSM-IV personality disorders work group, a position from
which she had tormented Frances as relentlessly as Frances was now tormenting
Regier. Her main complaint back then was about Self-Defeating Personality
Disorder. While Frances thought it was poorly conceived and had little
empirical support, Caplan thought it was just plain sexist. Frances thought
Caplan’s critique was “too polemical10”
and warned her that since the proposal was sure to be rejected, there was no
need for “heated controversy.”
Frances’s dismissal seemed only to inflame
Caplan, who submitted her own DSM-IV diagnosis: Delusional Dominating
Personality Disorder (DDPD). Among the fourteen proposed criteria were “a tendency to feel inordinately threatened11
by women who fail to disguise their intelligence” and “the presence of . . .
delusions that women like to suffer.” DDPD was, she wrote, “most commonly seen
in males,” often in “leaders of traditional mental health professions, military
personnel, executives of large corporations, and powerful political leaders of
many aims.” It was a “modest proposal,” she wrote, “an antidote to . . . the
institutionalized sexism in the mental health system.”
“I
really wasn’t sure12 what to make [of ] your
‘delusional dominating personality disorder,’” Frances responded. “How serious
are you about it?” Much as he thought the proposal was a provocation, the
reason he gave for rejecting it out of hand was the standard DSM-IV demurral:
that there wasn’t enough evidence for DDPD even to be considered. But when
Caplan asked for funds to develop that evidence, Frances refused. “It is disruptive to constantly tinker13
with the classification,” he wrote, adding, in case she didn’t get the hint,
“if this sounds discouraging, I’m afraid it is meant to.”
After Caplan quit the work group, she
wrote They Say You’re Crazy: How the World’s Most Powerful
Psychiatrists Decide Who’s Normal, a broadside against DSM-IV, in which
she cast the affair as an instance of the good-old-boy politics that powered
the DSM. So even if Caplan did give Frances
a shout-out14 for “bravely com[ing] forward with
a mea culpa,” it was very unlikely that she was in cahoots with him when she
came up with a modest proposal for the DSM-5: Toxic Psychiatric Drug Syndrome.
In her letter to the task force, she also made some recommendations: that the
APA “join an initiative to hold Congressional hearings about psychiatric
diagnoses,” that it add a black-box warning to the actual DSM-5 emphasizing
that the diagnoses were not to be used as “the basis for any professional or
legal decision that may limit the liberty, or discriminate against, any
individual,” and that, “because of . . . ongoing significant problems in the
process,” publication be indefinitely delayed.
The APA swatted away Caplan as summarily
as Frances had, although without his personal touch. They used a public relations
firm, which arranged a conference call between representatives of “consumer
groups”—Caplan was positioning herself as a champion of people given
unwarranted diagnoses and prescriptions—and the DSM leaders. Caplan heard that
there would be twenty others on the hour-long call, so she tried to coordinate
with the others on the questions that would be asked, but the hired guns
refused to disclose the participants or forward a list of proposed questions to
them. On the appointed day15,
according to Caplan, after Carol Bernstein assured the callers that the APA
needed “the expertise of patients, families, and their advocates,” Kupfer and
Regier, along with a task force member, used the first half of the call to give
their talking points. Participants who wished to ask questions were then
instructed to dial a code, and after a silence during which a queue was
constructed, six were allowed to ask a single question each; their phones were
muted as soon as they delivered it. The APA representatives stuck to their
script and, after promising (but refusing to schedule) further discussion, said
good-bye.
The new bosses were no different from the
old bosses, Caplan concluded. They might give the “impression of openness to debate,”
she wrote in her Psychology Today blog, but in real
life, critics like her would be “largely ignored,” their evidence “shoved
aside,” and the world’s latest most powerful psychiatrists would once again
“put in the next edition of the manual whatever they pleased.”
If Caplan was railing against the
psychiatrists’ process, the British Psychological Society was going right for
the content of what displeased them. In a twenty-six-page manifesto released in
June, the BPS accused the APA of “the
continued and continuous medicalisation16 of . . . natural
and normal responses.” These responses, the BPS went on, “undoubtedly have
distressing consequences which demand helping responses, but which do not
reflect illnesses so much as normal individual variation.” Attenuated Psychosis
Symptoms Syndrome (APSS), for instance, “looks like an opportunity to
stigmatize eccentric people, and to lower the threshold for achieving a
diagnosis of psychosis,” leading in turn to more drug treatments. The overall
thrust of the manual, the BPS complained, was to identify the source of
psychological suffering “as located within individuals,” rather than in their
“relational context,” and to overlook the “undeniable social causation of many
such problems.”
The APA could hardly deny any of this. As
Regier had told the consumer groups on the conference call, the manual’s new
organizational structure was designed to reflect “what we’ve learned about the
brain, behavior, and genetics during the past two decades.” It doesn’t get much
more “within the individual” and outside the “relational context” than that.
And, as proposals like APSS and the elimination of the bereavement exclusion
made clear, one of the purposes of the DSM-5 was to make sure that no one who
was suffering would be deprived of the benefits of diagnosis.
On the other hand, the APA couldn’t ignore
the British Psychological Society or treat it as a mere “consumer group.” But
that didn’t mean they would acknowledge the actual criticisms, as Regier made clear in his official response17.
The BPS had cited a “well known member of the ‘Critical Psychiatry Network,’”
he wrote, one “that has largely adopted the Thomas Szasz approach to mental
illness.” These critics, Regier reminded his readers, think “we shouldn’t
consider any mental disorder, including individuals whose psychosis renders
them mentally incompetent, to have a brain-based illness.” Antipsychiatry was
once again deluding people into thinking that the APA was making grievous
errors.
Compounding the BPS’s ideological excess,
Regier went on, was plain ignorance.
What seems to be missing
is an appreciation of mental disorders as the result of gene-environmental
interactions that would trigger abnormal neuronal function in the brain. Why
the brain should be exempt from pathology when every other organ system is
subject to malfunction is left unaddressed.
To question the APA’s
insistence that psychological suffering was always the result of brain
pathology was to deny that the brain could malfunction at all.
“It should be recognized that mental
disorders are by no means a modern construct,” Regier wrote. “Psychiatric
disorders have existed since the beginning of recorded history.”
Regier didn’t offer any evidence for this
extravagant claim, nor did he try to square it with his insistence in other
venues that psychiatric disorders were constructs that clinicians reified at
their own peril. But then again, he probably thought he was saying something
nonextravagant (and self-evident): that mental suffering has always existed,
and that throughout recorded history it has only been awaiting psychiatrists
like him to elucidate the gene-environmental interactions that triggered the
brain pathology that causes it. But to think there could be psychiatric
disorders before there were psychiatrists, to think the only way to understand
our suffering is as an illness to be cured by doctors, is to ignore the fact
that for thousands of years of recorded history, people thought that mania and
psychosis and depression and anxiety were the mark of the prophet, or
manifestations of sin or witchcraft or devil possession, or just the nature of
life in a fallen world. It is also to overlook the failure of psychiatry, at
least so far, to prove that it is the proper venue for understanding and
treating what we have come to think of as mental illness. And to think, after
all the failures of the DSM to develop an accurate taxonomy, that this time it
will be different, that only naysayers and dead-enders and other benighted
miscreants could possibly believe that recasting sin or possession or
witchcraft as illness is anything other than the mark of progress—well, that is
the province of people who, as Herman Melville once wrote, despite “previous failures18,
still cherish expectations with regard to some mode of infallibly discovering
the heart of man.”
These people, Melville observed, are like
the mathematicians who “in spite of seeming discouragement . . . are yet in
hopes of hitting upon an exact method of determining the longitude.” But other
scientists maintain this optimism, including, Melville wrote, “earnest
psychologists.” He probably didn’t mean to slight psychiatrists. It’s just that
he wrote the novel in 1857, which is long after the beginning of recorded
history, but only a few years past psychiatry’s emergence as a profession, and
long before it began to try, despite seeming discouragement, to enshrine its
infallible understanding of mental suffering in the pages of a book.
• • •
Melville’s observation comes
in his last novel, The Confidence-Man. In it, a
colossal swindler embarks on a riverboat on an April Fool’s Day and proceeds to
take advantage of the passengers’ credulity and greed. It’s a novel about
trust—the reader’s as well as the passengers’—which Melville advises his
readers to place not in psychologists, no matter how earnest, but in novelists,
who, he says, can give us the same knowledge of the twists of our nature that a
“stranger entering19,
map in hand, Boston town” has of the city’s crooked streets. But Melville, ever
the ironist, won’t let us forget that we place confidence in the novelist at
our own peril. He is anything but earnest; whatever truth he depicts emerges
from the elaborate lie of a fictive world. Even his publisher was in on the
joke: The Confidence-Man hit the streets on April 1.
The APA has books to sell, too. But it
doesn’t have the luxury of calling attention to its own fictions and chalking
them up to art. It can’t say with Melville that “he who, in view of its
inconsistencies, says of human nature . . . that it is past finding out,
thereby evinces a better appreciation of it than he who, by always representing
it in a clear light, leaves it to be inferred that he clearly knows all about
it.” Neither can it afford Melville’s arch awareness of the fallibility of all
claims to knowledge about the human heart, about the dangers of placing our
confidence in anyone’s book about us. So don’t look for the DSM to be published
on April Fool’s Day. And, despite the fact that it is full of fictive
placeholders, don’t expect the APA to suggest that booksellers shelve it with
the likes of The Confidence-Man.
Which doesn’t mean psychiatrists are above
the open and intentional use of fiction, at least not when it comes to
inventing mental disorders. Indeed, storytelling was central to at least one
DSM-5 proposal: to add a diagnosis called Hebephilia to the sexual disorders
chapter. Don’t feel bad if you’ve never heard of Hebephilia, which is what Ray
Blanchard—the Canadian doctor who incurred the wrath of the transgendered—calls
the attraction of grown-ups to kids in early adolescence. According to Blanchard,
lead author of a paper calling for including Hebephilia in the DSM, even among
professionals there is a “general resistance
or indifference20 to the adoption of a technical
vocabulary for erotic age-preferences.” Clinicians are more likely to have
heard of “granny porn” than of gerontophilia,
Blanchard said, and hardly anyone uses teleiophilia to
talk about “the erotic preference for people between the ages of physical
maturity and physical decline”—this despite the fact that, as Blanchard noted
with some apparent bitterness, “the word normal has
been off-limits for describing erotic interests for decades.”
Blanchard wanted to overcome this
resistance, at least when it comes to hebephilia, because he thought it was a “discriminable erotic age-preference21.”
Some men, in other words, have that underlying pattern of arousal necessary to
making a diagnosis. They are turned on by kids on the threshold of adulthood
more than by anyone else. He can say this with some authority because he and
his colleagues examined 2,591 men, most of them convicted sex offenders, in
order to determine what aroused them.
This is where the storytelling comes in.
The scientists provided the men with audiovisual aids—large pictures of naked
young people, ranging in age from five to twenty-six, displayed on a triptych
in front of them, and, piped in through headphones, fictional narratives of
sexual situations involving people whose ages roughly corresponded to the
pictures on display. The men sat in easy chairs, looked at the pictures, and
listened to the tales, one of which started this way:
Your neighbors’ 7-year-old girl22 is staying
overnight at your place. You tell her it is time to get ready for bed. She asks
if you will come and tuck her in. When you go to her room, she is already
between the covers. You bend over to kiss her on the forehead, but she wraps
her arms around your neck and pushes her mouth against yours. Giggling, she
throws back the covers to show you she is naked. You sink to the bed, tenderly
pressing your lips against the little groove between her legs.
Okay, it’s not Melville. It’s not even Fifty Shades of Grey. But the researchers weren’t asking the
men for their critical opinion of the stories. Actually, they weren’t asking
the men anything at all, at least not in the usual meaning of that word. They
were asking their penises. Sex offenders, especially convicted sex offenders (who
were Blanchard’s subjects) lie. But penises do not—mostly, however, because
they do not talk. But Blanchard had a solution to this problem: the volumetric
plethysmograph, or, as I like to call it, the Penis Whisperer.
The way it works is that the subject sits
down in an easy chair. He slips a glass cylinder over his penis. After he pulls
a sheet over himself “to minimize his
embarrassment23,” a rubber cuff at the open end of
the tube is inflated until it seals against the shaft of his penis. A hose
attached to the bottle leads to a pressure transducer, which registers the
slightest change in air pressure in the sealed cylinder—like, say, the kind
that would be caused by a swelling penis. By mapping the behavior of the
bottled-up penis onto the pictures and stories provided to its owner,
researchers could chart the true course of a man’s desires.
But before they could say much about
whether the readings meant the men were hebephiles, the scientists had to know
which phallometric stimulus category the objects of
desire belonged in. To do this, they relied on the Tanner scale, an instrument
that uses criteria like breast size, scrotum color, and pubic hair texture to
rate the development of each photographic subject on a five-point scale. Having
split the pubic hairs, Blanchard and his team were able to use the
plethysmograph readings to prove that some men indeed show a strong preference
for pubescent kids as defined by Tanner (breasts: 2.67; pubic hair growth: 2.33
[girls] 3.33 [boys]; genital development 3.83), most of whom were between
eleven and fourteen years old. From this consistent response, they concluded
that “hebephilia exists24
and . . . that it is relatively common compared with other forms of erotic
interests in children.” Which meant that the DSM-5 should either expand
Pedophilia to include “erotic attraction to pubescent . . . children, or,
alternatively, add a separate diagnosis of Hebephilia.”
But wait a minute!
you’re probably saying to yourself—that is, if you weren’t so creeped out by
this research that you stopped reading. Did it really take doctors poring over
pictures of naked kids, showing them to men while whispering erotica into their
ears, and charting their penises’ responses to prove that men can be attracted
to kids in the bloom of youth? Have they not heard of Humbert Humbert? Or read Death in Venice or Plato’s Symposium?
Or maybe just grazed the ads of the most recent issue of Vogue
or the celeb photo spreads in People? Have they been
to a shopping mall recently? Did they really just crash through an open door
and claim to have arrived where no one had gone before?
Well, yes. And that’s not all, nor is it
the part that Melville might most appreciate. Having infallibly determined the
longitude of men’s penises, Blanchard and his team went on to make what
Melville called “a revelation of human nature on fixed principles”—that the
attraction, when it is to kids at a certain Tanner stage, is an illness.
But for all his charts correlating penile
response to stimulus category and his charts of mean
ipsatized penile response and his tables of Z-score transformations of the
extremum of the curve of blood volume change, Blanchard never says which fixed
principle allows him to conclude that what most states consider statutory rape,
and most people consider flat-out wrong, is a mental illness. He doesn’t even
bother talking about clinical significance, let alone philosophical notions
(and, if he did, he’d have to explain how it goes against natural selection for
men to be attracted to girls whose bodies are advertising fertility in nature’s
neon lights). He seems to think that the charts and tables speak for
themselves, that because he has figured out a way to measure it, a doctor’s
pronouncement that hebephilia exists, coupled with our belief that it is
repellent, ought to be enough to convince us that if this feeling is in a human
heart, then it can only be the symptom of a disease.
Not that it is such a hard sell, this idea
that a person who commits a heinous act is sick, at least not to a public
confident that doctors know what is and isn’t a disease. Diagnoses are
explanations of the otherwise incomprehensible, and to judge from the rates of
Bipolar Disorder among children and antidepressant use among adults, from the
relief that diagnosis brings to people like Michael Carley and Nomi Kaim, from
the speed with which Jared Loughner and Anders Breivik were deemed
schizophrenic, and from the opinion, at least in some quarters, that a better
mental health system would somehow prevent mass shootings in schools and movie
theaters, the market for representing our troubles in psychiatry’s clear light
is strong.
This confidence—the belief that doctors
know all about our suffering—is precious to the APA. It’s what they lost forty
years ago, and what Spitzer worked so hard to restore with a book that looked
scientific. It’s what the organization is really selling when it sells the DSM.
Without this confidence, who will buy the book? And without the book, who will
believe the psychiatrists? And without belief, how will their treatments work?
That’s why it’s one thing for Steve Mirin
and Steve Hyman to acknowledge the book’s shortcomings to each other or for
Kupfer and Regier to insist that its categories aren’t really real, and quite
another for the complaint and criticism to come from Frances or Caplan or the
British Psychological Society. Criticism from the inside can be tolerated and
sanitized and turned into a marketing campaign about the living document. But
criticism from the outside must be repelled with all necessary force, for it
threatens to let the rest of us in on what psychiatrists already know: that
there is no fixed principle for their revelations.
So you really have to wonder why, in the
course of revising the DSM, the APA put that confidence at such great risk. Why
would they suggest turning statutory rape into a mental disorder, or
bereavement into depression, or adolescent eccentricity into psychosis? For
that matter, why would they propose, in a country where a third of the
population is morbidly obese and where food has become the latest preoccupation
of the affluent, to turn “eating, in a discrete period of time, an amount of
food that is definitely larger than most people would eat in a similar period
of time under similar circumstances,” and “eating until feeling uncomfortably
full” or “when not physically hungry,” and “feeling guilty after overeating”
into Binge Eating Disorder? Why would they propose, in a political and economic
climate that offers no end of worries and occasions for despair, that people
who are anxious and blue, but whose symptoms do not rise to the level of either
Major Depression or Generalized Anxiety Disorder, should not be deprived of a
diagnosis but instead should be said to suffer from Mixed Anxiety-Depression
(which is a pretty clunky name until you consider its acronym)? Why would they
propose with a straight face to a society of iSlaves that there is such a thing
as Internet Use Disorder? Don’t they grasp just how fragile confidence is?
I can’t really answer that question. But I
will point out that the APA wouldn’t be the first American corporation to
overplay its hand. It’s happened to the best of them—General Motors, Kodak,
Xerox, and all those other companies that suffered disruption and failure when
they failed to remember what the confidence man must never forget: that
confidence is always built on air, and that when it becomes known that what you
are offering isn’t what you’ve cracked it up to be, your brand might lose its
allure, and your company might lose its franchise.
Chapter 16
Early in
August 2011, an “Important Notice” appeared on the DSM-5 website. It was from
the DSM-5 field trials team and addressed to DSM-5 field trials participants.
“Have our e-mails been reaching you?” it asked.
As it happened, I hadn’t heard from the
team since the end of February, when I got a note from Regier and Kupfer
professing their “delight” at my acceptance as a clinician in the field trials
and promising more details soon. In the meantime, however, I’d heard (from Bill
Narrow) that my Wired article about the revision
hadn’t played any better at the APA than it had with Frances. So when no news
had come by July, I figured that maybe the delight had worn off and that the
DSM leadership had come to the same conclusion as Donna Manning had—that
allowing me into the field trials was like “letting the plague rat onto the
ship.” (I think she meant this in a good way.)
But the silence turned out not to be about
me at all. “We are . . . test piloting1
the training materials,” the team explained after I e-mailed in July asking for
an update. They added that they hoped to have them out “in a few weeks.”
A few weeks later, however, the only thing
the APA had out was the Important Notice, which offered a new explanation for
having been incommunicado. This time the problem was about me, sort of.
The most common reason2 for this is
because our emails are being blocked by your email server’s Spam filter. If you
have not received any recent (i.e., within the past 2 months) email
communications from the APA regarding field trial participation, please be sure
to check your Spam or junk mail folder and look for any communications from us.
I wondered if the team had capitalized
“Spam” out of deference to Hormel Foods, one copyright holder to another. I
also wondered why they didn’t just put the information that we had supposedly
missed right into the notice. I can’t say with certainty that the team was
resorting to the excuse that all of us have used at one time or another to
explain our dilatory e-mail habits, but I was sure of one thing: there were no
messages from the APA trapped in my spam filter. Neither had any e-mails made
their way to Michael First or Dayle Jones, both of whom had also signed up—or,
according to Jones, to any of the would-be volunteers she knew.
In early September, when I still hadn’t
gotten the errant messages, or anything at all, I e-mailed Eve Moscicki, the
APA researcher in charge of the clinician field trials, asking when I might
hear from her team and when the trial might begin. The next day her office sent
an apology and the password I needed to log in to the REDCap website. I also
received a separate apology directly from Moscicki. She explained, “We have learned3
that some security settings automatically delete our e-mails and the recipient
never sees them.” She didn’t say why the APA couldn’t figure out how to do what
every Viagra dealer and Nigerian scamster seemed to know how to do. (I did pass
along my skepticism to Moscicki, pointing out that no one seemed to have
received anything and suggesting that the problem might be at her end. “Thanks for your candid note4,”
she wrote back. “Much appreciated.”)
I went to the Vanderbilt site. My password
and login didn’t work. Ten days, and many e-mails later, I was finally able to
sign in. Just a day after that, the APA finally figured how to get an e-mail
blast past all those spam filters. It was another
note from Kupfer and Regier5, congratulating
me, once again, on being accepted into the program. They didn’t acknowledge
that it had been five months since they first did that, and a full year since
the APA announced the start of field trials. They did, however, give me my
official title—Collaborating Investigator—and assigned a new significance to
this “unique opportunity”: it would be, they promised, “one of the most
important psychiatric research studies of this decade.” And if that wasn’t
reward enough, they were also offering fifteen continuing education credits, my
name in the DSM-5, and a free copy of the book, whenever it came out.
• • •
One part of my training had
already begun. As Bill Narrow had explained at the APA meeting, and as the team
reminded us, we Collaborating Investigators were supposed to “familiarize”
ourselves with the revisions by poring over the website, paying attention to
the diagnoses we were most likely to render.
This was a tough assignment. The changes
were many and complex. Here, for instance, is the DSM-5 proposal for Generalized Anxiety Disorder6
(GAD), a diagnosis most of us collaborators were likely to use, as it stood in
June 2011.
A.
Excessive anxiety and worry (apprehensive expectation) about two (or more)
domains of activities or events (e.g., family, health, finances, and
school/work difficulties).
B.
The excessive anxiety and worry occurs on more days than not, for 3 months or
more.
C.
The anxiety and worry are associated with one or more of the following
symptoms:
1.
restlessness or feeling keyed up or on edge
2.
muscle tension
D.
The anxiety and worry are associated with one (or more) of the following
behaviors:
1.
marked avoidance of activities or events with possible negative outcomes
2.
marked time and effort preparing for activities or events with possible
negative outcomes
3.
marked procrastination in behavior or decision-making due to worries
4.
repeatedly seeking reassurance due to worries
E.
The disturbance causes clinically significant distress or impairment in social,
occupational, or other important areas of functioning.
F.
The disturbance is not attributable to the direct physiological effects of a
substance (e.g., a drug of abuse, a medication) or another medical condition
(e.g., hyperthyroidism).
G.
The disturbance is not better accounted for by another mental disorder (e.g.,
anxiety about Panic Attacks in Panic Disorder, negative evaluation in Social
Anxiety Disorder, contamination or other obsessions in Obsessive-Compulsive
Disorder, separation from attachment figures in Separation Anxiety Disorder,
reminders of traumatic events in Posttraumatic Stress Disorder, gaining weight
in Anorexia Nervosa, physical complaints in Somatic Symptom Disorder, perceived
appearance flaws in Body Dysmorphic Disorder, or having a serious illness in
Illness Anxiety Disorder).
And here is the old one7:
A.
Excessive anxiety and worry (apprehensive expectation), occurring more days
than not for at least 6 months, about a number of events or activities (such as
work or school performance).
B.
The person finds it difficult to control the worry.
C.
The anxiety and worry are associated with three (or more) of the following six
symptoms (with at least some symptoms present for more days than not for the
past 6 months). Note: Only one item is required in children.
1.
Restlessness or feeling keyed up or on edge
2.
Being easily fatigued
3.
Difficulty concentrating or mind going blank
4.
Irritability
5.
Muscle tension
6.
Sleep disturbance (difficulty falling or staying asleep, or restless
unsatisfying sleep)
D.
The focus of the anxiety and worry is not confined to features of an Axis I
disorder, e.g., the anxiety or worry is not about having a Panic Attack (as in
Panic Disorder), being embarrassed in public (as in Social Phobia), being
contaminated (as in Obsessive-Compulsive Disorder), being away from home or
close relatives (as in Separation Anxiety Disorder), gaining weight (as in
Anorexia Nervosa), having multiple physical complaints (as in Somatization
Disorder), or having a serious illness (as in Hypochondriasis), and the anxiety
and worry do not occur exclusively during Posttraumatic Stress Disorder.
E.
The anxiety, worry, or physical symptoms cause clinically significant distress
or impairment in social, occupational, or other important areas of functioning.
F.
The disturbance is not due to the direct physiological effects of a substance
(e.g., a drug of abuse, a medication) or a general medical condition (e.g.,
hyperthyroidism) and does not occur exclusively during a Mood Disorder, a
Psychotic Disorder, or a Pervasive Developmental Disorder.
The APA didn’t make it easy for us to see
the differences by placing the diagnoses side by side or creating a chart or,
for that matter, just using their word processor’s Track Changes command as
Michael First had in Honolulu. And there were many changes. Six months of worry
had become three. Fatigue, difficulty concentrating, irritability, and sleep
troubles were out, while avoidance, procrastination, reassurance seeking, and
“marked time and effort preparing for activities or events with possible
negative outcomes” (think Mrs. Dalloway) were in. The threshold had been
changed from three out of six Criterion C symptoms to one out of two Criterion
C and one out of four Criterion D symptoms. “A number of events” that are the
subject of worry has become “two or more domains of activities or events.” And
so on.
The good news was that I hadn’t ever
committed the old criteria to memory, so at least I wouldn’t have to unlearn
them. I was, however, going to have to get accustomed to using criteria to make
the diagnosis in the first place. That’s not something anyone I know in this
business actually does. Mostly we’re content to find a label that matches
people in some vague way and then get on with the business of helping them
figure out what’s going on in their lives that landed them in our offices.
There are exceptions, of course. Take the
psychiatrist I will call Dr. Benway. He’s a respected practitioner in my neighborhood
to whom I had referred a young woman I’ll call Charlotte. She was thirty-two
years old, the daughter of Chinese immigrants, and recently divorced. I’d been
seeing her for a little more than a year, and she had just begun to talk about
the way her father used to crawl into bed with her and, as the rest of the
family slept, force her to have sex with him. She hadn’t told anyone about this
before, and she was unraveling in the way people often do when they start to
take apart the finely built edifice behind which they’ve hidden their shame and
fear and rage. Charlotte was also in the midst of a huge project at work, one
that she needed to complete if she was going to keep her job. So it was not a
good time for her to be anxious all day and sleepless at night. She had asked
me if I could help her get a prescription for Valium from someone other than
her family doctor, to whom she did not want to have to explain herself, and
that’s where Dr. Benway got involved.
Returning to me after her visit, she told
me that he had given her an antidepressant and a mood stabilizer for her
depression and suggested that she try a stimulant for her ADHD; he told her
they would explore that possibility more when she returned to him the following
week. “Do you think I have ADHD?” she asked.
I told her I did not think she met the
criteria.
“Then why would he say that?” she asked.
“And why did he prescribe Zoloft and Abilify? Do you think I have depression?”
She told me about the psychological tests she’d filled out as part of her
paperwork for Dr. Benway, the ones that asked her about different thoughts and
feelings she’d had over the last weeks or month. Then she asked, “What is my
diagnosis anyway?”
I tried the therapist’s usual evasions,
asking her why she wanted to know and what it meant to her to have her
professional parent figures disagreeing about her and what it was like for her
to think her therapist didn’t know what he was talking about. But she wouldn’t
be dissuaded. This was the first time Charlotte had ever been demanding in this
way—direct and forthright and confident—and even if it was a demand I was
poorly equipped to meet, I felt that I had to meet it. So I fessed up.
“You don’t have one,” I said.
“Why not?”
I explained that therapy, not unlike
medication, was really targeted at symptoms, not illnesses, and to the extent
that we were surely trying to get at what lay underneath the symptoms, the
DSM’s labels and criteria were not particularly helpful toward that goal, that
they renamed her suffering without explaining it.
I didn’t tell Charlotte I’d stolen that
line from William James. I also didn’t tell her the other reason I hadn’t given
her a diagnosis. But I did tell Dr. Benway, because when I called him (to
pester him on her behalf to prescribe the Valium so she could sleep, and maybe
to chide him for the cocktail he’d mixed for her), the first thing he asked was
what her diagnosis was.
“She doesn’t use insurance,” I said. “So
she doesn’t have one.”
This could have been Dr. Benway’s moment
to go Gregory House on me, to reveal the sign I had missed and the diagnosis it
led to, to question how I could possibly treat someone in the absence of a
diagnosis. He didn’t do any of this, however. I’m not sure why. It may be
because our clinician communication—about Charlotte’s current functioning, her
anxiety, her insomnia and difficulty concentrating, her mood swings—didn’t seem
hampered by the fact that we weren’t using the language scientifically proven
to make our conversation reliable. It may be because when he explained the
cocktail he’d prescribed—the way the Abilify/Zoloft combo could “put a floor
under her” without agitating her and how adding Ritalin to the mix might just
get her neurotransmitters all nicely balanced—I didn’t point out to him that
his opportunity to medicate Charlotte exceeded anyone’s knowledge about any of
that. Truce, standoff, going along to get along: Dr. Benway’s silence about my
diagnostic negligence and mine about his diagnostic exuberance could have been
any of those. But somehow I think it might be something else entirely—that we
both knew the truth of what I had said: In the absence of an incentive, who
would bother with a diagnosis?
• • •
But now that I am a
Collaborating Investigator, perhaps I should consider giving Charlotte a
diagnosis. The DSM-5 with which I am supposed to familiarize myself offers all
sorts of possibilities. GAD, for example, with its markeds
and excessives providing all kinds of wiggle room for
the insurance-dependent, is, despite its many changes, an obvious choice. Major
Depressive Disorder has been left mostly alone (other than the absence of the
bereavement exclusion, and, no matter what the new criteria said, if presented
with a grieving patient, I’m going to pretend to be astute and not add the
insult of a diagnosis to the injury of a bereavement), and if Charlotte doesn’t
reach its five-of-nine threshold, there is always what has been called
Dysthymia in DSM-IV and what the DSM-5 proposes to call Chronic Depression, a
two-of-six offering. Adjustment Disorder with Mixed Anxiety and Depressed Mood
calls for no more than six months to elapse between the psychosocial stressor
to which the patient is adjusting poorly and the onset of symptoms, but if I
decide that the stressor is Charlotte’s disclosure of the incest and not the
incest itself, then that diagnosis would work just fine.
But there’s another possibility in the
DSM, one that doesn’t ask me to look for the symptoms of ersatz diseases, but
to pay attention to what Charlotte actually brings into my office: herself.
Because Charlotte may be anxious and depressed and failing to adjust, but she
is also the kind of person who arrives late for her appointment and then, as
the clock approaches the end of her time, says, “You’re not going to throw me
out of here now, are you?”
I tell her that we have to stop at the
usual time, regardless of when we started. “Why does that feel like being
thrown out?” I ask her.
“I can’t believe it. I killed myself to
get here on time. Really, almost. I drove like eighty miles an hour. I can’t
help it if the traffic was bad,” she says. “And anyway, what’s so important
that you have to do?”
I don’t answer.
Her voice rises. “You don’t care about me,
any more than a whore cares about a john,” she says. “And why would you? This
is just your job. But why would anyone listen to me if it wasn’t their job?
Look at me.” She sweeps her hand along her body, like a salesman demonstrating
his product. “I’m fat and ugly and disgusting.” (She is actually trim and
pretty, but this isn’t the moment to tell her that.) She has been fiddling with
her hair the whole session, but now she’s tearing at it with such force that I
can hear it ripping from her scalp and see strands falling onto the couch. “And
you just pretend, and you’re not very good at it. You can’t wait to get rid of
me.”
Which, at that moment, you wouldn’t blame
me for saying, is sort of true.
That’s how Charlotte wants me to feel:
like she feels, unloved and uncertain of herself and the others around her. And
now that she’s landed her blow, she’s pulling even more frantically at her
hair. “Okay, I get it. I’ll go,” she says. “And you don’t want me to come back,
do you?” She rummages angrily in her purse, pulls out her checkbook, scrawls
the check. But she is not only rebuking me. She’s also imploring me to assure
her that her outburst hasn’t made me want to kick her out or punish her for
being mean. Having made herself unlikable, she’s waiting for me to tell her
that I like her.
Now, I might not go that far, but on the
other hand, I didn’t kick her out of therapy. I’ll take a lot. Not because I’m
a saint, but because this is what she is paying for: not indulgence exactly,
but acceptance, the peculiar kind of love conveyed when I stand back from the
action and participate in it at the same time, when I watch Charlotte flail and
let her land her blows and respond to the pain she inflicts without taking it
personally. And what I’m seeing when Charlotte is launching her attacks on both
of us is not a disease. Neither is it an assortment of symptoms. It’s who she
is, her character, forged out of the crucible of the family, that strange
little enclave where we raise our young, each on our own, behind closed doors
or in homes where, if you were lucky, there were the resources and the courage
and the love that it takes to send a person into the world more or less intact,
but if you were not lucky, if your parents were like Charlotte’s, so distracted
by the exigencies of life in a strange new country, or so adept at ignoring
what they could not afford to acknowledge, that a father could see his daughter
as a sexual object and a mother could turn a blind eye—a lapse made even more
unlikely, and yet somehow more inevitable, by the fact that the mother and her
mother’s mother, as Charlotte found out recently, also grew up in incestuous
families—if all those stars lined up and crossed you, then you too might have
come to think that the disgusting thing that was happening was happening
because you were disgusting, so disgusting that no one would care what was
being done to you, you too might have figured that the best you could do was to
shut up and take your lumps, and you too might have been seething all the time
you were submitting. You might have been left desperate for love, and sure that
you’d found it, until one little thing—an encounter with the tyranny of the
therapist’s clock, his exercise of power over you, his disregard for your
wishes—leaves you raging and unable to do anything but pour out the rage in a
way that gets you rejected, unable to stop yourself, even as you watch yourself
tumble, for maybe the millionth time, through that trap door in yourself and
land in your own self-hatred.
Or you could be like the man whom
Charlotte had married—Joe, I’ll call him. I met the two of them together when
they came to see me about two years before the conversation I just described
took place. Actually, they weren’t supposed to see me as a couple. Joe—eight
years older, tall, good-looking, a wealthy businessman who wore his success on
his monogrammed, gold-cuff-linked sleeve—had been referred by his lawyer, who
thought it would look good to the judge if he was in counseling when his case
came up. Of course, the lawyer didn’t put it that way. He just said something
like “This guy could really use to be seen, if you follow my logic.”
It was hard to argue with that. Joe had
been arrested after he’d punched a parking lot attendant in the face. He
thought the worker had shown insufficient respect when he’d told Joe he
couldn’t park where he wanted to. “Like it really mattered. Fucking moron!” Joe
told me soon after he sat down, and before I’d had a chance to ask about the
incident.
“That’s why you coldcocked him?” I asked.
“Because he was a moron? Or just because he told you what to do?”
“Look, the space was empty. If he had bothered
to think about it, if he wasn’t just going by some other stupid fuck’s stupid
rules, then he would not have been hassling me,” he said. “It’s what’s ruining
the country, the way people just follow rules without thinking, without
figuring out if they should make an exception.”
“And he should have made an exception for
you?”
“Of course he should have. I could have
fit my car in there without any trouble. I know how to drive, for chrissakes.
Any swinging dick can get into a car and step on the gas. But I’ve been
trained. I did one of those week-long courses for Mercedes owners.”
Five minutes with this guy and I was
already hating him. I changed the subject.
“Whose idea was it for Charlotte to come
today?” I’d been surprised to discover her in the waiting room, the two of them
perfectly dressed and groomed, flipping through back issues of Home & Garden. I was even more surprised when she
followed him into my office.
“Both of us,” Joe said.
“But you didn’t tell me you wanted to
bring your wife with you when you made the appointment.”
“Why? Is that a rule of yours?”
I guess I hadn’t changed the subject after
all.
After I didn’t answer, Charlotte spoke up.
“Actually, it was my idea to come. Joe was so upset about getting arrested and
all, and then it got worse when he heard he had to come here. I thought there
were certain things you needed to know, because you’d get totally the wrong
idea if all you knew was that he’d punched some random dude. I thought you
needed to know that Joe is a special guy, and how well he can treat people.”
She put her hand on his knee.
“Don’t you think Joe can speak for
himself?” I asked.
“Of course I can,” he said. “But I thought
you would need proof that I wasn’t that kind of man.”
“Okay, well, it is a rule of mine. Not
that spouses can’t be here, but that if you are here as a couple, then we’re
going to be talking about your marriage or something like that. A joint
business, a problem with your kid, a disagreement about your in-laws, or that
you just can’t get along. But not as a character witness. My understanding,” I
said to Charlotte, “is that Joe is here because he’s had this fight and this
arrest,” and then I turned to Joe to say, “My guess is that this isn’t the
first time someone who failed to appreciate you took it on the chin, Joe.”
“So what are you saying?”
“That if what you want to do is to figure
out why this kind of thing happens to you, other than the fact that everyone
else in the world is a moron, and what you can do about it besides punch their
lights out, or why you are so afraid that everyone is going to dislike you,
then I’m your guy. But if what you want is for me to help you or your lawyer
win a case, or to make you feel like you deserve to be able to assault people,
then I’m not. Because I’m sure there are reasons you feel that way, but I don’t
think you deserve that.”
Joe stared at me for a second, probably
the same way he stared at the kid in the parking lot. He stood up, pulled a
money clip out of his pocket, tore off a hundred-dollar bill, and dropped it on
my desk. “This ought to cover it,” he said. “I’ll tell my lawyer to find
someone who can help.” Without a word, Charlotte stood up, too, and the two of
them breezed out of my office. I can’t say I was sorry to see them go.
When she called me about a year later to
tell me Joe had left her for a twenty-two-year-old woman and she needed to see
me (“Because you were right,” she said. “You nailed what an asshole he was”),
Charlotte was in the kind of agony that goes along with being a self, with
having no choice but to be at the center of your world, and of finding nothing
there but fear and self-loathing. But even as she began to get over Joe, and to
understand that there is only the slightest difference between fitting another
person like a hand fits a glove and sharing a pair of handcuffs, the anxiety
and depression didn’t go away. They seemed less and less related to what had
happened with Joe, more like the inevitable if regrettable outgrowth of who she
was.
So I could diagnose her with GAD or
MDD—she more or less fit those criteria—just as I could have diagnosed Joe, had
he stuck around, with Intermittent Explosive Disorder, for he was surely a
walking IED. But diagnoses like these don’t quite seem to do Charlotte or Joe
justice, especially not when it seems so clear that what they suffered from
wasn’t anything like the kind of illness that comes and goes like the common
cold, or comes and stays like diabetes. Troubles such as theirs seem to arise
out of their troubled selves. And as it happens, there is an entire section in
the DSM devoted to describing those troubles, which the book calls personality disorders and defines this way:
A Personality Disorder is an enduring pattern8
of inner experience and behavior that deviates markedly from the expectations
of the individual’s culture, is pervasive and inflexible, has an onset in
adolescence or early adulthood, is stable over time, and leads to distress or
impairment.
The ten personality disorders listed in
the DSM come last in the book. They also have their own diagnostic duchy, known
as Axis II (as opposed to Axis I, where the rest of the disorders reside). This
segregation, the book explains, “ensures
that consideration will be given9 to the possible
presence of Personality Disorders . . . that might otherwise be overlooked when
attention is directed to the usually more florid Axis I disorders.” But I think
the real reason lies in a more fundamental difference between the two axes. An
Axis I disorder is what you have. An Axis II disorder
is what you are. (Personality disorders share Axis II
with mental retardation.)
Despite this crucial difference,
personality disorders look like the other disorders in the DSM. Borderline Personality
Disorder (BPD), for instance, the diagnosis Charlotte would qualify for, is a
five-of-nine affair, with criteria like “frantic efforts to avoid real or
imagined abandonment” and “markedly and persistently unstable self-image or
sense of self.” Narcissistic Personality Disorder (NPD), another five-of-niner
(including “grandiose sense of self-importance,” “sense of entitlement,” and
need for “excessive admiration”), matches Joe pretty well. (And it’s not at all
rare to find a borderline married to a narcissist.) But you can’t miss the
Freudian echoes in these disorders. Borderline refers
to the border between neurosis and psychosis, and narcissistic
is a nod to Freud’s observation that some people treat the world as a
mirror that they must shatter when they don’t like what it reflects.
But even if the names weren’t a dead
giveaway, it would be impossible to conceal the fact that personality disorders
are a throwback to the Freudian conviction that our suffering reveals the
neurotic shape into which our timber is twisted by the psychosexual
catastrophes of childhood and the impossible demands of society, and that
treatment always involves a reckoning with those forces and the person they
have made us.
The presence of personality disorders in
the DSM preserves this old, officially out-of-fashion idea that personality
underlies our difficulties. The book never comes out and says so, but Allen
Frances wrote the personality disorders section of the DSM, and he’ll tell you
unabashedly that this is the case. “I think
this is the best way10 to see and treat most disorders,”
he said. (Although it’s not the best way to get paid for treating them.
Insurance companies don’t generally reimburse for those diagnoses, so even if
you think that’s what you’re treating, you can’t tell them that.) But Frances
was trained in those olden days, before the demands of science required
psychiatry to distance itself from Freud by divorcing its account of our
afflictions from their causes. It is as if the psychiatrists of his generation,
the ones who saved their profession by meeting those demands, could not quite
let go of the idea that who we are matters, and kept that thought alive on Axis
II.
• • •
As Freud himself might have
predicted, smuggling psychoanalysis into a DSM that claimed authority by
purging it has created an internal conflict that yields no end of trouble.
“I have
never really been a doctor11 in the proper sense,” Freud wrote.
That may be why in all his talk of neuroses and psychoses, complexes
and symptoms, defenses and resistances, he remained
uninterested in carving the psyche at its joints by naming its afflictions. He
mostly ignored Kraepelin (who was a contemporary of his) and his parsing of
mental disorders from one another. (Although he was pleased to pick up one of
Kraepelin’s patients, Sergei Pankejeff, and turn him into the Wolf Man, title
character of one of his most gripping case studies.) We all have parents, we
all live stretched between instinct and conscience, between memory and desire,
between brutality and civilization, so we all suffer degrees of the same
illness; to have a personality is always to at least flirt with neurosis.
So in the Freudian view, all personalities
are more or less disordered. Which is exactly what led to those 85 percent
prevalence rates, to the reliability crises, and ultimately to the suspicion
that psychiatry may not belong in medicine. As problematic as the DSM’s
response has become when it comes to Axis I disorders, with its categories and
criteria and axes, its at least three months and its three out of six symptoms, it still works, as long as you
limit your definition of works to achieves
reliability under ideal conditions. But personality disorders have never
worked even in that limited sense. “They
have the lowest reliability12 of any major
category in the book,” Frances, who served on the DSM-III personality disorders
work group, told me. (The kappas were .56 to
.6513.) And he’s been saying so for a long time. Within a
few months of the publication of DSM-III in 1980, he was telling readers of the
American Journal of Psychiatry that “the personality disorders are not at all
clearly distinct14 from normal functioning or from
each other,” which is why they were significantly harder for clinicians to
distinguish reliably than Axis I disorders were.
In that paper, and in one he wrote two
years later, Frances suggested an alternative approach to personality
disorders. “Rather than being diagnosed15
within one or another distinct personality type,” he wrote, “the patient might
be rated (perhaps on a scale of 1 to 10) for each personality characteristic.”
People don’t have BPD so much as they are anxious about abandonment, impulsive,
and entitled—qualities they share more with people who might qualify for, say,
NPD than with people whose personalities are less troublesome. Long before
Darrel Regier proposed dimensional diagnosis for DSM-5, Frances was suggesting
exactly that, at least for the personality disorders.
When he started work on DSM-IV, Frances
said, a dimensionalized personality disorders section was one of his goals. He
said that he recruited Thomas Widiger as the DSM-IV research coordinator in
part because he was a “committed
dimensionalist16” and that he urged the work group
to come up with an alternative to the categorical approach. “We worked hard to
forge a consensus that could inform a simple DSM-IV proposal,” he said. “But we
failed. We couldn’t reach agreement on how to rate the factors.” The process
devolved into those pointless arguments he’d wanted to avoid—“the distinctions
without differences that bedevil the field.”
Widiger remembers it differently. He’s not
so sure Frances hired him for his dimensionalist expertise—“I believe I was chosen17
to be the research coordinator because I was hardworking, conscientious,
familiar with meta-analyses, and had collaborated with Allen many years before
DSM-IV,” he told me, adding that only two of the one hundred projects he worked
on concerned dimensions. And, he says, the problem was not really the result of
contention among the troops but a failure of the general to bring them
together. “There were advocates of different models,” but the same was true
when DSM-III was written, “and that didn’t stop Spitzer from coming up with a
compromise among them. If you recognize that the field needs to shift to a
dimensional model, you can easily address the differences of opinion.”
Twenty years later, Widiger was still mystified
by Frances’s waffling, especially in light of his long history of advocacy for
a dimensional approach. But Frances was committed to making changes only in the
presence of incontrovertible evidence. By that principle, if the work group
couldn’t resolve its own arguments, the only conclusion was that dimensions
weren’t ready for the DSM, at least not his DSM. No matter how wrongheaded he
thought the existing model was, no matter how long he’d been advocating for a
different one, in the end he had to settle for the tepid observation, made in a
section tacked on to the introduction to the personality disorders, that
dimensional models were “under active
investigation18,” and for a paper, published just before DSM-IV19
came out, suggesting that it was only a matter of time before personality
disorders were diagnosed dimensionally. The nosological conservative had been
hoist with his own petard.
• • •
Widiger thought he was going
to get another chance. He was the sole personality disorders expert in the
research planning conferences organized by Michael First in 2000. First was
also an advocate of dimensions. “Patients have just one personality,” he wrote
in a paper that set the DSM-5 research agenda for personality disorders. “It might be more consistent20
. . . to indicate that a patient has one personality disorder, characterized by
the presence of a variety of maladaptive personality traits.” He went on to
suggest a seven-point plan for implementing a dimensional approach in the
DSM-5.
First pointed out that much of the work
had already been done. Just as Spitzer had drawn on years of research into
diagnostic criteria in fashioning his first proposals, so too would-be DSM
reformers could turn to any number of dimensional models of personality as a
starting point. There was Cloninger’s Tridimensional Personality Questionnaire
and Timothy Leary’s (yes, that Timothy Leary)
Interpersonal Circumplex, the Big Five and the 16-PF, the DAPP and the SNAP and
the SWAP. They differed in many ways, but they were all attempts to find the
basic building blocks of personality, and then to show how individuals emerge
as different agglomerations of those factors. The 16-PF, for instance,
identifies sixteen source traits that are derived from
42 clusters, which were refined from 171 groups, which in turn were reduced
from the four thousand or so adjectives in Webster’s
that describe facets of personality, and the Big Five, also known as the Five
Factor Model, claims that all those adjectives can be placed under one of five
domains—openness to experience, conscientiousness,
extraversion, agreeableness,
and neuroticism. An individual personality, according
to this theory, is the unique mix of these common qualities.
No matter how they are counted and named,
these factors are, of course, all reifications. There really is no such thing
as extraversion, even if you know it when you see it, any more than there is
such a thing as Major Depressive Disorder. But these personality models have
all been used extensively. Researchers have developed tests and subtests and
rating scales that can locate people along the dimensions of each model.
They’ve tied the resulting profiles to religious belief and political
affiliation, to drug use and child abuse, to learning styles and patterns of
memory. And, of course, they’ve applied their models to the
personality-disordered, showing how those patients’ troubles can be reliably
attributed to the lack or excess of particular factors.
While the competing personality theories
have generated as much intramural conflict as you might expect, First saw the
proliferation of models as an opportunity for nosology. All that active
investigation had yielded a huge body of concepts and measures from which a
revision could be fashioned. And if the DSM could incorporate this data into
its diagnostic regime, he thought, it could return something vital to the
personality researchers who generated it: a “uniform
classification of general personality functioning21”
that would bring the same kind of order to the field that the DSM-III had
brought to the general classification of mental illness.
As much as everyone had to gain from this
outcome, First didn’t think it would be easy to bring about. “That is why I pushed22
to have the personality research conference take place first,” he told me. “I thought
if they got started working on it within the next year, before work started on
the rest of DSM-5, then maybe they would have it worked out in time.”
That meeting took place late in 2004. Tom
Widiger, who had been part of the 1999 planning conferences, chaired it. Regier, he said, had asked him23
to find a “common ground” among competing personality theories and to fashion a
model for DSM out of them, and he leaped at the chance to finish the work he
felt Frances had abandoned. He searched for the commonalities among them, and
eventually determined that the eighteen leading theories, and all their
different schematics of personality, converged on four domains, each of which
had its own spectrum. According to Widiger’s
distillation24, we are all more or less
extraverted or introverted, constrained or impulsive, emotionally stable or
unstable, and antagonistic or compliant. People whose personalities were
disordered could be thought of as, for instance, too extraverted or too
compliant or not stable or impulsive enough, and thanks to the plethora of
tests available, their location in those domains could be specified. Charlotte
and Joe could thus be diagnosed without recourse to woolly concepts like borderline or narcissism; instead
they could be described in terms of those factors without pretending that they
had separate illnesses.
While he knew this compromise was not a
shoo-in for DSM-5, Widiger was pretty sure that he had given the APA a way to
catch up with the “basic science research25
on general personality structure” and that, given the hunger for a new
approach, it had a good chance for “eventual adoption.” The paradigm shift, at
least when it came to personality disorders, was finally at hand. It wouldn’t
be a move to a nosology based on biomarkers (although there are intriguing
connections between genetics and neurochemistry on the one hand and personality
traits on the other). It wouldn’t entirely solve the problem of reification,
but it would at least rid one section of the DSM of diagnostic categories that
everyone agreed really didn’t make sense and replace them with dimensions,
which nearly everyone agreed were a better way to conceptualize mental illness.
The personality disorders work group—with Widiger at its helm, or so he and
many others thought—would lead psychiatry into the future.
• • •
“The devil, of course26,
could be in the details,” Widiger wrote at the end of his “common ground”
paper. The details he had in mind were scientific, and, given his prominent
position in the field, he figured he would be heading the team that would work
them out. But the details that arose were not scientific at all. In 2005, he
and a colleague began to plan another conference about dimensions in DSM-5.
Three months into those conversations, Widiger discovered that he would not be
invited to that conference. And then, late in 2006, psychiatrist John Livesley,
who had attended the conference, called to tell Widiger that he had just seen
the list of people who would be on the DSM-5 work group. Widiger had gotten the
Michael First treatment—an acknowledged leader in the field, who had done
yeoman service for the APA, who most people thought would get the job, had been
unceremoniously exiled. “Nobody on the work
group27 ever asked for my input or
informed me about what was going on,” Widiger said. He was left to figure it
out from what was posted on the website.
The first proposals Widiger saw appeared
in February 2010. They represented, according to the work group, a “significant
reformulation.” Diagnosis would no longer be a matter of checking the criteria
against the patient. But neither would it be a shift to a purely dimensional
approach. Instead, they proposed a “hybrid” model that required clinicians to
go through a four-step procedure. First, they would use seven criteria, including
identity integration and cooperativeness,
to determine whether the patient had a personality disorder, which was defined
as the failure to develop “a sense of
self-identity28 and the capacity for interpersonal
function.” They would then determine which of five types of
personality disorder (antisocial/psychopathic, avoidant, borderline,
obsessive-compulsive, or schizotypal) the patient had. To figure this out, they
would not use criteria, but instead match the patient to prototypical
descriptions of the disorder. Then they would see which of thirty-seven trait
facets—social withdrawal, for example, or recklessness—nested in six trait
domains, such as negative emotionality and disinhibition, best described the patient.
If the patient didn’t fit one of the types, they would diagnose her with a
personality disorder, and the facets and domains would be used to describe the
disorder further. And finally they would determine how badly disordered the
patient’s personality was by rating it on a scale of one to three along four
dimensions for two different areas of functioning.
Don’t worry if you didn’t get that. Some
hybrids are elegant (think of Priuses or Gala apples). Others are more like
mules. Even if the personality disorders proposal makes sense (and I’m not sure
it does), as a clinician I can assure you that it is way too complicated and
time-consuming for anyone to actually use. More important, however, the
proposal had little if anything to do with all those validated theories and
their measurement instruments that Widiger had labored so hard to integrate
into a single model. The trait facets and domains seemed to bear little
relationship to the long history of research that had once made personality
disorders seem so promising as a game-changer. And the types—well, it was at
least clear where the committee had found them: in the DSM-IV. But they didn’t
explain why they had adopted only five of the original ten personality
disorders.
Actually, they did try to explain. Andrew
Skodol, the work group chair, reported that they had conducted a literature
review and eliminated the five diagnoses that the least amount of research had
been done on. They argued that the lack of studies indicated that these
diagnoses had insufficient “empirical
evidence29 of validity and clinical utility,”
failing to note that absence of evidence was not evidence of absence, that, in
fact, the decision amounted to letting the marketplace decide which diagnoses
should stay and which should go.
Skodol also ventured an explanation for
not simply choosing one of the established personality theories, with its
validated concepts and measures, and instead cobbling together a model that, as
the APA work group noted on the website, was still “pending empirical
validation.” “We knew we couldn’t
incorporate30 anybody’s model in toto,” he told
me, “because the APA wasn’t going to pay royalties” to any copyright holder.
Whatever the rationale, the proposal left
Widiger hopping mad. “The empirical support is a farce,” he wrote in an e-mail
to his colleagues, the section “embarrassingly
bad31.” It would become “the laughingstock of the DSM and
psychiatry,” he predicted. “It’s a monumental mistake.”
Widiger wasn’t alone in being appalled.
John Livesley went public with his charge that the proposal was “a disaster.”
He withdrew his name from the work group’s journal article describing the
changes and published his own dissenting opinion in March 2010, lamenting the
proposal as a “lost opportunity” that
“negates years of progress32 toward a scientific-based
classification system.” In April, Frances called the proposal a “cumbersome hodgepodge33”
whose dimensions were “the favorites of the few members of the work group who
have personal research experience in this area.” The comments submitted to the
website during the spring ran strongly against the proposals. In September, a
group of eight psychiatrists and psychologists, some of the biggest names in
the business, ranging from the ancient psychoanalyst Otto Kernberg to the even
more ancient father of cognitive-behavioral therapy, Aaron Beck, to the upstart
political psychologist Drew Westen, put aside their differences to tell readers
of the American Journal of Psychiatry that the
proposal was “an unwieldy conglomeration34”
whose traits and facets “have not been investigated empirically,” which meant
that the model “no longer rests on the decades of research” that had been “the
chief rationale” for making the change to a dimensional model in the first
place.
In the fall of 2010, the task force staged
what Skodol called an “intervention.” “They hated the prototypes”—the
descriptions of personality disorders that had replaced the criteria. “They
reminded them of DSM-II,” he explained, and they weren’t crazy about the rest
of it, either. “You guys look like outliers,” they told him, as they ordered
the group back to the drawing board—this time with two “consultants”
(“minders,” one committee member called them) to assist in reformulating the
proposals. In a series of weekly phone conferences, chaired not by Skodol but
by one of the consultants, a new proposal was hammered out and a “simplified
and streamlined” proposal was posted on the website in late June. Now there
were five trait domains instead of six, and thirty-one facets instead of
thirty-seven, and six types instead of five. The criteria for those types were
back, reflecting the task force’s mandate to, as Skodol put it, “make the
section look more like the rest of them.”
Skodol took his very public rebuke in
stride. He understood his colleagues’ protests. “I mean, if you had spent your
career studying Dependent Personality Disorder”—one of the five slated for
elimination—“then I can see why you would be upset.” Entire data sets
accumulated over years would have to be mapped onto new categories. In at least
one case—Narcissistic Personality Disorder—the vehemence and volume of the
public comments prevailed over the lack of empirical support, leading the
committee to rescue it, against Skodol’s wishes, from nosological oblivion.
But, he told me, even if this was the “most political” of the decisions, “if
you’re going to welcome comments, it doesn’t make sense not to respond to the
comments.”
Skodol seemed stung about just one aspect
of the “politics.” His group had taken seriously the mandate to switch to a
dimensional system, but “the rest of the work groups didn’t get it, and Darrel
and David were never able to convince them that dimensionality was the way to
go,” he told me. “I don’t think they had quite the clarity of vision that Bob
Spitzer had when he did DSM-III. He had this vision, and he sold it until it
was bought, and I don’t know that Darrel and David ever did that.”
Kupfer and Regier, in other words, had
failed to do in DSM-5 what Frances (at least according to Widiger) had failed
to do in DSM-IV: to ram through the changes that would decouple psychiatry from
the categories that most of its leaders knew were fictional, that had once
worked to restore the profession’s reputation, but now threatened it. Maybe the
problem was that Kupfer and Regier’s “bottoms-up” approach registered with
their foot soldiers as a lack of leadership, or perhaps the leap from
categories to dimensions was so long, the stakes of missing so high, that
Spitzer himself couldn’t have sold it. Or maybe Freud was right. Maybe the
trouble that surfaced in the personality disorders, the section of the DSM most
indebted to the past, was only the latest symptom of a neurosis, of a dream
that can’t be fulfilled: to make psychiatry into just another specialized
branch of medicine.
Chapter 17
In
September 2011, David Kupfer traveled across his home state to kick off
“Categories and Controversies: The Ethical Dimensions of the DSM-5,” a program
at the Center for Bioethics at the University of Pennsylvania. He told the
audience of about seventy-five how glad he was to be at the university that two
of his children had attended and that housed many of his research partners. In
these friendly confines, he seemed confident. “You don’t have to pay
attention,” he said, “because I’m assured you have the slides, so if you wanted
to wander around or take a nap . . .” He was casual and personal as he told us
about his experience working on DSM-IV (which, he said, had left him with “no
interest and no desire” to work on DSM-5, but he’d nonetheless been talked into
taking the reins) and about the importance of innovating while still
maintaining continuity with the past. In a nod to the day’s topic, he gave
assurances about the importance of public input and displayed the statistics
from the public comments, which now totaled 10,751. He explained that DSM-5
would be a living document, although he still wasn’t sure how or when or under
what circumstances DSM-5.1 and further updates would be issued. And he ended
with an announcement, delivered with mock seriousness. “We’ve decided on the
color of the cover,” he said. The slide showed the familiar DSM cover, only in
purple instead of the DSM-IV-TR’s gray. “It was a huge debate, but that’s been
settled,” Kupfer said with a smile.
Kupfer acknowledged the DSM-5 troubles
only obliquely, noting almost in passing that there were “individuals who will
say from the outset that it’s ridiculous to revise DSM-IV,” a charge he breezed
past with a brief reminder of the current book’s shortcomings. But just as I
was contemplating that nap, he turned to a subject that was, at least to me,
new and startling.
“I want to tell you a little about the
competition,” he said, a group at Columbia, led by a “young psychiatrist” named
Helena Hansen. “They’re not a group that has anything to do with DSM-5,” he
continued. They had invited Kupfer to one of their meetings. “I didn’t have to
wear a vest to protect me,” he joked, “and it was a great experience.” Kupfer
reported that Hansen and her team were proposing a “DSM receptor,” a group
“outside the usual suspects” that would “periodically convene” to monitor “the
implications of DSM-5 on society” and “collaborate closely with the DSM task
force” to reckon with the findings, and that Kupfer was planning to take them
up on their offer.
“I call them my friendly gadflies,” he
said. He didn’t add “as opposed to some other gadflies I know,” but anyone who
had been following the developments would get the point: the APA was taking
concerns like Frances’s seriously enough to appoint a committee of ombudsmen.
When I tracked her down, Helena Hansen
wasn’t at Columbia, but rather at New York University, where she was a
professor of anthropology and psychiatry. She told me she was indeed part of a
group looking into the social dimensions of psychiatric nosology. They had
responded to the APA’s call for public comment, had gotten some money from the
Robert Wood Johnson Foundation to hold a meeting on the subject—the session
Kupfer had attended—and sent out an article for review.
“There
has been a continual struggle1 to recognize and
incorporate socio-cultural considerations into the DSMs,” she told me in an
e-mail. “This has not been seen as mainstream to the project, which is focused
on buying credibility for psychiatry through biological formulations.”
She sure sounded as if she had the chops
for the gadfly position. But there was a problem: my e-mail was the first she’d
heard of Kupfer’s plan.
“I am not sure what Kupfer meant by
gadfly,” she wrote.
I sent her my transcription of his talk.
“This
is amazing2!” she wrote. “Wow. Well, I am
tickled that we are now a ‘committee of experts.’”
Hansen seemed willing to do the job. But
she wasn’t exactly waiting by the phone for Kupfer to call and offer it to her.
“We are just hoping the piece gets published,” she told me.
• • •
Back in California, the
unfriendly gadfly sent me a staccato message in mid-November that seemed more
fit for a telegram than an e-mail. “Approaching
endgame3. This is turning out to be much
worse than I anticipated. A truly shitty way to end a career.”
Frances’s dour dispatch contrasted sharply
with the ebullient one he had sent just a few weeks before. “A random and geographically diverse4
pick-up team of previously unknown idealists joins forces to create a
grassroots movement that saves DSM-5 from itself and spares the world an orgy
of diagnosis and a worsening epidemic of prescription drug use.” And that was
just the subject line.
The man who had once portrayed himself as
“pretty Spockean5
(as in Star Trek, not Benjamin)—too rational, old, and
indifferent to take things personally”—was evidently having some mood swings.
Among the idealists who had buoyed him was
psychologist David Elkins, head of one of the American Psychological
Association’s divisions. He had written an
open letter to the APA6, complaining about the DSM-5’s
lowered diagnostic thresholds, shaky evidence, carelessness with the public
health, and, of particular concern to psychologists, its “reconceptualizations
of mental disorder as primarily medical phenomena.” Elkins posted the letter on
a petitions website on October 25, and it had attracted nearly five thousand
signatures by November 8. That was the day that the president of the American Counseling
Association sent a letter on behalf of his
115,0007 DSM-buying members to the president
of the APA. It reiterated the petition’s objections about the quality of the
science behind DSM-5. It called for the book to acknowledge that “mental
disorders may not have a biological component” (although it did not explain
just how it would be possible to have a mental disorder that did not somehow
involve the brain). And it urged the APA to make public the work of the
scientific review committee it had appointed to review the proposed changes, as
well as to allow an evaluation of “all evidence and data by an external,
independent group of experts.”
This was a “tipping point,” Frances wrote
me. It wasn’t the first time he’d thought that. In February 2010, the tipping
point was going to be his open letter to the APA board. At the end of that
year, it was going to be my Wired article, which would
“bring Darrel to see DSM-58
through the eyes of the world that lives outside the bunkers.” In the summer of
2011, he thought it would be his blog detailing the scientific shortcomings of
DSM-5. But this time, he thought, the APA—its trustees if not its DSM
bureaucrats—would have to see how bad things were. It was one thing to dismiss
his protests as the raving of a jealous ex-chairman clinging to his passing
glory (and royalties) and quite another to ignore these two powerful groups of
professionals—and customers—not to mention the two or three hundred people from
around the world signing the petition every day.
Of course, the APA was still hearing from
Frances. His fingerprints were all over the letters from the psychologists and
counselors, and he continued to chide them in his blogs—BlackBerryed in from
San Diego and Carmel, as well as from Italy and Israel and Turkey and wherever
else he happened to be traveling (often presenting his PowerPoint on the
impending disaster)—and in the interviews he was granting to journalists all over
the world. And he was now, he told me, “rattling some cages” on a back channel
to the APA trustees and officers, with whom he was “trying to negotiate9
a face-saving compromise.” (I think he meant their faces.) Even as he repeated
his claim about the unimportance of bosses (“The most useless person on the
battlefield is Napoleon,” he wrote), he was in the thick of the battle, more
godfather than general, perhaps, but directing the war just the same.
And he was trying to direct me more than
ever.
“Cast
of fascinating and colorful characters10 who deserve
recognition and will greatly enrich human interest in your story,” read the
subject line of a note introducing me to a former television news producer
(“bright, active, and great contacts”), a “somewhat eccentric and fascinating
British lady who knows all there is to know about social networking,” and a
“seasoned mental health consumer advocate.” And these weren’t even the same
previously unknown idealists who, just a few weeks earlier, he had nominated as
the “unsung heroes” of my book.
“This
will likely be the most important11 interview you do
for the book,” he wrote, when I told him about an interview I’d scheduled with
an APA trustee. He gave me some advice on how to “get him comfortable” with me
and warned me that I shouldn’t “spook him” by letting him know just how much
contact he and I had had.
“Don’t
waste your best brains12,” he advised me, when he heard
about another interview, whose subject, Frances thought, “was a nice enough guy
but peripheral.”
He was trying to help someone he believed
to be an ally, I think. But as allies go, I was problematic. I had sent him a
peace offering for the bullshit quote—a copy of On Bullshit—but
it continued to rankle. “I was in Dubuque13,
Iowa, in the courtroom testifying . . . before a jury of upstanding cornfed
godfearing people who got to discover [via] Greenberg just how foul mouthed was
this defender of the constitution,” he wrote. “Thanks again, Gary.”
But it wasn’t the prosecutors and juries
he was most worried about. It was the real enemy, the antipsychiatrists, to
whom “your brilliant opening14”
had given ammunition. He allowed that maybe I hadn’t meant this outcome, but
that just made matters worse. “It was my lips that sank this ship,” he wrote,
“but you know sin on this one too . . . You are not concerned enough to avoid
giving them aid and comfort.” Heedless of the consequences of my own words, I
was encouraging patients to discontinue treatment.
“I am pretty light about most things in life,
but this is not a joke and you still don’t get it,” he scolded. It was an
unusually excoriating performance for someone who, true to his word, had
previously favored teasing me—for instance, calling me “Paula Caplan in drag15”—over
yelling at me.
Of course, it’s not as if Caplan or any
other antipsychiatrists needed my help, not when Frances himself was delivering
one blistering blog after another. The Citizens Commission on Human Rights, the
agitprop wing of Scientology, was hanging on his every word and gleefully
reprinting news articles about this “one-time
pillar of the psychiatric establishment16,” as one report
put it. Even the real Paula Caplan had reached out to congratulate him for his
courage in an e-mail he forwarded to me under the subject line “Fate has an ironic sense of humor17.”
“Everything
I say18,” he lamented, “is seized by the
antipsychiatry fanatics and misused for their own unfortunate purposes.”
The more his criticisms of DSM-5 were
turned against his profession, the more he protested that he was Panza, not
Quixote. Neither was he Saul, suddenly truth-struck on his way to Damascus and
testifying to the new revelation, nor was he an apparatchik-turned-dissident
denouncing his former comrades for their ideological excesses, nor was he a
deposed emperor confessing to his own nakedness even as he exposed the new
boss’s. He was a loyal opponent, not an enemy of the state, and he wanted to
make sure I understood that.
“Where
you see intelligent conspiracy19, I see dopey
incompetence,” he wrote. “In movie terms, you see APA and DSM-5 as The Parallax View meets The Stepford Wives. I see it as the
Keystone Kops meets The Gang That
Couldn’t Shoot Straight.”
“Dereification
is just as dumb20 as reification,” he told me. “A construct
is just a construct—not to be worshiped and not to be denigrated.” Psychiatry,
he was saying, has to live in the tension between the desire for certainty
about the nature of our suffering and the impossibility of understanding it (or
ourselves) completely. A DSM that tries to end this tension by turning itself
into a living document was bound to collapse into chaos; that was the cardinal
error of the incompetent DSM-5 regime. But to criticize the nosological
enterprise, and with it psychiatry itself because it can’t achieve certainty
was to erect a straw man and then burn it—and to endanger the good the
profession could do. This, Frances told me, was the greater mistake. And he was
sure I was making it.
“I like
to think the best of you21,” he wrote. He wanted to think I
was not so much against psychiatry in principle as “angrily disillusioned
[that] there is no Santa Claus”—offended that it can’t be as scientific as,
say, physics. I was, he said, referring to James Joyce’s Ulysses, an “upside-down Jesuit,” demanding an explanation that
religion never claimed to offer and then enthusiastically denouncing it for its
failure to provide it.
If this was the case, then, like Kupfer
and Regier, I was guilty only of incompetence. But there was another
possibility. “The less charitable interpretation of your blind spot is that it
fits your Caplanesque worldview”—that I was prejudiced against psychiatry,
suspicious of its claim to dominion over our inner lives, and that its failure
to live up to a trumped-up scientific standard, so baldly on display in the
unfolding debacle, was only a convenient excuse for me to denounce it.
Which I suppose is true. Not that I am
somehow determined to see psychiatry ridden out of the medical kingdom. Nor do
I think all psychiatrists are drug-pushing Pharma dupes. But it hadn’t been my
idea to turn psychoanalysis into a branch of medicine in 1926. Neither had I
had anything to do with the decision, made four decades ago, after the attempt
to render the psyche as just another organ in the body had led to disaster, to
save psychiatry by creating a DSM ripe for the reifying and then, when the
categories became cumbersome or inadequate or just plain embarrassing, to blame
others for taking them too seriously. Nor was it I who kept insisting, against
all evidence, that the mind could be understood as the output of
neurotransmitters, its suffering as chemical imbalances, and psychiatry as a
Santa Claus doling out drugs from an ever-growing bag.
And here’s where Frances had me dead to
rights: in my worldview, for which I cannot blame Paula Caplan, there are more
choices to explain events than Parallax or Keystone, conspiracy or coincidence.
We are in the grip of history, I believe, and if its long arc does not bend in
any foreordained direction, it is also not random. Which means that
hamartia—the fatal, unrecognized flaw—is always tragedy waiting to happen and
needs only the right story to be seen for what it is.
Frances might not agree with that. He’s a
literary man, but he also constantly warned me against reading meaning into the
DSM. Still, our dispute wasn’t only about the significance of the flaw, but
about its nature as well, about what exactly it consisted of and where it was
to be found. Since we’d met, he had been urging me to read A
Canticle for Leibowitz, a novel by Walter Miller. At the end of
November, I told him over the phone that I’d just finished the book, which
turned out to be a pretty good piece of science fiction squarely in the
postapocalyptic tradition. The title character, an electrical engineer named
Isaac Leibowitz, has survived a twenty-sixth-century nuclear holocaust that has
led to the Simplification, an era in which the elite and educated have been
exterminated by the Simpletons, who have outlawed learning and destroyed books.
But Leibowitz, along with a band of “bookleggers,” has set out to preserve the
world’s scientific knowledge in a monastery library. (Leibowitz converted to
Catholicism after the war.) That effort earns Leibowitz martyrdom and
beatification, but his Memorabilia lives on, and by the thirty-eighth century,
the knowledge contained in it has escaped the monastery, once again wreaking a
holocaust, but not before a small group manages to blast off from Earth in a
rocket ship, carrying, so we presume, the Leibowitzian Memorabilia and its
destructive knowledge to another world.
“What’s
the ending mean22?” he asked.
“That you have your choice between
ignorance and survival or knowledge and death.”
“And?”
“And what?”
He told me that Miller had been a tail
gunner in World War II who had participated in the destruction of Montecassino,
a Benedictine abbey in Italy. “He wrote the book as an expiation. He’s writing
about wise guys like you and me throwing hand grenades at traditions that we
think are stupid. But those traditions have a value we might miss,” he said.
“It’s the intellectuals who create the nuclear weapons. The dumb
traditionalists turn out to have it right. A lot of false beliefs help people
cope with life.”
Frances’s thin voice descended nearly into
a growl. “So don’t throw grenades unless you know what you are doing, Gary.
Don’t throw grenades. There are some traditions if you fuck with . . .” He
trailed off. “You wouldn’t want to tell a placebo responder he’s on placebo.”
• • •
The APA wasn’t so happy with
me, either.
Early in November, just about when Frances
was admonishing me, I contacted its press office to clarify a point from my
interview with Regier and to nail down the exact order of events that resulted
in banishing the drug companies from its educational programs and from the
stock portfolios of DSM contributors. I also asked if an APA official would
comment on the psychologists’ petition, now that it had amassed so many
signatures. So far the press office had stayed silent, except to note that the
petition was just one of the “thousands of comments” that had been heaved over
its transom—all of which were “being reviewed by task force and work group
members.”
After a few days, I received this message23
from the APA’s director of communications, Eve Herold.
Dear Gary,
We have
received several requests from you for access to APA experts and positions on issues
related to the DSM for the book you’re writing. I wanted you to know that we
will not be working with you on this project. Last year we gave you free access
to several of our officers and DSM experts for the article you wrote for Wired. In spite of the fact that we went to considerable
lengths to work with you, the article you produced was deeply negative and
biased toward the APA. Because of this track record, we are not interested in
working with you further as we have no reason to expect that we would be
treated any more fairly in your book than we were in the Wired
article.
I think she meant “biased against.”
Glad as I was to be spared the APA’s
talking points, I didn’t understand why it would preemptively surrender its
opportunity to correct my errors or respond to its critics, who they had to
know were talking to me. I also wondered how Herold was going to stop her
“experts”—at least the ones who didn’t work directly for her organization—from
being in contact with me, which many of them had been doing all along, gladly
and forthrightly. The confidentiality agreement hadn’t stopped them. Would a
communiqué from headquarters?
But mostly I was wondering if I would lose
my job as a Collaborating Investigator in the field trials. I’d already put in
eight hours or so, completing the Field Trials Human Subjects Protection Basic
Training and mastering the Informed Consent Process, learning how to fill out
the Patient Log, how to Register the Patient, how to log onto the Portal, how
to Push the Data to the Clinician Database, looking over the REDCap Flowchart
and Disorder Quick Reference Troubleshooting Guide, reading the sixty-page
System Manual, and sitting through the ninety-minute Webinar. I’d taken the
quizzes and practiced on the case vignettes, and finally, just a week before
Herold’s blow-off, I’d received an e-mail from the field trials team, informing
me that I had completed the training and would soon be given access to the
“LIVE database.” Had I worked so hard and come so far, only to be cut from the
team just as I was about to take the field?
I had my answer the next day in an e-mail
from the field trials’ operations manager. It wasn’t a pink slip at all, but
rather a congratulations on my having successfully completed the DSM-5 field
trials training, and a new login and password for the field trials site.
It was astounding that the APA would forgo
the opportunity to spin its story to me—not to mention so baldly display its
Kremlin tactics, and in writing no less—and yet let me in for an unfiltered look
at their prized field trials. Most likely, no one had figured out that the
biased writer and the Collaborating Investigator were the same person (although
I made no effort to conceal this fact, using the same contact information in
both capacities). But another e-mail from the operations manager—a note that
had come just a few hours after Herold’s—suggested a different explanation.
That message told me to disregard any e-mail I might have just gotten from her.
As it happened, I hadn’t received anything. But just in case I wanted an
opportunity to disregard it, she attached the errant e-mail. It was a note from
Kupfer and Regier, thanking me (for the third time) for participating in the
field trials, but also urging me to complete the training, and letting me know
that the task force had extended the deadline to do so. “We realize how challenging it is24
for practicing clinicians to find time to participate in research,” they wrote,
before reminding us about the CME credits and the free copy of the DSM-5,
complete with our names listed in the back, that awaited us in May 2013.
It sounded as if they were having trouble
getting those five thousand clinicians on board. Perhaps, like Michael First,
who told me it was “hard to find a spare six hours to do it,” they were just
too busy, or maybe they thought a free book and their name in agate type were
insufficient compensation for the task. Whatever the explanation, it appeared
that I was among the very few. I may have been persona non grata in the
communications department, but over at the research department, people like me
were much in demand. Plague rat or not, they couldn’t afford to toss me
overboard.
Recruiting my first trial patient was easy
enough. Lee and I were still in that phase of therapy in which we really liked
each other—positive transference/countertransference, the Freudians would call
it. She would not want to displease me—a good thing, as it turned out, when the
test proved to take an hour and forty-five minutes to complete.
Not that Lee got nothing out of the deal.
She did seem pretty thrilled to sit at my desk and use my computer. Back in the
psychoanalytic days, surrendering my chair and my equipment would have been a
meaning-rich event. What was it like for her to sit in my chair and use my
computer? How did it feel to be asked for a favor by her therapist? That
conversation is either silly or significant, depending on whether or not you
believe that the secrets of who we are come into view most clearly in dreams
and slips of the tongue and reactions to the unexpected, and deserve to be
illuminated.
Lee and I did eventually talk about some
of that. But those subjects hadn’t been covered in my training as a
Collaborating Investigator. Instead, I’d been drilled on the necessity of
obtaining explicit informed consent, which meant acknowledging that “there may
be no benefit for the patient from participating,” and some risk—“that the
patient may feel uncomfortable answering personal questions about thoughts and
feelings.” But, I was to assure the subject, those risks were minimal, and the
patient could always “talk to the clinician about any concerns or upsetting
feelings,” and could bail at any time. I’d been warned to make sure she could
not, while using my computer, gain access to confidential information. And, in
the Webinar and the online training and the manual, I’d been given all the fine
points of the software, how to save and retrieve and submit. Technical and
legal considerations had replaced those hoary concerns about the actual meaning
of the experience.
It’s hard to imagine Lee was finding much
meaning as she clicked on the Level 1 cross-cutting measures and the Level 2
measures for the Level 1 domains—mood, anxiety, sleep, and substance use—she’d
flagged as troublesome, and answered the WHO Disability Assessment Schedule
questions about “getting along with people” and “participation in society.”
Neither were we talking about what it meant for her to give me my chair and
computer back, or watch me fumble through the next hour or so, opening the
modules and going down the checklists and reading boldfaced alerts like this
one:
To make the diagnosis of
Major Depressive Disorder, one has to rule out whether the major depressive
episode is better accounted for by Schizoaffective Disorder and is superimposed
on Schizophrenia, Schizophreniform Disorder, Delusional Disorder, or Psychotic
Disorder Not Otherwise Specified. To do so you SHOULD inquire about history of
schizoaffective disorder, schizophrenia, and/or any psychotic symptoms!!
I navigated the menus and proceeded
through the forty-nine pages of mood disorders and the thirty-one pages of
anxiety disorders, the eighteen pages of sleep-wake disorders, the sixty-three
pages of substance use disorders (many pages of which could be skipped simply
by deciding that I did not want to explore the possibility that Lee suffered
from cannabis use disorder or circadian rhythm sleep disorder, but it wasn’t
entirely clear how I was supposed to know exactly which ones to skip; in all
that training, I’d been left to my own devices to study up on the diagnoses
themselves), and I concluded that she suffered from Major Depressive
Disorder—Severe and Insomnia Disorder and Alcohol Use Disorder—in Full
Remission, all the while feeling retroactive sympathy for Bill Narrow, who knew
long before he put hand to mouse that Virginia Hamm was a hoarder just as much
as I knew that Lee was a depressed insomniac with a drinking problem, but had
to go through with the exercise anyway.
On the other hand, Narrow had a part in
designing this 501-page monster and I didn’t.
But what about when the fix wasn’t in?
What about someone I didn’t really know? The second interview I was supposed to
conduct was with a new patient, and Claudia fit the bill. She had shown up on a
rainy night twenty minutes late for her first visit after three increasingly
frenzied phone calls in which I assured her that her GPS was correct about how
to get from where she was to my building and one more as she wandered the
hallways looking for my office, which she did not find until, after another
phone call, I went out to meet her. She was easy enough to spot, a tiny woman
with a pixie haircut, frantically flitting from doorway to doorway like a lost
Tinker Bell. When I found her, she pressed her hands together under her chin Namaste-style and bowed slightly, my credibility as guru
evidently established simply by my knowing my way around my building. It was a
gesture she repeated three or four times in the course of our visit, just after
I’d made a comment. After she left, I tried but could not for the life of me
recall what those comments might have been. It’s possible my memory got lost in
the jumble of details that poured out of her mouth at top speed (she suffered from
what we therapists call logorrhea), but more likely, I
hadn’t said anything particularly insightful, being too busy absorbing her
distress and confusion, her depression and anxiety and paranoia, her fragmented
stories of her fraught love affairs with men and women, the way she flew from
bed to bed like a hummingbird, alighting just long enough to sip some nectar,
searching for the next flower before she was even finished with the last—the
most recent being a man whom she had, after a flurry of texts and e-mails and
aborted trysts, accompanied to a hotel room, only to find his girlfriend
already installed, and she, for reasons she couldn’t quite explain, but maybe
it was the three martinis they drank, went ahead with his suggested sexual
encounter with the girlfriend—and her troubles at her graphic design job, which
she was afraid she was about to lose, or maybe she had lost already, she wasn’t
sure, but she was too afraid to ask her boss, with whom she had been having
sex, but who was leaving the company and his replacement was gay, so he
probably wasn’t going to exchange job security for sex (not, she assured me,
that this was what she’d been doing with the boss). Plus which she somehow had
ended up with the boss’s pet birds, three squawking cages full, who needed care
and feeding beyond what she could give any longer, and what she really wanted
to know from me was what to do about the birds.
Being with Claudia was like riding a raft
through white water. I might be skeptical of the value of the DSM, but I was
ready to try anything to channel these rapids into an orderly stream of
information, a diagnosis that would grant me the ability to communicate
efficiently about Claudia to at least one clinician—me. So I was glad to offer
her the opportunity to participate in the study (and the free visit in return),
and she, for reasons she never stated, but most likely at least in part because
she didn’t exactly know how to say no to men, was glad to consent.
The very next week, after one more visit,
one more fruitless attempt to piece together some coherent story out of the
fragments of her life, I surrendered my desk and computer to Claudia. Her
finger hovered above the mouse frequently as she read over the items, sometimes
out loud. She sighed and laughed and, a couple of times, had an extended
conversation with the computer (only one side of which I could hear). Twice she
came to a complete stop, staring at the screen for a minute or so without
scrolling or clicking or reading, transfixed, I thought, by something else
entirely. After forty-five minutes, she stood up, made her little bow, and
returned to her chair.
I pushed the data. We had our work cut out
for us. She’d scored high in all the cross-cutting domains except substance
use, where she had a zero—a strange result, I thought, since so many of the
escapades she had described in our first session were fueled by alcohol. I
fumbled through the diagnostic interview a little less with her than I had with
Lee. But then again, I had more time to plot my course through the criteria
while Claudia pondered every question closely. She wasn’t sure if she had
“feelings of worthlessness or excessive and inappropriate guilt” or “excessive
anxiety” or a “distinct period of abnormally and persistently elevated,
expansive or irritable mood that lasted 4 consecutive days and was present most
of the day nearly every day.” She would give an answer and take it back and
venture another, hovering over her response like a checkers player who never
lifts his fingers from his piece, until I finally had to say, “Let’s go on,”
and she let the last move stand.
Claudia was certain about some criteria.
She did not drink too much. She was not confused about sex. And she did not
have a “diminished ability to think or concentrate, or indecisiveness.”
I don’t think she was lying. I think she
was, as we therapists say, in denial. And who could blame her? She was too
mercurial for introspection, and even if she hadn’t been, these weren’t exactly
the best conditions under which to reveal her frailties and flaws. I was, after
all, still more or less unknown to her, our lack of intimacy at wild odds with
my probing, no less so than it is in the gynecologist’s office, only here there
was no sheet to cover her, no nurse to hold her hand or distract her, and I was
not crouched where she couldn’t see me, but looking right in her eyes as I
asked questions made indecent by their detachment from anything real or live
between us. Efflorescent inner life rendered as symptom by a stranger wielding
the DSM’s computerized language as if it were a speculum: who would not resist?
It had been a little more than an hour
since Claudia had relinquished the computer, nearly two hours since we had
started this dispiriting adventure. I decided to skip the substance use disorders
despite my doubts about her answers and click right to the part I had
originally thought might yield something useful, a way to organize my own
thoughts in the face of her chaos: the personality disorders section.
At first, it looked straightforward enough.
There was ample “evidence of impairments” in her “experience of self as unique
with clear boundaries between self and others,” in the stability of her
self-image and her “ability to regulate [her] emotional experience.” Yes, she
had some problems with intimacy. But how much impairment? REDCap wanted to
know. On a scale of zero to four, just how fucked up was Claudia?
Here I was given a choice. I could
“proceed directly to rating” and pull a number out of the air, or I could get a
“detailed description of levels.” I went for the details, which turned out to
be extensive, three pages of description about “identity” and “self-direction”
and “empathy” and “intimacy.” Was she a Level 2—“Excessive dependence on others
for identity definition, with compromised boundary delineation”? Or did she
have the “weak sense of autonomy/agency” and “poor or rigid boundary
definition” of a Level 3? Or was her experience of
autonomy/agency “virtually absent,” and her boundaries “confused
or lacking,” which earned her a Level 4? Was her self-esteem “fragile” (Level
3) or merely “vulnerable” (2), or perhaps riddled with
“significant distortions” and “confusions” (4)? Was her capacity for empathy “significantly
compromised,” “significantly limited,” or “virtually absent”? Was her desire for connection with
others “desperate,” “limited,” or “largely based on
meeting self-regulatory needs?”
I had no idea. And even if I had, or if I
knew how to get this confused and confusing woman to parse it for me, there
still loomed thirty pages or so to get through, box after box to check about
her self and interpersonal functioning, her separation insecurity and depressivity, her negative affectivity and
disinhibition, the types and facets and domains of her traits, hundreds of
boxes, or so it seemed, before I could make my final diagnosis, and, with the
authority vested in me as a Collaborating Investigator of the American
Psychiatric Association, determine which of the constructs that deserve neither
denigration nor worship, that aren’t real but still can be measured from zero
to four, that need to be taken seriously enough to warrant payment and maybe a
round of medication but not so seriously that anyone would accuse them of
existing, which fictive placeholder would join her height and blood pressure
and her childhood illnesses and surgeries and all the other facts of her
medical life. At which point I realized that no matter what diagnosis I settled
on, I wouldn’t so much have tamed her rapids as funneled them into the
diagnostic turbines, raw material for the APA’s profitable mills.
I was longing for the pre-DSM-III days
when I could have read this paragraph:
This behavior pattern25 is characterized
by ineffectual responses to emotional, social, intellectual, and physical
demands. While the patient seems neither physically nor mentally deficient, he
does manifest inadaptability, ineptness, poor judgment, social instability, and
lack of physical and emotional stamina.
I could have then written
down this diagnosis, perhaps cruel but to the point: inadequate personality.
Not that ineffectual and deficient
are any easier to define, but at least the DSM-II wasn’t asking me to rate them
on a scale of zero to four. At least it didn’t first claim that they were real
enough to measure and then insist that they weren’t real at all.
“I think we’ll stop here,” I said.
“How did I come out?” Claudia asked.
It was a totally reasonable question.
She’d just invested more than two hours in this procedure. After this kind of
grilling, anyone would wonder. And Claudia might have been hoping the same
thing I was—that somehow this process would provide some kind of clarity about
her.
“Oh, I won’t know right away.” It was only
a partial lie. Overwhelmed by the data, I had already forgotten which diagnoses
I’d reached, and now that I’d clicked Send, I couldn’t go back and look. I
wouldn’t know until I opened the files into which I’d been downloading the
forms as we went.
I wanted to ask her how this interview had
been for her. I wanted to apologize to her for the inadequacy, the
pointlessness, the sheer idiocy of the exercise, for the two hours I’d spent
with her during which we had not only failed to get closer to each other or to
an understanding of her troubles but actually, I worried, moved further away.
It was nearly nine at night. I’d been in my office since eight that morning. So
I thanked her for helping me out and scheduled her next appointment and said
good night.
I never saw Claudia again. I don’t know
why. She just didn’t show for her next appointment and never returned my phone
calls. Maybe she decided therapy wasn’t for her, or I wasn’t the therapist she
should see. Maybe she ran out of money. But I’ll always think it had something
to do with those two hours of flailing about in the fields of the DSM, that my
failure to take the measure of her suffering had turned into her failure to
measure up, that the futility of the field trial had made the whole therapeutic
enterprise seem futile, that when the DSM’s desiccated vocabulary, at least in
the hands of a nonbeliever, proved no match for the immensity of her suffering,
Claudia had lost that most precious therapeutic commodity: confidence.
• • •
Just before Christmas, the
APA sent out Inside DSM-5 Field Trials: Your Voice in Action!,
a newsletter for us participants. “The
journey into the future26 begins with a few small steps,” it
proclaimed. But apparently not enough of us were taking them. “We understand
that these steps can be time consuming, or even a bit confusing,” the article
continued, “but we believe that the value of training and participating extends
far beyond that of the field trials.” It didn’t say exactly what other benefit
lay in store for us, but it did reassure us that the APA staff was standing by
to help us achieve it.
Farther down the page was the reason the
APA had had to resort to badgering us. Of the 5,000 clinicians who had signed
up, only 1,000 had so far started training, only 195 had completed the
training, and only 70 had enrolled any patients. The newsletter writers did
their best to sound upbeat—“in fact, nearly 150 patients have joined the
study,” they wrote, leaving out the fact that the goal was 10,000—but anyone
with a calendar could see the problem. More than a year after the sign-ups
began, three months after Kupfer and Regier had sent out their plea for
cooperation, and only two months before the data had to be in, the RCP trials
had scarcely begun.
That look at the calendar revealed an even
more disturbing problem. The APA had originally planned two sets of field
trials—the first to reveal the bugs, the second to make sure they’d been shaken
out. The second phase was originally scheduled to end in February 2012. But
even though the academic center field trials were progressing better than the
clinician version—and by some accounts were largely finished, although no one
would say—their findings still weren’t in, and no release date had been given.
Neither had the APA announced the inevitable result: that the second phase
would have to be canceled if the DSM-5 was to be published on time. That news
had just appeared when a new timeline was posted on the website.
Something else had shown up quietly on the
website. The banner at the bottom of every page, which, as recently as July
2011, had proclaimed that the APA represented “38,000 physician leaders in
mental health,” had been changed. The organization now represented only 36,000
doctors. And at the end of 2011, the
treasurer delivered grim news27 to the remaining
members: Annual income from the drug industry, once $18 million, was now only
$4 million. Meeting revenues were off by $1.6 million. Ad revenues had sunk to
$6 million, off their high of $10 million. Membership dues were down by
$500,000. Thanks to cuts in expenditures, the APA was still running a surplus
of about $2.85 million, but, the treasurer reported, “this is due to a [$5.6
million] surplus for American Psychiatric Press,” whose most profitable
property was, as it had long been, the DSM. Without the DSM, in other words,
the APA would have lost nearly $3 million.
These numbers only strengthened the
concern among critics like Frances that in its haste to freshen its cash cow,
the APA was trampling over science. That, of course, was impossible to prove,
but one thing was clear: toward the end of 2011, the APA was patrolling its
intellectual property lines more vigilantly than ever, as a woman in England
found out the hard way. For a couple of years, Suzy Chapman, a patient
advocate, had been running a blog called Dsm5watch28. Chapman, a
caregiver for a patient with chronic fatigue syndrome, was interested primarily
in developments related to CFS, but her blog covered the entire revision
process (as well as that of the International Classification of Diseases).
Unlike the APA, which removed old criteria and timelines as it changed them,
Chapman had preserved excerpts from earlier iterations of the DSM-5, and her
website, which also collected news and opinion pieces about DSM, had thus
become one of the largest and most reliable repositories of revision-related
information on the Web.
This may or may not be why, on December
22, she received a letter from Cecilia Stoute, the licensing and permissions
manager of the American Psychiatric Press. It wasn’t a Christmas card.
“It has
come to our attention29,” Stoute wrote, “that the website
http://dsm5watch.wordpress.com/ is infringing upon the American Psychiatric
Association’s trademark DSM-5 (serial number 85161695) and is in violation of
federal law by using it as a domain name.” Chapman’s “unauthorized actions,”
Stoute continued, “may subject you to contributory infringement liability
including increased damages for willful infringement.” To avoid that outcome,
Chapman must “immediately cease and desist any and all use of the DSM-5 mark”
and remove it from her domain name.
“I
thought it was a hoax30,” Chapman told me—an impression
reinforced by a second letter she received, this one instructing her to remove
the DSM-5 mark from a second website, as well as a Facebook page and a Twitter
account. But those domains didn’t belong to her and never had. They were run by
the psychologists who originated the petition. Those sites remained online
despite the APA’s copyright, as did Dsm5.com, Newdsm5.com, Dsm-5diagnosis.com,
Dsm5band.com (INSANITY NEVER
SOUNDED SO GOOD!), and even Dsm5sucks.com.
But no matter how outlandish the claim or
how selective the action or how shaky the APA’s legal grounds, and no matter
how much the move reeked of intimidation, Chapman felt she had no choice but to
comply. “I could not finance a legal wrangle31
with the APA,” she told me, adding that she feared that her blog’s host would
remove her site at the first sign of trouble, wiping out years of work with a
single keystroke. So she changed her blog name to Dxrevisionwatch.
As she feared, the new URL caused her readership to plummet to nearly zero—but
not for long. On January 3, Frances wrote about Chapman’s travails in his Psychology Today blog. Within a couple of weeks, traffic to
her website was double its pre-putsch levels.
That’s probably not what the APA had in
mind.
The incident left Chapman wondering about
the APA. “What kind of organization slaps heavy legal threats on a member of
the public just two days before Christmas, when it would be hard to get legal
advice? What kind of organization is so lax that it issues cease-and-desist
letters without having first established who owns the contested domains?”
The answer was obvious: an organization
that was both intelligently conspiratorial and dopily
incompetent. Or, as they might say in Hollywood, The Gang
That Couldn’t Shoot Straight meets The Parallax View.
Chapter 18
Speaking
of conspiracies, Darrel Regier had a theory about Allen Frances’s complaint
that the DSM-5 would extend the reach of psychiatry into everyday life. “The idea of medicalizing normality1,”
he told a reporter in late January, “comes from a perspective that there are no
psychiatric disorders, and you need to avoid stigmatizing people by giving them
one.”
It’s possible that Regier had joined the
crowd who believed that the former most powerful psychiatrist in America had
become a devout antipsychiatrist. Or maybe he had just misunderstood what
Frances really meant. But it’s also possible that Regier was getting desperate.
You couldn’t exactly blame him. The middle
of January 2012 was the start of a terrible month-long period for him, the APA,
and the DSM-5.
The first storm blew in from offshore on
January 19, when Fred Volkmar gave a talk to the Icelandic Medical Association.
Volkmar and a couple of his Yale colleagues had dusted off the data from the
DSM-IV field trials for childhood disorders and then applied the proposed DSM-5
criteria to the same subjects. They determined that only 44 percent of the
subjects who had received a diagnosis in the original study would have made it
onto the proposed autism spectrum. And only twelve of the forty-eight original
Asperger’s patients—the same cases that had unexpectedly strengthened the case for
including Asperger’s in the DSM-IV—would have qualified under the new regime.
Volkmar had presented much of this data
before, at a November meeting of the American Academy of Child and Adolescent
Psychiatry in Toronto, but he wasn’t in any hurry to have it known by the
general public. “I wasn’t exactly hiding it2,”
he told me. “But I am (or have been) friends with a number of people on the
committee, and I knew that this would cause bad feeling.” And, he added, “I
knew that the powers that be would take no hostages on this one.” So he didn’t
approach reporters with the incendiary news that three-quarters of Asperger’s
patients might soon be losing their diagnoses (or wouldn’t be getting them in
the first place).
But then Benedict Carey, the New York Times reporter on the psychiatry beat, happened to
call Volkmar on the eve of his trip to Iceland, fishing for news on the autism
front. Volkmar still didn’t draw attention to the data reanalysis, but he did
send Carey the slides from his upcoming presentation, and as soon as Carey saw
the slide listing its results, he grasped their significance. His front-page
story, “New Definition of Autism Will Exclude Many,” appeared on January 19 and
quickly rocketed around the world via newspaper, TV, and blog. The Times followed up the next day with a story about the
possible impact of a reduction in diagnoses on children and their families.
When he heard the news, GRASP’s Michael
Carley was already rethinking his position in favor of the DSM-5 proposal—and
not only because of Volkmar’s research. He’d gotten hold of another
soon-to-be-published article, this one from a group at Louisiana State
University, that had concluded the new criteria would exclude 37 percent of the
patients, most of them at the high-functioning end of the spectrum. He now
found himself siding with his son.
“It was
one thing to make a change3 that relabeled people,” Carley told
me, “and another to make a change that they knew would exclude so many.”
The promises the APA had issued since
announcing the proposals now seemed like mere “damage
control4,” Carley told his members. “We
think those who reassuringly tell us, ‘No one will be left behind,’ really
mean, ‘No one will be left behind who deserves a diagnosis under the DSM-5
criteria.’” He now urged GRASPers to take action: by signing a petition
opposing the changes and by flooding the APA’s phone lines with complaints.
“Yes, they are telling you to e-mail instead,” he acknowledged. “But we ask
that you please instead be the articulate, impassioned, and peaceful nuisance
that is needed in this debate, and not adhere to their instructions.”
The APA scrambled its experts, but they
couldn’t seem to agree on their talking points. “We have to make sure5
not everybody who is a little odd gets a diagnosis of autism or Asperger’s
disorder,” David Kupfer told The New York Times. Cathy Lord echoed this concern, telling the same
reporter that her work group wanted to make sure “that autism was not used as a
‘fallback diagnosis.’” But she also reassured readers that “the committee’s own
data shows very few who currently have a diagnosis would be dropped.” She
didn’t say why, if the problem was so insignificant, the committee had gone to
so much trouble to fix it.
Another work group member, Bryan King,
tried a different approach. The question of overdiagnosis had never even been
relevant to the proceedings, he claimed. “There
has never been an agenda6 for us to restrict or limit the
numbers of people diagnosed with autism,” he told Medscape
Medical News, an industry outlet. “We’ve only wanted to get the criteria
right,” he continued, as if a reduction of diagnoses was only a side effect of
a drastic reduction in the number of possible symptom combinations that could
result in a diagnosis. And even if a few people lost their official labels, they
had nothing to fear: if one label disappears, he said, “then a different label
will appear in its place. There will always be a way to capture the need for
treatment.”
King didn’t say exactly what label was
waiting in the wings for those fallback-diagnosed, a-little-odd kids who may or
may not exist. Neither, apparently, did he realize he was giving up the game,
acknowledging that capturing rather than establishing the need for treatment had become the purpose
of diagnosis, nor did he consider how antipsychiatrists would treat that
comment. After all, if every complaint that brings a person to a doctor demands
a diagnosis, the next thing you know you’ll have a wholesale imperial
medicalization of normality.
King was clear on one thing: Volkmar had
unduly scared the bejesus out of people, at least to judge by the calls to
King’s clinic, where the phones, he said, had been “ringing off the hook.”
At APA headquarters, despite Carley’s
efforts, it wasn’t the phones that were taking the brunt. It was Regier’s e-mail
in-box, which, he told a reporter, had been deluged with “10,000 plus e-mails7”
in the wake of the New York Times articles.
Regier added that he would have liked to respond to Volkmar’s numbers with his
own, but he “was not willing to give detailed data . . . until [they] are
subjected to peer review and are published.” He didn’t add “like some people I
know,” but the implication was clear: Volkmar wasn’t playing fair, and Regier
was once again the victim of his own scrupulousness. And in case he hadn’t
sufficiently questioned Volkmar’s integrity, Regier threw another elbow,
telling a reporter that Volkmar had a new book coming out about Asperger’s—a
book whose market might well disappear with the diagnosis.
“I hope this is not what he said,” Volkmar
responded, when the reporter passed along the comment.
“There is certainly a better way to phrase
this,” Regier wrote back (after complaining that he hadn’t had much luck in
“changing how journalists present a story”). “The point I was making is that
Fred has a particular interest in Asperger’s,” he explained. That, evidently,
was the best phrasing he could find.
• • •
Only five days after the
autism story broke, a Carey-penned DSM piece8
once again made the front page of The New York Times. This time around, the hook was a World Psychiatry article
by Jerry Wakefield and Michael First9 questioning the
evidence on which the proposal to remove the bereavement exclusion was based.
Their argument was a detailed refutation of the research that Sid Zisook and
his colleagues had mustered in favor of their notion that there wasn’t enough
difference between bereavement-related depression and all other depression to
warrant the exclusion.
“An estimated 8 to 10 million people lose
a loved one every year, and something like a third to a half of them suffer
depressive symptoms for up to a month afterward,” Wakefield told Carey. “This
would pathologize them for behavior previously thought to be normal.” The
article went on to detail the other DSM-5 proposals that threatened to raise
the prevalence of mental disorders—Attenuated Psychosis Symptoms Syndrome,
Binge Eating Disorder, Premenstrual Dysphoric Disorder. Carey quoted a
psychiatrist who forecast a wider use of drugs as a result and let Frances
issue yet another warning about the medicalizing of normality. Some experts
were worried about the “corrosive effect” all this “politicking” might have on
the revision process, Carey wrote, but others—including Steve Hyman and his
successors at NIMH—thought it was mostly beside the point, which was why they
were no longer interested in the DSM. “Nature does not respect psychiatric
categories,” Carey concluded, and added that while there might someday be a
nosology that nature would respect, “until then, there . . . will be the
diagnostic manual.”
Carey gave Jay Scully an opportunity to
defend the APA’s position. Rather than address the questions raised by the
article, however, Scully decided to blame the messengers. “We’ve got electronic
media around the clock, and we’ve made drafts of the proposed changes public
online, for one thing,” he told Carey. “So anybody and everybody can comment on
them, at any time, without any editors.” It was a curious tactic, and one that
didn’t shed much light on the subject of diagnostic inflation, but then again,
Scully couldn’t respond to that worry with reassuring statistics about
prevalence from the field trials—and not because, as Regier had implied, the
detailed data awaited analysis or because professional decorum demanded
reticence, but because there was no such data, and there would never be any.
Helena Kraemer, chief architect of the
field trials, had said as much earlier in January. Writing in the American Journal of Psychiatry, she had “set out realistic expectations10”
for her project, starting with the “contentious issue” of prevalence. Rates
were going to change, Kraemer warned. Some new criteria were going to pick up
more mental disorder in the population, and some were going to exclude people
who might previously have been included. The only way to avoid these outcomes
would be “to require that any existing difference between true and DSM-IV
prevalence be reproduced in DSM-5”—or, to put it another way, to rig the game
to leave prevalence unchanged. “Thus,” Kraemer concluded, “there are no
specific expectations about the prevalence of disorders in DSM-5.”
But who was expecting that diagnostic
rates would remain unchanged? Surely not Wakefield and First and Frances, or
any of the civilians worried about the reach of psychiatry. Like Kraemer, they
fully expected prevalence to change; what worried them was the possibility this
would lead to epidemiological chaos. But unlike Kraemer, they weren’t in a
position to find out, and, as she made clear in her very next sentence, she was
not going to do that.
“The evaluations primarily address
reliability,” Kraemer wrote, as if it somehow followed that because prevalence
rates were bound to change, they weren’t worth looking into.*
She didn’t explain further, so it is
possible that this is not what she meant. Perhaps Regier had decided the
problem that attracted him to the field—the Midtown Manhattan Study’s wild
prevalence rates—was suddenly unimportant, or Kupfer had decided to leave the
question to his imaginary gadfly friends. Maybe Kraemer thought her readers
would leap over the gap in logic and assume that the only reasonable thing to
do was to abandon the subject of how many people would be declared mentally ill
in favor of the question of whether psychiatrists could agree on which mental
illnesses they had. (Of course, as she had announced the previous May and
repeated in the AJP article, people should temper
their expectations about that subject as well.) But whatever the reasoning, it
was clear that the field trials hadn’t been designed to address the issue. In
fact, it seemed as if they’d been designed not to, as if the prevalence
question needed to be avoided at all costs because the answers might be too
disturbing, because they couldn’t help but point to the fact that the
diagnostic sands were still shifting, and thus undermine confidence in the APA.
Okay, maybe that’s too much like The Parallax View. Certainly the APA’s disorganized,
off-the-point, whiny response was pretty Keystone Kops. And even the most
sure-footed organization might well have been knocked to its knees by the rush
of events.
Scully and his crew barely had time to
draw breath before The New York Times
struck again—this time with a pair of op-ed
columns11 about Asperger’s appearing on the
same day, one by a psychiatrist who acknowledged that it was overdiagnosed (and
looked forward to a time when “biological markers” would separate the sick from
the weird), and the other by Benjamin Nugent, a writer whose psychologist
mother, an expert in Asperger’s, had gotten him diagnosed when he was a
teenager, but who, after he “moved to New York City and . . . met some people
who shared my obsessions,” realized he wasn’t sick at all.
Before the APA could accuse all these
writers of believing that mental illnesses don’t exist, or wonder if the Church
of Scientology had bought The New York Times, the news that the DSM-5 would throw kids out into the
diagnostic cold had spread to more than one hundred outlets in twelve
countries. In Great Britain, a group of dissenting psychologists and
psychiatrists called a press conference. “The
proposals in DSM-512 are likely to shrink the pool of
normality to a puddle,” one of them said, and the sound bite made it into
papers and blogs all over the world. The Lancet13, perhaps the
most venerable of all medical journals, ran, in a single issue, a report on
research showing Attenuated Psychosis Risk Syndrome to be invalid, an editorial
decrying the removal of the bereavement exclusion, and a moving essay by the
Harvard medical anthropologist Arthur Kleinman about his grief after losing his
wife of forty-six years. A year later, Kleinman wrote, “I still feel sadness14
at times and harbour the sense that a part of me is gone forever. . . . I am
still caring for our memories. Is there anything wrong (or pathological) with
that?” Even politicians were piling on. State legislators in Illinois and New
York introduced bills proposing to make the DSM-IV definition of autism,
Asperger’s, and Pervasive Developmental Disorder the law of their lands, “even if,” as the Illinois version put it15,
“subsequent changes to the diagnostic criteria are adopted by the American
Psychiatric Association.”
So it’s no wonder the APA was on its heels
and in disarray. Or at least that’s my explanation for their surprisingly
ineffectual response. When they weren’t launching ad hominem attacks or whining
that they were the misunderstood victims of their own good intentions, or
repeating their long-stale talking points to reporters and in mostly ignored
press releases, they were silent. They didn’t bother responding, by letter or
column, to the onslaught in The New York Times. They didn’t answer Kleinman or The
Lancet or hold a news conference of their own to counter the British
renegades’ arguments. They didn’t expound on the philosophical and scientific
conundrums posed by psychiatric diagnosis. They didn’t argue that diagnostic
uncertainty was the rule rather than the exception in medicine. They didn’t
warn people not to take the DSM too seriously. They didn’t even make the
obvious point that the two articles in the Times—one
of which thrashed the APA for diagnosing too few people, the other for
diagnosing too many—were at least an indication that it wasn’t trying to fix
the game either way. Perhaps the APA’s leaders were shell-shocked, or tired, or
simply lacked the intellectual horsepower to respond. Maybe they really
believed, as David Kupfer told MedPage Today, that
even though the deadline was rapidly approaching, “the door is still very much open16”
to changes. Or maybe they had figured out that when the DSM-5 came out in May
2013, none of these complaints, no matter how trenchant or eloquent, not
Frances’s or Wakefield’s or First’s, not The New York Times’ or The Lancet’s—not one of
them would matter. Maybe they decided that since they had the ball—indeed, they
owned the ball—they could just duck their heads and run out the clock.
• • •
There was one other
DSM-related op-ed in The New York Times
in late January. I wrote it. “You’ve got to
feel sorry17 for the American Psychiatric
Association,” it began, “at least for a moment.” I wasn’t being entirely
ironic. I did feel a little sorry for the APA. Not that the organization
deserved my sympathy or needed my help, but there was something nearly pathetic
about its inability to mount a spirited defense of its own work, about the fear
that prevented it from telling us what all its members knew: that the disorders
listed in the DSM were not real diseases, but, as my essay put it, “useful
constructs that capture the ways people commonly suffer,” that this is why the
arguments were fraught and endless, and that it was foolish to think this task
force would come up with anything better than previous task forces: provisional
categories that would inevitably change with time. The APA couldn’t, or
wouldn’t, say this—perhaps because it would turn into fodder for its enemies—so
I said it for them. It seemed like the least I could do.
Plus I got to quote Herb Peyser: “We’re
like Cinderella’s older stepsisters. We’re trying to stick our fat feet into
the delicate slipper so the prince can take us to the ball. But we ain’t going
to the ball right now.” I thought this image captured the problem perfectly. I
still do.
I did not receive a thank-you note from
the APA’s Office of Communications. That might be because I ended the essay by
saying that even if it wasn’t going to the ball anytime soon, once the DSM-5
came out, the APA would be laughing all the way to the bank. But I did get an
e-mail from Frances, sent at six a.m. the day the article ran. In its entirety,
it read:
From: Allen Frances
To: Gary Greenberg
Subject: As the scorpion
told the frog
What do you expect, I am a
scorpion.
Sent from my Verizon
Wireless BlackBerry
I asked him to elaborate and got this
back:
When you had an incredible
platform to help contain DSM 5 damage, you couldn’t contain your antipsychiatry
quixotic instincts and instead had bigger fish to fry. This is unfortunate for
a Panza like me (with much smaller ambitions like protecting kids from
antipsychotics) because your broadside against psychiatry allows the DSM 5
crowd to simply shrug you off . . . So in tilting against windmills, you made
yourself irrelevant to DSM 5.
I’m not sure where Frances got the idea
that I wanted to be heard by the DSM-5 crowd. It was clear, however, why he saw
my article as antipsychiatry: because I had said out loud, while standing on
that “incredible platform,” that his profession’s authority rested on nothing
more than agreement among experts. Not that he denied this, but he was sure it
should not be said so publicly, and it was making him wonder if he’d made a
mistake by being so candid with me.
“I often ask myself why I am so good to
you when I know you will stab psychiatry in the back,” he had written earlier.
He answered his own question. “It is the Prince Myshkin in me.” But, as was
often the case when Frances called himself an idiot, it seemed his real barb
was directed elsewhere.
Frances’s winter of discontent was lasting
into spring. “The man is an absolute fool and an incorrigible tool,” he wrote
of one DSM-5 activist. The psychologists’ petition was “dying as the feckless
humanists fiddle.” Paula Caplan had started her own petition, calling for a
boycott of the DSM and for congressional hearings into the harmful effects of
psychiatric diagnosis. Infighting among the groups opposing the APA was
growing. “This is getting really disgusting,” he wrote.
There were a couple of bright spots. Late
in February, the Department of Health and Human Services confirmed that the
ICD-10 would not be implemented until October 2014, meaning that the APA no
longer needed to hurry the DSM to publication in 2013. In early March, a
psychologist’s blog post about the bereavement exclusion attracted 65,000 hits
in four days—“a spontaneous revolt by the large community of the bereaved,”
Frances wrote in the Psychiatric Times—and his latest
hope for a tipping point. And the APA handed him a rhetorical opportunity when
it hired James Tyll, a former Pentagon flack, to handle its DSM communications,
and he promptly told a Time reporter that Frances was
a “‘dangerous’ man trying to undermine an earnest academic endeavor.”
“Fresh from DoD,” Frances riposted in The Huffington Post, “it may be difficult for the new
spokesman to leave behind combat clichés. Who knows? I may have become a
picture card in his deck of high-value targets.”
But overall Frances’s tone was darkening.
“How can you possibly continue to fiddle?” he asked his former friends on the
back channel. In an open letter he urged the board of trustees to keep the
bereavement exclusion, get rid of Disruptive Mood Dysregulation Disorder and
Attenuated Psychosis Symptoms Syndrome, and abandon Hebephilia “before more
harm is done.” Take these steps, he wrote, and they would prevent a further
loss of “public and professional faith,” reduce the likelihood of overdiagnosis
and overmedication, and “allow me to throw my cursed BlackBerry into the
ocean.” And in case that wasn’t enough to spur them to action, he added that
“as the responsible leaders of the APA, you cannot avoid your fiduciary
responsibility to regain control of the staff and to rein in a runaway DSM-5
process.” Otherwise, he wrote, they risked “dramatically reduced DSM-5 sales,
APA budget shortfalls, declining membership, and the potential loss of the DSM
franchise.”
After all his appeals to common sense and
professional wisdom, to aristocratic humility and the spirit of moderation,
Frances was apparently reduced to hoping that it was true what they say about
capitalism: that money talks.
• • •
“Wonderful news18,” Frances
blogged in late April. He had caught wind of some changes—that Attenuated
Psychosis Symptoms Syndrome and Mixed Anxiety-Depression would be placed in the
Appendix of the DSM-5, as would Internet Use Disorder, and that Hebephilia was
not going to get its own diagnostic category (although it would probably be
listed as a subtype of Pedophilia). Regier and Kupfer attributed these changes
to data from the field trials, but to Frances, this meant that they had
finally, and wisely, concluded that there was indeed such a thing as bad
publicity.
“For the first time in its history,” he
wrote, “DSM-5 has shown some . . . capacity to correct itself.” There were
still many outstanding concerns (and just in case the APA had lost track, he
listed twelve of them), but it seemed that “extensive criticism from experts .
. . public outrage . . . negative press coverage,” as well as the data, had
paid off. Frances wasted no time in using this as a rallying point for his
troops, urging them to exploit “this opening chink in the previously impervious
DSM-5 armor” and “take this last opportunity to be heard.”
More bad news was soon filtering out from
the field trials, though, including a rumor that Major Depressive Disorder and
Generalized Anxiety Disorder, longtime staples in the psychiatric pantry, had
achieved extremely low reliability scores, an indication that those little
tweaks, coupled with the poor design of the study, had made a huge difference,
and this strengthened Frances’s fears that the reliability numbers would be a “stain on psychiatry19.”
“Looks like I wasted my time,” he wrote
me. “Cassandra, not Cincinnatus.”
Though it had relented on some of the
diagnoses, the APA was showing no signs of changing its tactics. Indeed, it
reprised one of its earliest moves. In mid-April, just a couple of weeks before
the APA’s annual meeting, members of the task force and work groups received a
communiqué from Kupfer and Regier, reminding them that the confidentiality
agreement to which Spitzer had objected (but which they had signed) had new
implications now that studies were appearing in the academic press using the
proposals they had generated.
“We
encourage the wide dissemination20 of these
important studies,” the memo read, but lest anyone get it in their heads to go
Volkmar on the APA, Kupfer and Regier wanted to “remind you that the content
and work products that have been generated as part of your ongoing activities .
. . is [sic] considered to be the property of the
APA.” This meant that “permission is required for its use,” which in turn
required that any outside publisher obtain a license from the APA to use its
intellectual property. As for people who might have unwittingly violated the
copyright agreement already, “please let us know immediately so that we can
work out any copyright issues before publication.”
So it wasn’t just outsiders such as Suzy
Chapman who needed to fear the copyright police. Nor was it only publication
that might attract their notice. “We ask that you refrain from submitting any
manuscripts . . . without first consulting the APA’s American Psychiatric
Publishing,” Kupfer and Regier wrote. Simply circulating a paper was a no-no.
“It is imperative that our publishing arm and attorney be made aware of any
such instances,” and also of any papers already under consideration. Indeed, it
seemed, any attempt to use the material published on the DSM-5 website in any
venue not approved by the APA would be considered a violation of a copyright
that the lawyers were gearing up to enforce vigorously.
The APA had evidently figured out that
money doesn’t just talk. It can also prevent talking.
“What
possible copyright excuse21 can there be?” Frances asked, when
I told him about the memo.
“It is
just too nutty22,” he wrote a week later. The memo,
the “crazy low reliabilities,” the fact that essential questions had not begun
to be addressed, the way Kupfer and Regier were living inside an echo chamber
and doing all they could to seal off the DSM from the outside world, the
flagrant violation of the most basic academic and scientific freedoms—suddenly
this wasn’t just Keystone Kops antics anymore.
“I used to compare them to the Kremlin,”
he wrote. “But they are really North Korea and that is a whole lot more
dangerous. Expect chaos.”
Chapter 19
A little
bit of chaos did break out at the APA’s 2011 annual meeting in Philadelphia, in
the form of a couple hundred Occupy the APA: Boycott Normal protesters, waving
signs (DSM—MEDICALIZING
THE SYMPTOMS OF LIFE) and chanting chants (“Hey,
hey, APA! How many kids did you kill today?”). Kim Jong-un would probably have
approved of the notices urging attendees to check the credentials of strangers
approaching them with questions (because people “presenting themselves as
journalists are not always who they say they are”) and to refer the unbadged to
the Office of Communications and Public Affairs; the Supreme Leader might even
have given an extra food ration to the security guard who broke up a family
photo session in the main lobby, citing an APA edict banning unauthorized
picture taking.
But the Occupiers were corralled at one
entrance to the sprawling convention center, and at least one unsanctioned (and
officially persona non grata) journalist—that would be me—roamed the halls
unmolested, asking questions of whomever he liked, and if the scene was a
little more tense than in Honolulu, brotherly love reigned supreme over chaos
and fascism most of the time. John Livesley’s highly public resignation from
the personality disorders work group, announced just the week before, didn’t
stop him from participating collegially in forums with the remaining members,
and Andrew Skodol met the continuing, now nearly universal outcry against the
personality disorders proposals with charm and equanimity. Michael First
learned that despite his criticisms, the APA was probably going to renew his
franchise on two DSM-related products—the Structured Clinical Interview for DSM
Disorders and a handbook of differential diagnosis—and would (“after I sign my
life away”) provide him with advance copies so he could get to work. Darrel
Regier and David Kupfer were all smiles and handshakes as they greeted
colleagues before their first presentation about the DSM, held on the first
morning of the meeting.
The session was just a warm-up, an
opportunity for Kupfer and Regier to reiterate the shortcomings of the DSM-IV,
to talk about paradigm shifts without quite saying whether or not the new book
would constitute one, to once again list all the effort, time, and money that
had gone into the revision. As he had in Hawaii, Lawson Wulsin, the APA’s
liaison to other medical specialties, gave his advice on psychiatry’s ongoing
struggle for respectability and money. “Mental illness has been promoted to
constituting a respectable public health problem,” he said. This meant that
psychiatrists now had a huge opportunity, but only if they could “learn how to
work outside their comfort zone, and how to get well paid for it.” The key to
this, he continued, was joining other medical specialties in “integrated care
settings,” where they could deliver “measurement-based care.” The DSM-5, with
its focus on dimensional measures, would be one of the tools psychiatrists
could use to “do well and win at that game.”
The afternoon symposium was the main
event—the public announcement of the results of the field trials. Before the
packed room could hear the numbers, however, Helena Kraemer once again
described her methodology—and the problems with the DSM-III and DSM-IV that she
had attempted to remedy. Since she’d presented it the previous year in Hawaii,
her critique had become a full-on broadside against Spitzer and Frances. Their
sample sizes were too small. They had created conditions that were too
pristine. They had invited conflicts of interest, letting work groups design
the field trials, allowing clinicians to choose subjects most likely to qualify
for the diagnosis in question, taking too much of a hand in adapting the kappa
statistic to the DSM-III, focusing too much on maintaining prevalence rates in
DSM-IV. “There was a bias in those studies,” she said. Spitzer and Frances had
feathered their own nests, but no matter how good the results made their DSMs
look, they were “badly inflated and that causes a problem now.”
The resulting problem—unreasonable
expectations of how reliable psychiatric diagnosis should (or could) be—had a
solution. It was the downward adjustment she had first suggested at the
previous annual meeting, the one where she announced that a kappa of .2 would
be “acceptable.”
“I regret that now,” she said, but not
because such a low number was unacceptable. What she actually meant was that a
result of .2 “might be accepted.” A very low kappa,
she allowed, was a “point of worry,” but by no means should it be automatically
discarded. In fact, an overall reduction in reliability numbers would signify
not that the criteria (or the tests) were faulty, but that the APA’s
researchers had succeeded in duplicating the messiness of the real world.
By that standard, the field trials were an
unalloyed triumph. It was left to Regier to announce the results of the studies
conducted at academic medical centers. He led with schizophrenia, which had
achieved a kappa of .81 in DSM-III and .76 in DSM-IV, but in the DSM-5 came in
at .46. Alcohol Use Disorder scored a .40, compared with .81 in DSM-III. Agreement
on Oppositional-Defiant Disorder was .41, much lower than the .66 found in
DSM-III and the .55 in DSM-IV. Some of the new disorders received relatively
solid ratings—Hoarding Disorder notched a .59, Binge Eating Disorder a .56, and
Disruptive Mood Dysregulation Disorder a .50. But others were dismal, like
Mixed Anxiety-Depression, whose kappa of less than .01 was deemed
“uninterpretable,” as were kappas for four other disorders, including the once
stalwart Obsessive-Compulsive Disorder. Results from the personality disorders
trials were also confounding; Toronto’s Centre for Addiction and Mental Health,
one of Canada’s leading psychiatric hospitals, managed a .75 reliability in
identifying Borderline Personality Disorder, while clinicians at the august
Menninger Clinic in Houston scored only a .34 using the same criteria. Some
reworked disorders did fare better than did their predecessors—PTSD, at .67,
was eight points higher than the DSM-IV trial and beat DSM-III by twelve; ADHD
was also a few points better than it had been, although Regier had to
acknowledge that “we’re still going back and forth” on whether there would be
eighteen or twenty-two criteria; the autism spectrum rang up a solid .69,
although that was much lower than the .85 of the DSM-IV trial for autism.
But these high-ish numbers were the
exceptions, and if the audience members had managed to recalibrate their
expectations, perhaps by reminding themselves that in golf lower is also
better, they were not able to suppress a murmur when Regier announced that the
kappa for Major Depressive Disorder—whose criteria were, other than the removal
of the bereavement exclusion, unchanged—was .32 and that Generalized Anxiety
Disorder had scored a paltry .20.
Something had gone terribly wrong. Those two
diagnoses were the Dodge Dart and Ford Falcon of the DSM, simple and reliable
and ubiquitous, and if clinicians were unable to agree on who warranted them,
there were only a few possible conclusions: that the DSM-III and DSM-IV had
been unreliable from the beginning, that the DSM-5 was unreliable, or that the
field trials were so deeply flawed that it would be impossible to say with any
kind of certainty just how reliable the new book would be.
Darrel Regier is not a demonstrative man.
But even so, he seemed strangely cool, as if he had pumped himself full of
Valium before announcing results that were not merely bad but disastrous.
Hadn’t he promised all along that the field trials would bear out the revisions
and staked his (and the APA’s) reputation, as well as the fate of the DSM-5, on
the results? And didn’t the lower kappas and the discrepancies among sites
signal a return to the dark days before DSM-III, when diagnoses depended more
on where they were rendered and by whom than on what was wrong with the
patient? Here he was, announcing a miserable failure, but if he grasped the
extent of the debacle, nothing about his delivery showed it.
That might be because he had an
explanation, one that seemed to satisfy him. “It’s important to go back and
look at where we were and where we’ve come,” he told us. “We’re in a different
era of statistical sophistication now.” Unlike Spitzer and Frances, “we gave
[clinicians] a set of options and they had to choose,” he explained. In that
unsophisticated era, clinicians “didn’t have other diagnoses to confuse them,”
which is why they got such high kappas. But the DSM-5’s “state-of-the-art
design” had ensured that they would be confused, and the dismal numbers were
the proof of the DSM-5’s validity.
The problem, in other words, was not in
the numbers but in ourselves. We’d swallowed what Spitzer and Frances had
dished out; their comfort food had fattened our expectations, and if the new
numbers challenged our unschooled palates and proved a little hard to digest,
they at least represented the way psychiatric diagnosis works in the real
world. We were just too unsophisticated to understand that failure is success.
• • •
One failure couldn’t be
gussied up, no matter how hard Eve Moscicki, head researcher for the APA’s
Practice Research Network, tried. And try she did, as she presented the results
of the Routine Clinical Practice trial, the one in which I had participated.
She tried the Kraemer gambit, lowering the bar at the outset by explaining that
“this is a first-time presentation” that would offer only “a flavor of the
results.” She tried Regierian obfuscation, telling us only how many patients
had been enrolled, but not how many of the five thousand clinicians who signed
up had actually completed the study. (“I don’t have the exact numbers off the
top of my head,” she said during the Q&A, but she finally had to
acknowledge that only 640 had submitted data on at least one patient.) She
tried distraction, blaming the failure on bureaucratic delays and the
unexpectedly long software training rather than on the study’s design, its
imposition of a near-impossible burden of conducting hours-long interviews
using unfamiliar instruments whose clinical value was questionable and whose
reimbursement value was zero. She tried the corporate mission-statement
approach—reframing the “unique challenges” faced by the APA as “opportunities
for innovative resolutions.” She even went Hollywood, calling her talk “Trials,
Tribulations, and Triumphs,” as if it were an elevator pitch for a movie about
a plucky heroine overcoming adversity.
If all her bobbing and weaving hadn’t
tipped us off to the extent of the fiasco, it became obvious about fifteen
minutes into her talk when, after one last reminder that her study was about
the feasibility and usefulness of the revisions and not their reliability, she
finally flashed some data on the screen—a bar graph depicting how easy (or
hard) clinicians found the new criteria to use.
“For ADHD, the majority of clinicians
thought it was very easy or extremely easy,” she said. The same was true, she
went on, for autistic disorders, anxiety, and depression. This might have been
a bright moment in an otherwise bleak afternoon but for one thing: according to
the graph, while the narrowest majority (52 percent) had indeed given a
thumbs-up to ADHD and anxiety disorders, the number who thought the autism and
depression criteria and measures were very easy or extremely easy to use was
below 50 percent. Moscicki didn’t seem to notice this discrepancy between the
story she was telling us and the data she was showing us. Perhaps she thought
that since she was presenting only a flavor, she was free to add sweeteners to
taste, or maybe she just didn’t care what we thought, or figured that no one
would point out the discrepancies, no matter how obvious, for the same reason
that people are reluctant to mention that a coworker smells bad or has left his
fly unzipped: because you really don’t want to embarrass him.
And up to a point, she was right.
Moscicki switched from “ease of use” to
“usefulness.” She put up the slide about ADHD and autism diagnoses.
“It looks to me like . . . I want . . .”
She trailed off and peered at the slide, which showed even more anemic results
than the earlier one. It was as if she had never seen it before, although she
may only have been calculating the odds of getting away with this forever. “It
looks to me like almost a majority for ADHD thought the criteria were pretty
useful, and for autism, clearly the majority thought the criteria . . .”
A man’s voice rang out in the darkened
room. “It’s not a majority,” he said. “Look, thirty-seven plus seven”—the
“very” and “extremely useful” numbers—“doesn’t equal fifty.”
The interrupter, who turned out to be a
blogger for Scientific American, didn’t bother asking
exactly what “pretty useful” was supposed to mean. He didn’t ask Moscicki if
she thought it was kosher to make up a diagnostic entity called trauma, which she acknowledged she had teased out of the
anxiety disorders and which looked suspiciously like a category she had cooked
up so she could parade its 62 percent favorable rating. He didn’t point out the
lunacy of spending all that time (including mine) and money to find out not
whether the criteria or the cross-cutting measures were reliable or valid, but
rather only whether clinicians liked the DSM-5, as if the APA were looking for
Facebook friends. He didn’t raise the question of selection bias, that is,
whether or not the same factors that motivated the few volunteers who actually
followed through also predisposed them to give the DSM a Like. He didn’t have
to do any of this. Nor did he have to deconstruct propaganda or slog through
weedy statistics. He just did the simple math and came to the obvious
conclusion.
“This is totally appalling,” he said.
“It’s okay, it’s okay,” Moscicki replied.
It was not clear whom she meant to comfort. “This is a first look. If it’s not
a majority, it’s a large number of them.”
But her antagonist wasn’t buying it.
“This is deceptive,” he said, as he slung
his backpack over his shoulder, spun on his heel, and stormed out.
Like the kid in the story about the
emperor’s clothes, he had managed to say out loud what everyone in the room, or
at least those who could add, must have been thinking: that Moscicki had
crossed the Frankfurt Line, the one between bullshit and lies.
• • •
The conference featured at
least one glimmer of good news for nosologists. Regier mentioned it a couple of
times in his various talks, but the honor of revealing it went to Charles
O’Brien, a University of Pennsylvania psychiatrist and head of the DSM-5 work
group for substance-related disorders.
Before O’Brien got down to the business at
hand—his committee’s proposals—he turned to the business of business. “People
should understand that when they read things in the newspaper about Pharma
influence, I don’t believe it,” he said, as he made the conflict-of-interest
disclosure required of every speaker. “We stopped that a long time ago, even
though in the past we might have had some consultancies.” O’Brien didn’t say
exactly what they had stopped, but it clearly wasn’t the consultancies. Indeed,
he was still working for three drug companies. “Only two of them are actually
producing drugs that you can prescribe or buy,” he explained, and this work “is
really socially important, because there are very few medications available and
not many companies are working on this.” The public fails to understand this,
and psychiatry (or at least psychiatrists’ income) is the victim of its
ignorance.
This was a riff that could not help but
ingratiate O’Brien with his audience. And he needed all the help he could get.
He had to explain to his colleagues, many of them skeptical, why his group had
eliminated the categories of substance abuse and substance dependence, which the DSM-IV had used to sort out
the people who merely get in trouble with drugs from those who get addicted to
them. In their place, the committee proposed the supercategory of substance use disorders, which, it said, occurred whenever
there was a “problematic pattern” of substance use that led to “clinically
significant impairment and distress.” O’Brien’s group, perhaps remembering that
no one had yet defined clinical significance, had listed eleven further
criteria. If an impaired patient met two of them, he or she had the disorder.
So, for instance, if in a twelve-month period you “often” drink “larger amounts
or over a longer period than intended,” and experience “craving or strong
desire or urge to use alcohol,” you qualified for Alcohol Use Disorder. The few
studies that had been done using the new diagnoses indicated that many people
looked forward intensely to their next party and, when they got there, took
that third martini or extra toke—enough, in fact, to cause some Australian
researchers to forecast a DSM-5-related 60
percent increase1 in the prevalence of drug-related
diagnoses.
O’Brien thought these warnings were
balderdash, but he also thought the DSM-IV was balderdash. “I feel free to
criticize DSM-IV,” he said, because he’d been part of that revision, which he
now characterized as “a bunch of wise men sitting around a table and asking
what happens when people start using drugs.”
“Although we thought we were wise, we were
wrong,” he said. “There is no evidence to support this idea of drug abuse.”
Not that people don’t use drugs to their
own or others’ detriment. But the problem isn’t that sometimes the use causes
collateral damage (abuse) or becomes habitual (dependence). The problem is
“compulsive, out-of-control drug seeking.” O’Brien would have preferred to call
the reformulated disorder addiction, but “some people
have a kind of allergy to the word,” believing that it carries too much stigma.
Avoiding the a-word is “useless,” O’Brien said. “When you have the president
talking about addiction to oil, the word has lost its pejorative tone,” and
besides, even if the president did mean it pejoratively, addiction is “what the
average doctor is going to call it.” But the chair was evidently outvoted, and
the anodyne new name won the day.
Whatever its name, O’Brien had no doubt
about the nature of the problem. “Addiction is a brain disease,” he said. Of
course, this was the tacit assumption of the DSM, not to mention of psychiatric
nosology for the last hundred years: that what psychiatrists were treating were
illnesses that originated in the brain, and that someday they would find out
exactly where and how. That promise, O’Brien reminded the crowd, had gone
unfulfilled. “Let’s take depression or anger or any of the other things we
diagnose,” he said. “They’re all subjective. You have to get hints from what
the patient says and how they say it, but you have no test for it.”
On the other hand, “we do have tests for
craving,” he said. “I think craving could become the first biomarker in
psychiatry. I can show you where it is in the brain.” And so he did, flashing a
photo on the screen. “If you’re an addict,” he said, “you’re noticing this
person is booting right now.” Actually, you didn’t have to be an addict; the
picture featured a tied-off arm, a blood-filled syringe stuck into a tracked-up
vein. What would be different if you were an addict—at least it would if you
had just been given a shot of carbon-11 raclopride, a radioactive marker, and a
PET scanner had just detected its emissions—is the way your brain would light
up upon beholding this image. “This is the caudate, this is the putamen,”
O’Brien said, pointing to the next slide, a chart of an addict’s neural
activity. “There’s a complete correlation here between the subjective feeling
of craving and the degree of inhibition of the binding of raclopride.”
Similarly, said O’Brien, show an alcoholic an image related to drinking, and
you will notice “increased blood flow to the cingulate gyrus, the anterior cingulate,
the insula, and the nucleus accumbens down here.” In both cases, you’re seeing
disturbances in dopamine metabolism, “the reward system,” as O’Brien put it.
You’re seeing addiction—not the experience, which can only be described in
words and assayed subjectively, but the thing itself—caught when it thought no
one was looking, naked and unmistakable.
Of course, there was a catch. “The
clinician would have to have a brain-imaging machine,” said O’Brien. “But these
are getting to be very common,” he added. He didn’t have to explain to this
crowd what that really meant: that devices like brain scanners could be huge
profit centers, a way to go outside their comfort zone and get well paid for
it, as Lawson Wulsin would put it, to win at the game by delivering the
measurement-based care that insurers crave.
It’s too bad the doctors’ brains weren’t
being scanned as they gazed upon the evidence that their most fevered cravings
were on the verge of fulfillment, that after a century of wandering in the
biomedical desert, one psychiatrist was ready to lead them home.
O’Brien ended his talk by pointing out
that it’s not just boozers and cokeheads whose addiction (and, presumably,
recovery) can be verified by the magic machines. “We’ve listed gambling with
the use disorders and we’ve put Internet Use Disorder in the Appendix,” O’Brien
said. He’d saved it to the end, but this news was hardly an afterthought. By
poaching what the DSM-IV had called Pathological Gambling from the disorders of
impulse control work group, his committee had pulled off a coup. It had made
official what once was only folk wisdom: that we could be addicted to behaviors
as well as to drugs. We could be workaholics and shopaholics, sex addicts and
love addicts, hooked on cyberporn and jonesing for carbs. (Indeed, the first
question O’Brien fielded was from the head of the Food Addiction Institute, who
demanded to know why food addiction hadn’t been
included.) Any strong desire could be put under surveillance and diagnosed with
dead certainty, and any behavior with the telltale signs, anything that set
that circuitry in motion, could be called a disease.
The brain scanner, O’Brien said, “tells us
directly what’s going on.” And that’s the beauty part: no need to take your
hints from what junkies or boozers say or how they say it. Indeed, there’s no
need to talk (or listen) to them at all. Neither is there any reason to pay
attention to those English professors and other amateurs who, emboldened by the
DSM’s simple language, might kvetch that it might not be such a good idea to
pathologize desire in a country where people line up at midnight to buy the
newest iPhone, where greed is a virtue and the pursuit of wealth a spectator
sport, where an entire economy depends on an endless cycle of craving and not-quite-satisfaction.
When the DSM is finally full of words like nucleus accumbens
and putamen, these critics will be out of business.
And so will the rest of us. Because if the
brain scanners fulfill their promise, psychiatrists will finally be able to cut
out the middleman entirely, and with him the subjectivity that was once
psychiatry’s bread and butter, but which, especially when it comes to
diagnosis, has become its bane. After all, who needs dimensional assessment
forms, let alone the stunted conversations that allow clinicians to fill them
in, when you have raclopride?
• • •
While Regier was presenting
the results of the field trials, the 159 voting members of the APA Assembly
were taking up a question of great importance to him. Roger Peele, the assembly’s
representative to the DSM-5 task force, had proposed an action paper that
called for all the dimensional measures Regier had proposed—the cross-cutting
assessments, the severity scales, and the personality disorder ratings—to be
placed in Section 3, the task force’s new name for the Appendix, where they
would await “further study.”
“I
wanted to avoid a repeat of Axis V2,” Peele told me,
referring to the DSM-IV scale that asks a clinician to rate a patient’s overall
functioning from 1 to 100. Once that measure had been instituted, Peele
remembered, “insurance companies used it as a basis to deny service.” The
result was predictable—“One of the first things you were told when you joined a
hospital staff was, ‘Doctor, all Axis V’s on this ward are a forty or
less’”—and regrettable.
“It makes a farce of psychiatry,” he said.
And it wasn’t just the insurance companies
whose demands turned psychiatry into a game of Diagnosing for Dollars. A public
sector psychiatrist, Peele knew that bureaucracies like his were number-crazy.
If the DSM offered measures, then clinicians were sure to be compelled to use
them, and their workload would increase—a problem obscured by the Facebook
approach to evaluating the measures. “The ‘liking’ of severity scales . . . by
clinicians volunteering to be part of the DSM-5 field trials is not necessarily
representative of the vast majority of American clinicians who did not
volunteer to be part of such trials despite many opportunities to do so,” he
wrote in the resolution.
Perhaps the burden of the dimensions would
have been worthwhile, and the method of evaluating them unimportant, had they
had any scientific integrity. But “most, if not all, are not based on science,”
Peele told me—and that was assuming you could even find out what they were.
“Some of them are so immature that if you go to the website, they aren’t even
shown.” And indeed, even at this late date, a click on the tab for many
proposed measures returned the message that “recommendations . . . are
forthcoming. We encourage you to check our Web site regularly for updates.”
The day before the assembly meeting,
Regier had had a chance to defend himself to a committee with the power to
endorse the resolution to the full body. He spoke longer than anyone else at
the meeting, but nothing he said swayed the committee, which recommended the
passage of the resolution; and the very next day the assembly voted unanimously
to send the dimensional measures, which Regier had once promised as the key to
springing the APA from its epistemic prison, to the elephant burial ground.
• • •
As he had in Hawaii, Michael
First spent the beginning days of the meeting hanging out with this year’s
gathering of the Association for the Advancement of Philosophy and Psychiatry.
It wasn’t quite so captivating this time around. “Too much name-dropping of
philosophers whose work I am not familiar with,” he told me, “so the arguments
are too hard to follow.”
Still, First knew enough about philosophy
and its significance to the DSM to have once put his name on a paper urging the
task force to appoint a DSM-5 work group that would take up “conceptual issues”
such as the definition of mental disorder. “Conceptual
questions are not minor ‘side issues3’ to be dealt with
in improvised ways,” the group wrote. “Conceptual clarification is a critical
partner to good scientific work . . . [and] advances the scientific rigor of
our work.” The paper was published in 2008. The task force never responded.
Four years later, and too late for them to
have any impact, the philosophers were given a chance to philosophize at one of
the annual meeting’s official symposia—“Philosophical and Pragmatic Problems
for DSM-5.” But, as they had in Hawaii, they remained mostly on the fringes,
this time at a Crowne Plaza a few blocks from the convention center, where the
elevator actually stopped at the floor of the meeting room. Everyone attending
had heard David Kupfer assert that the DSM was all but completed, and the
panels on ideology and the role of science in medicine and other chewy issues
seemed more like pathologists’ probes at a postmortem than clarifications
contributed by critical partners.
First was the discussant for the
symposium, which the APA had scheduled for the same time slot as the
field-trial session. He had asked me to report the results to him. He shook his
head as I read them off.
“Point twenty for GAD?” he asked.
“Really?”
He ventured an explanation. The new
criteria required a clinician to determine if the patient’s anxiety led him or
her to avoid activities “with possible negative outcomes” or to procrastinate
“due to worries” or to “repeatedly [seek] reassurance.” These, First thought,
were vague notions, poorly written and untested; it was no surprise that
clinicians could not agree on them.
This much, he acknowledged, was
speculation. But that was his point: he had to speculate, and so would the
people who had to figure out what to do with the DSM-5, because the field trials
had not been designed to find out what had gone wrong, nor was there time for a
second round to see if the problem, whatever it was, had been fixed. There was
only one possible solution, First said: to go back to the DSM-IV definition.
I thought I might have glimpsed, for the
first time, some Firstian schadenfreude, but he sounded more disappointed than
gloating, like a professor explaining a concept to hardheaded students for the
umpteenth time. He told me he was beginning to give up hope that the APA would
listen to him, that indeed he was already looking beyond the publication of
DSM-5. As the problems of the new book became clear, he thought the APA might
draft him back into service, giving him a chance once again to do what he’d
been born to do. After the conference, I suggested that if the DSM-5 turned out
as he feared it might, he was likely to have his work cut out for him. “Yes,” he said, “but I do like a challenge4.”
• • •
Susan Swedo, chief of the Pediatrics
and Developmental Neuroscience Branch at NIMH, started her talk on the second
day by announcing she’d changed her title from the original “Neurodevelopmental
Disorders, Including Autism Spectrum Disorder, Intellectual Developmental
Disorder and Learning Disorder” to “Making National Headlines.” And it wasn’t
because the new title was catchier.
“I felt
if I just addressed5 what is being said about our
criteria versus what they actually say,” she explained, “maybe you’d come away
with a better idea of what we are doing.”
As much as she might have wanted to
deliver the straight skinny to her colleagues, Swedo also wanted to settle some
scores.
“The most glaring [headline] was in The New York Times,” she said. It had reported that
Volkmar’s data had been “presented at a major medical meeting.” Swedo took a
beat. “That major medical meeting turned out to be the winter meeting of the
Icelandic Medical Association.”
The crowd tittered, and Regier laughed
into his microphone.
“Thank you for laughing,” Swedo said.
“Because there are about 250,000 people in Iceland, which means there are maybe
half a dozen child psychiatrists in the country.”
If there were any Icelandic patriots in
the crowd to defend their homeland (or just to tell Swedo that Iceland’s
population is about 320,000), they kept silent. Reporter Ben
Carey was definitely not present, so he couldn’t point out that his article
didn’t call the Iceland conference a “major medical meeting.” And Fred Volkmar
was back in New Haven, so he wasn’t able to remind Swedo that he had first
presented his data in fall 2011, at the American Academy of Adolescent and
Child Psychiatry’s annual conference, which is about as major as a meeting
gets, and one at which she was also on the program.
Darrel Regier was there, and he had to
listen as Swedo described her field-trial results as “superb,” then, as if
remembering the kerfuffle over the meaning of kappa, corrected herself. “I’m
sorry. Not superb. Very good. Superb only compared with the rest of DSM.”
Regier wasn’t laughing anymore, but he didn’t object out loud to the slight,
either. He was, after all, a veteran of scorched-earth campaigns; he must have
known Swedo wasn’t taking prisoners, that it was best to stay out of her way.
It’s too bad no one was in attendance from
the Asperger’s Association of New England, the group to which Nomi Kaim
belongs. It would have been interesting to hear the organization’s response
when Swedo, after complaining about all the people who had blown up her e-mail
in-box after Carey and Volkmar had unnecessarily struck “fear in their hearts”
and dismissing Volkmar’s study as “comparing apples to Apple computers” (but
without refuting his data), explained why she thought it was safe to ignore their
objections. “Most of the individuals who belong to the AANE call themselves
Aspies,” she said, “but that may need to be a new diagnosis introduced in
future editions of the DSM, because Aspies don’t actually have Asperger’s
Disorder, much less Autism Spectrum Disorders.”
In the Q&A, I asked Swedo how she knew
this.
“By my interactions with them,” she said.
“We have been petitioned by so-called Aspies and literally they are writing to
us and saying I am an Aspie . . . and they describe what, if they had seen a
psychiatrist, might have been called Obsessive-Compulsive Personality
Disorder.”
“So based on your interaction, you can
conclude that people who call themselves Aspies don’t have Asperger’s?” I
asked. Was she really diagnosing people whom she knew only through their
letters of complaint? Did she maybe want to qualify this or elaborate on her
earlier comment that Aspies were simply “Norwegian bachelor farmers, just a
little awkward . . . but we would consider them to have a normal variation”?
Did she mean to confirm in a public forum the worst fears of people with
Asperger’s and their families: that the APA, convinced that they had made it on
to the sick rolls illegitimately, was determined to kick them off?
Swedo backpedaled a little, allowing that
some of the AANE members might indeed have Asperger’s, but still, she insisted,
“there is an element of folks . . . who do not meet the criteria for DSM-IV.”
Whatever they had, and they may well have had something (after all, they were
harassing her), “it just didn’t have the same flavor as Asperger’s.”
Not that it really mattered, as Swedo’s
answer to another questioner indicated. By now, she was sitting next to Regier
and other panel members at a table, and the man wanted to hear from any or all
of them what role the availability of services had played in the revision.
Swedo took the mic. She told him a story about the field-trial clinician who
had sent her a note saying, “My patient did not meet criteria for autism, but I
know he has it, so I gave him the diagnosis anyway.”
This would have been the perfect time for
Swedo to dress down her correspondent with the same withering sarcasm she’d
used on Volkmar and Carey. After all, wasn’t this a perfect illustration of all
that was wrong with the DSM-IV—that it had turned clinicians’ instincts,
leavened by sympathy, into a diagnostic epidemic? Hadn’t the purpose of DSM-5
been to put an end to this kind of discretion and revoke the benefits of
diagnosis from all those undeserving bachelor farmers?
Apparently not.
“I think this is actually quite
appropriate,” Swedo said. “If the clinician’s gut feeling is that the patient
has the disorder, it’s appropriate for them to get [the diagnosis], to give
them the services, the treatment, whatever needs to happen.”
Swedo paused briefly. But if she was
weighing the implications of suggesting that doctors ignore the new criteria
the APA had just spent $25 million to fashion, if she was reconsidering what
her comments meant for her profession’s scientific credibility or for the reputation
of the man sitting right next to her, if she was even aware that she had just
admitted that the whole enterprise was a confidence game, a way to give doctors
plausible scientific cover even as they continued to diagnose and medicate
their patients based on their gut feelings, their whims and fancies and
judgments, it wasn’t evident when she resumed her answer.
“So politically it’s gotten a little
messy,” she said, “but scientifically and clinically I think we remain
committed to the idea that the purpose of the DSM is to provide clinicians with
a road map. We’re not driving the car.”
And the map doesn’t really matter, because
even if clinicians load the DSM into their GPS units, they’re going to take the
routes their gut tells them are best. And if a doctor decides to head for
uncharted territory, to lead his colleagues into the land where irritable
children suffer Bipolar Disorder, or where attraction to thirteen-year-olds is
Hebephilia, or a slave’s thirst for freedom is a symptom of drapetomania, if he
thinks his MD plates entitle him to take his patients off-road or the wrong way
down a one-way street or, for that matter, over a cliff, well, that’s not the
APA’s fault.
• • •
Within two hours of the
release of the field-trial data, Allen Frances had written a new blog post: “Newsflash from APA Meeting6:
DSM-5 Has Flunked Its Reliability Test.”
“The DSM-5 has managed to fail in ways
that go beyond my poor imagination,” he wrote. “Reliability this low . . .
gravely undermines the credibility of DSM-5,” and the result would be a “book
no one can trust.” The field trials thus signaled a “DSM-5 emergency”—an
imminent loss of the authority that the DSM-III had earned and the DSM-IV had
preserved—and the only way to “salvage this deplorable mess” was to reinstate
the second round of field trials, which, of course, would mean delaying
publication.
Speaking of deplorable messes, the blog
(which appeared on the Psychology Today website)
contained a table of the results with misaligned columns, indecipherable
abbreviations, and unintelligible figures. It looked as if it had been
assembled hastily on a BlackBerry, which it had—but not Frances’s. I’d sent the
list to him while Bill Narrow was droning on about something or other, and he’d
copied and pasted it with my clumsy thumbwork intact.
Partly I did it because I was bored. And
partly I did it for the same reason that your cat drops a beheaded mouse on
your doorstep: to express gratitude for your care and feeding, and, maybe, to
curry further favor. Although sometimes you have to wonder if Snowball is
trying to make a point by leaving a bleeding carcass for you to find first
thing in the morning—to remind you, perhaps, that while you may have an
electric can opener, in the tooth-and-claw world she still has an advantage.
Cats are sly and complicated creatures.
I wish I could say that I was too, and
that I had somehow tricked Frances into revealing one of psychiatry’s dark
little secrets when he wrote:
The great value to the
field of DSM-III was that it established reliability and preserved the
credibility of psychiatry at a time when it was becoming irrelevant because it
seemed that psychiatrists could not agree on a diagnosis. Everyone knew that
the reliability achieved in DSM field testing far exceeds what is possible in
clinical practice, but DSM-III took the major step of proving that reliability
could be achieved at all.
But I’m not that clever. And
Frances doesn’t need to be tricked into saying this, nor would he agree that it
has ever been a secret. In his world, the DSM was never more than a book of
useful constructs validated in idealized settings, and this is not a problem
because the point was never to establish the truth about mental disorders. But
Frances had a questionable conviction as well: that he could trash the DSM-5
without trashing his profession.
“The
controversy stirred by my critique7 of DSM-5 is a
terrible moment in the history of psychiatry,” he told me the month after the
annual meeting. “This is the worst thing to happen to the field’s credibility
since Rosenhan—and psychiatry is a field that especially requires credibility
to be effective. I know I have done grave harm.”
Frances reasoned that the damage to
misdiagnosed and overdiagnosed patients was a graver harm than undermining
psychiatry’s credibility with the truth. It was the kind of calculation
Cincinnatus might have made, hoping to hasten his return to the farm. Frances
had gambled that the fragile edifice Spitzer had erected and he had reinforced
would withstand the weight of the truth, that one of the guardians of the noble
lie could reveal it and yet somehow preserve the authority the lie had
purchased. And even as he fended off more antipsychiatrists drafting him
unwillingly into their cause and more attorneys eager to use his own criticisms
to undermine his (and his profession’s) credibility, he continued to be certain
he’d made the right choice.
It’s possible he was compelled by
unconscious inner necessity to blurt out the truth, or that contrition or
self-loathing or that old Freudian notion, the death instinct—the
inbuilt yearning for the chaos that the lies of civilization, noble and
otherwise, hold at bay—drove him. He would say that what he did was much
simpler than that, that it grew from an easy calculus, nearly bureaucratic in
its plainness: that the only chance to preserve the DSM’s hard-won authority
was to stop the APA from going ahead with the worst of its ideas—especially
those, like removing the bereavement exclusion, that would badly cashier the
reputation of his beloved profession. He would also say that it doesn’t require
vast sophistication to grasp the reality: that a language by which two doctors
can agree on a name for a patient’s subjective suffering is a signal
achievement no matter how contrived, and worth preserving despite its many
flaws.
In this, he may have overestimated the
value of that language. He may also have overestimated the tolerance of
Americans for bullshit. But above all, Allen Frances may have overestimated
himself.
Chapter 20
Or maybe
it was just me he overestimated.
In October 2012, I join Frances and
Manning in a hotel room near Harvard Medical School, where Frances is scheduled
to address a bioethics seminar. A documentarian working on a film about the DSM
is setting up her equipment. She has finally caught up with Frances after a
four-month chase. He has decided that she should interview the two of us
together. It’s not entirely clear to me if she is on board with that idea.
Since June, Frances has mostly been quiet about the DSM. He is still blogging
for The Huffington Post and Psychology
Today and the Psychiatric Times, where he has
weighed in on gun control and the presidential election and offered “to stop
being an amateur columnist” if David Brooks would “stop being an amateur
psychologist.” But the DSM has never been far from his mind, and as soon as the
lights are on and the camera is running, he is back to it and drawing me into
his explanation of all that has gone wrong with the DSM-5. I may be an
upside-down Jesuit and he a world-weary rationalist, but for the moment, we’re
just a couple of friends on the inside of the same joke. The filmmaker seems
entertained, although it’s possible she is simply egging us on in hopes of
capturing some outrageous Francesism on film. But he’s become more careful. In
fact, he tells the camera, he’s learned his lesson, the one about how
impertinent remarks might, in the wrong hands, turn his attacks on DSM-5 into
attacks on psychiatry.
The director describes an Internet video
she has seen, put out, she says, by Scientology’s Citizens Commission on Human
Rights, in which the narrator somberly intones that even the head of the DSM-IV
thinks psychiatry is bullshit. Frances looks over at me, vindicated.
The thing I don’t understand, he tells me
(and I’m working from memory here; I didn’t tape our meeting), is that you
think the words in the DSM are capable of great harm. So why aren’t you worried
about the harm your words can do?
The question makes me think of the
infamous line with which Janet Malcolm opened her book The
Journalist and the Murderer. “Every journalist who is not too stupid or
too full of himself to notice what is going on knows that what he does is morally
indefensible.” Malcolm was writing about the way Joe McGinniss had seduced and
betrayed Jeffrey MacDonald, promising exoneration and then penning indictment.
But Frances is accusing me of more than luring him into candor with assurances
that my criticism of psychiatric diagnosis was tempered by a recognition of its
uses, and then using him as a cudgel in my own crusade against psychiatry.
Indeed, he has always insisted he doesn’t care about his own image, and while
that may be a little too much protest, it’s not hard to believe that his
worries are genuine, and that my real betrayal is using his comment to harm the
people who need to have confidence in their doctors (and keep taking their
drugs) to get better. If the discrepancy between opportunity and knowledge
remains under wraps, it seems, that’s not bullshit. That’s wisely deploying the
placebo effect. That’s medicine.
The camera is rolling, or whatever it is
that digital cameras do. I’m pinned and wriggling, scrambling for some way to
explain why I don’t seem to care about what happens when people glimpse what’s
behind the curtain. It isn’t the first time a psychiatrist has warned me that
criticizing the profession would lead to dire consequences. It’s the
profession’s stock response to anyone who attacks it, and I have a stock
rebuttal: that I am sure more people have been hurt by the DSM, or at least by
the treatments that follow diagnosis, than by anything I ever wrote. Yet it
seems inadequate to the moment. I say some words, but they don’t really make
sense, and they surely don’t answer his question. Frances sits back in his
chair.
He has the right to his satisfaction. It
is true that I didn’t give a moment’s thought to the question of whether
reporting Frances’s comment (along with a lot of evidence that he is right)
would hurt anyone. I always figure people are better off with the truth, which
is probably why I went into both the therapy and the journalism businesses—and
why I get angry when one of those professions hides its own uncomfortable truths.
But as much as I like the way that sounds, maybe I’m just too full of myself to
see that I’m using Frances and the patients, that they have become character
and audience, and that I’m using truth as well, not as a virtue but as a
narrative device, as the MacGuffin for exposing humbuggery and chronicling
comeuppance, and that to undermine the already shaky foundations of a
profession that offers the last and only hope for some patients—that has
succeeded, at least in some cases, at quelling their hallucinations, modulating
their mood swings, allaying their anxiety, and restoring them to some semblance
of normal functioning—and to bring low the confidence man at the expense of his
potentially satisfied customers is simply indefensible.
• • •
But then again, so is
psychiatry, at least when it comes to the DSM. And not because the DSM-5 was
botched or because the profession is a cabal of Pharma collaborators, although
it harbors its fair share of both incompetents and conspirators, but because
even at its best, even in the view of honest and eloquent men like Steve Hyman
and Allen Frances, psychiatric diagnosis is fiction sold to the public as fact.
And not the Supreme Fiction that Wallace Stevens says begins “by perceiving the
idea / Of this invention, this invented world,” but a fallen fiction whose
authors, if they are to hold on to their power, must insist that they have
gathered together the scattered particulars of our suffering and sorted them
according to their natural formations, even as they harbor the knowledge that
they have done no such thing. That knowledge can be locked up, like Leibowitz’s
Memorabilia in its monastery, but it will always escape when the DSM is opened
for revision and doctors once again argue over matters that their science cannot
settle.
Later that day, Frances is once again
called upon to defend psychiatry against his own charges. In an elegant
wood-paneled room at Harvard, just after he has told a group made up mostly of
doctors why expert consensus—the method that has yielded the DSM—is both
necessary and dangerous to public health, Arnold Relman, the
eighty-nine-year-old former editor of The New England Journal
of Medicine, professor emeritus at Harvard, and a longtime critic of
for-profit health care, suggests that this tension is worse in psychiatry than
in other specialties because psychiatric experts lack biological findings that
can anchor diagnosis in something beyond the symptom. Where is psychiatry’s
pneumococcus, Relman seems to be asking. Frances has fielded this question
before, and he has a ready answer: that diagnostic uncertainty and lack of
treatment specificity haunt all of medicine.
It’s a version of the argument Steve Mirin
and Darrel Regier once made to the editors of The Washington
Post, and it was not entirely wrong. There are plenty
of illnesses that are described purely in terms of their symptoms—chronic
headache, for example, or idiopathic neuropathy—and devastating diseases, such
as multiple sclerosis and cancer, that seem unlikely to have a single form caused
by a single pathogen like pneumococcus. And while it is true that those
diseases are often diagnosed by lab studies, if only to rule out other known
causes of their symptoms, psychiatry is still not so different from other
specialties in this sense.
But even if medical nosology, taken in the
aggregate, is as fictive as psychiatric nosology, even if many of its diagnoses
are merely descriptions of the problem in a medical language, still it would
have its pneumococcus and its polio and its diabetes, not to mention its heart
diseases and bone fractures, its blood counts and biopsies and X-rays, its
antibiotics and vaccines, its cobalt-chromium stents and titanium joints, its
brain surgeries and organ transplants. Even if its unknowns far surpass its knowns,
medicine undeniably has its slam dunks. Even when they are found by accident,
as they often are, and even when they seem miraculons, as they often do, these
are not miracles or mere serendipities, but the discovery of the natural laws
that govern our suffering. Medicine’s sure knowledge of those laws saves our
lives and earns doctors our deference.
This is precisely what psychiatry lacks.
Without a single mental disorder that meets the scientific demands of the day,
let alone enough of them to make the DSM more than an invented world, and with
its claim to “real medicine” still mostly aspirational, it cannot make good on
its assertion that psychological suffering is best understood as medical
illness. So it must guard its position jealously. Lacking confidence in itself,
psychiatry must work ever harder to command ours. This is what unites the APA,
with its circle-the-wagons paranoia, its deceptions and duplicity and tortured
language, and Allen Frances, with his invocations of Leibowitz and his warnings
about patients gone wild. He and Darrel Regier may be bitter opponents, but
they both have the fear that comes with knowing the fragility of the edifice
they share.
• • •
The APA had at least one
opportunity for a slam dunk in the DSM-5. In an article published in The American Journal of Psychiatry, an international group
of seventeen prominent men—including clinicians, psychoanalytically minded
personality theorists, historians of medicine, biological psychiatrists,
critics of biological psychiatry, and Bob Spitzer—urged the DSM Task Force to
include in the DSM-5 a disorder they called melancholia.
“Melancholia,” they wrote1,
is “a syndrome with a long history and distinctly specific psychopathological
features.” Melancholia is Winston Churchill’s black dog, Andrew Solomon’s
noonday demon (an image he borrowed from Isaiah), William Styron’s darkness
visible—a form of depression noted by doctors since Hippocrates and
characterized by an unshakable despondency and sense of guilt that arises from
nowhere, responds to nothing, and dissipates for no apparent reason.
The authors drew on thirty years of
research to describe five clinical characteristics by which melancholia could
be distinguished from other kinds of depression. Among those characteristics
were biological findings that set the melancholics apart, notably hypercortisolemia and disturbances in sleep
architecture. A sleep study could show whether or not patients had the
reduced deep sleep and increased REM time characteristic of melancholia. And a
dexamethasone suppression test (DST)—in which patients
were given a synthetic steroid to see if it suppressed the activity of their
own hormonal system—could determine whether their cortisol, a stress hormone,
was in overdrive. Patients who meet the criteria for melancholia are much more
likely than other depressed people to show this abnormality. They are also much
more likely than other depressives to respond to two treatments: tricyclic
antidepressants (drugs discovered in the late 1950s and in wide use before the
Prozac era) and electroconvulsive therapy (ECT),
better known as shock treatment, and they show less response to both placebos
and cognitive-behavioral therapy. Melancholia, the proponents concluded, was a
“distinct, identifiable, and specifically
treatable2 affective syndrome.” It might even
be, although they didn’t say this, a type of depression that actually was the
result of a real chemical imbalance, a disorder onto which our biochemistry
could be mapped.
The proposal included plenty of standard
scientific evidence—clinical and lab studies, case histories, literature
reviews—and, with its tie to cortisol, melancholia seemed to fit in with
emerging theories about depression and stress. So you would think that the APA
would have leaped at the opportunity to finally prove to dismissive doctors in
other specialties and to a skeptical public that, at least in this one case,
psychiatrists were real doctors treating real diseases that could be discerned
with real tests and treated with real cures.
But you would be wrong. Melancholia not
only failed to gain inclusion, it was not even given much consideration. Only
five days after he had received the group’s proposal, in October 2008, mood
disorders work group member William Coryell was already telling Max Fink, one
of melancholia’s main proponents, that the odds were very long. The main
obstacle was exactly what Fink and his colleagues thought was one of the great
strengths of the proposal: the biological tests, especially the DST. “I believe the inclusion of a biological measure3
would be very hard to sell to the mood group,” Coryell wrote Fink—and not
because the test was unreliable. “I agree there is more data to support using
the DST for melancholia than for using any other measure for any other
diagnosis,” he conceded. Even so, the DST would be “very hard to sell since it
would be . . . the only biological test for any diagnosis being considered.”
Coryell didn’t finish the thought, but the implication was obvious: a test for
melancholia would make the lack of biological measures elsewhere in the DSM
that much more glaring. It was a success that would only highlight the APA’s
failures. (Coryell declined to comment.)
Sixteen months later, when the APA posted
its first draft of the DSM-5, Coryell was proven correct. Melancholia didn’t
even show up in the mood disorders section; it had merited only a single line
in a section of “conditions proposed by others”—a category it shared with
Parental Alienation Syndrome and Male-to-Eunuch Gender Identity Disorder, among
others.
“I [am]
flabbergasted4 that our suggestion . . . has been
excluded from consideration,” Fink wrote to Coryell. “Carving out a
well-defined type of mood disorder, one that carries with it the promise of
homogeneous samples and optimized treatment outcomes, is a small step in the
development of the classification, but it is one that has been extracted from
Nature grudgingly, and deserves greater attention and consideration within . .
. DSM-5.”
“I
believe you and your colleagues5 are fundamentally
correct,” Coryell replied. But, he added, his belief had “not been shared by
any of the other work group members,” so there was “no point in pursuing it
further.” Coryell ventured a new explanation for the outcome: that the proposal
would “entail a fundamental change in the boundaries” of a diagnosis (MDD) that
was “among the most enduring and stable” of the DSM’s categories. “Evidence for
such a sweeping modification would need to be quite extensive and compelling.”
But an ambiguous research record hadn’t
stopped the work group from gerrymandering the bereavement exclusion out of
MDD, nor was it stopping other work groups from considering destabilizing
changes like the removal of Asperger’s or the introduction of entirely new
diagnoses like DMDD. On the other hand, those diagnoses had one advantage over
melancholia: they didn’t threaten to introduce a biological measure into the
DSM and make the rest of the book look bad in the bargain. Offered a key to one
of the cells of its epistemic prison, the APA had decided that the cost of freedom
was too high.
• • •
In June 2012, the APA posted
a change to the permissions policy on its DSM-5 website. “The APA owns all products6
generated by the Work Groups developing DSM-5,” it declared. This included,
they asserted, not only proposed criteria, but also the discussions that led to
the work groups’ decisions. To those who wondered how this squared with the
insistence that this was the most transparent DSM ever, the APA issued a
reassurance: “Requests will be considered for permission to describe the
criteria and development process in narrative form.” The organization wasn’t
trying to erase history, only to control it.
There was no explanation of this change.
It was hard not to think that it had something to do with my having shown up at
the annual meeting and peppered the presenters with questions, from which the
APA’s communications experts could only conclude that their embargo had not
stopped me from writing my book.
On the other hand, the new policy also
came shortly after Allen Frances put his scathing description of the
development process on the op-ed page of The New York Times.
The APA, he charged, was guilty of “arrogance,
secretiveness7, passive governance and
administrative disorganization.” It had failed to rein in its experts, who had
in turn (and predictably) manufactured new disorders, heedless of the fact that
“new diagnoses in psychiatry can be far more dangerous than new drugs.” And now
he had come to a reluctant conclusion—that the APA “is no longer capable of
being sole fiduciary of a task that has become so consequential to public
health and public policy,” and that it should be stripped of the diagnostic
franchise.
Frances acknowledged that there was no
obvious immediate successor, but he suggested the Department of Health and
Human Services, the Institute of Medicine (a section of the National Academy of
Sciences), or even the World Health Organization. He mentioned one obvious
contender, the National Institute of Mental Health, only to dismiss it as “too
research-oriented and insensitive to the vicissitudes of clinical practice.”
Since sponsoring the planning conferences at the beginning of the DSM-5 effort,
the NIMH had indeed remained on the sidelines—not because nosology was out of
its bailiwick, but because the institute had lost faith in the DSM. “Our resources are more likely8
to be invested in a program to transform diagnosis by 2020,” NIMH director
Thomas Insel told me, “rather than modifying the current paradigm.”
The NIMH is placing its bets for a new
paradigm on a program it calls the Research Domain Criteria (RDoC), a name that
recalls the Research Diagnostic Criteria, the Washington University initiative
that led to the transformation of diagnosis in the DSM-III. Just as Spitzer and
his colleagues had been confronted with widespread dissatisfaction with the
diagnostic system among psychiatrists, so too had Insel heard the discontent among
his peers on his frequent trips to hospitals and universities around the
country.
What
Insel heard “over and over again9” on his tour was
that psychiatrists were tired of being trapped by the DSM. “We are so embedded
in this structure,” he told me. He and his colleagues had spent so much time
diagnosing mental disorders that “we actually believe they are real. But
there’s no reality. These are just constructs. There’s no reality to
schizophrenia or depression.” Indeed, Insel said, “we might have to stop using
terms like depression and schizophrenia,
because they are getting in our way, confusing things.” Thirty years after
Spitzer burned down the DSM-II and built the DSM-III in its ashes, psychiatry
might once again have to “just sort of start over.”
Spitzer’s error, at least according to
Bruce Cuthbert, the NIMH psychologist in charge of RDoC, was not that he tried
to cram psychological suffering into faux medical categories, but that he
continued to think of suffering as a function of the mind. “So many of our disorders10
historically have been conceived of as disorders of mind,” Cuthbert says. This
leaves scientists in an impossible position. “As scientists we have to measure
things,” he says. “What else can we do?”
But the attempt to measure the mind has
led to nothing but dead ends like the old, now discredited theories about
depression and serotonin. “There was going to be a one-to-one map between our
putative mind diseases and biology,” says Cuthbert. “Whoops! It wasn’t that
simple.”
The way to start over, according to
Cuthbert and Insel, is to forget about the mind and look directly to the brain
for understanding our suffering. We shouldn’t take the fact that people have
been describing disorders of the mind such as melancholia for more than two
thousand years or schizophrenia for more than a century as evidence that those
diseases exist and then try to find them in the brain, Cuthbert said. Instead
we should ask, “What does the brain do? What did it evolve to do? And we know
that now.”
What we know now, Cuthbert explained, is
that “there are very specific circuits in the brain that perform somewhat
specific things.” Previous attempts to map the brain onto disorders of the mind
failed not only because they were looking for mind disorders, but also because
they had the brain’s role in psychopathology wrong. The trouble didn’t
originate in individual brain structures like the hippocampus or frontal
cortex. Neither was it in droughts and floods of neurotransmitters. Rather, it
was to be found in circuits of neurons, the pulsating networks that experience
builds in the brain, each their own little ecosystem in the vast
electrochemical jungle between our ears. Understanding circuits, or even
knowing that they existed, wasn’t even possible a generation ago, but now,
thanks to MRI, PET, and other brain-scanning technologies, “we know there are
circuits for fear,” Cuthbert said. “We know there are circuits that guide us to
approach things that are desirable and to go get them, like the food that we
need for nourishment. We know there are circuits for memory. So we know
something about the organization of these circuits now, and we have an idea
that these circuits are involved in lots of different disorders.”
Cuthbert doesn’t expect neural circuits to
map onto the DSM disorders any better than neurotransmitter metabolism has. But
then again, this may not matter. If, for instance, researchers can trace the
neurocircuitry of the startle response, figure out all the electrochemical
events that make an animal blink and hunch and shrink away from a sudden noise,
then they will be on their way to understanding the anxiety found in many DSM
disorders. The arousal itself having been elucidated, it will no longer be
merely a scattered particular waiting to be gathered under the correct
diagnosis. Indeed, fictive placeholders will no longer be necessary. They will
be replaced by the natural formations that the brain scanners have detected as
the sources of this particular kind of suffering.
Cuthbert pointed to a chart titled “Draft
Research Domain Criteria Matrix.” Its rows list the five natural formations the
NIMH is interested in: negative valence systems, including threat, fear of loss,
and frustration; positive valence systems, including motivation, learning, and
habit; cognitive systems (attention, perception, and memory); systems for
social processes (facial expression identification, imitation,
attachment/separation fear); and arousal/regulatory processes (stress
regulation). Its columns are eight units of analysis—such as genes, molecules,
and cells—which the NIMH would like researchers to use to investigate the
domains. So, for instance, a scientist interested in working memory (a
cognitive system) might want to look into the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex,
while a researcher in the negative valence domain could propose a study about
the hypothalamic-pituitary axis or the bed nucleus of the stria terminalis or corticotrophin-releasing
factor. Ultimately, so Cuthbert and Insel hope, the matrix will be
filled in with knowledge about these domains, and the neural substrates of the
distress of people with attachment/separation fear or difficulties in
regulating stress will be elucidated, pinpointed, and presumably targeted for
treatment, without any need for recourse to putative mind diseases.
Cuthbert was not clear about whether it is
the mind that is putative or only its diseases, although the fact that most of
this research is going to take place on animals is a clue to the relative place
of the human mind in this scheme. And, indeed, it is hard to see how the idea
that human consciousness is something more than the sum of its parts—an idea
that, however muted, still lingers in the notion that a state of mind such as
depression can be something real, something that surpasses and unites its
scattered particulars—can survive an effort such as RDoC. Not that the program
signals the death knell of the self (and not that psychiatry, for all its
influence, could slay the idea of human agency that has developed over the last
five thousand years or so), but it does seem to signal the profession’s intent
to complete its abandonment of the mind as the location and source of our
suffering, an effort that began in earnest when Spitzer kicked psychoanalysis
out of the DSM and that might end as it turns to circuits and systems whose
primary virtue is that they can be measured. It seems to signal a future in
which diagnosticians will let the brain talk in its own language of inputs and
outputs, of ganglia and dendrites, of myelin sheaths and afferents; tell its
owner what it is saying; and then provide treatments that are no longer
targeted at mythical chemical imbalances or fictive disorders but at the faulty
circuits that are causing distress.
At the APA meeting in Honolulu, Insel laid
out his vision of that future. He showed an animation illustrating the
differences in brain development between children with ADHD and normal kids,
differences that he said originated very early in life. “We call this attention deficit/hyperactivity
disorder11,” he said, but “think about it for
a moment. Attention, that’s cognition; hyperactivity, that’s behavior; so this
is a cognitive-behavioral disorder. That’s the way we define it, the way we
characterize it, the way we study it, the way we treat it.” He looked over at
the PowerPoint screen, where the two kinds of brains were still projected.
“This to me looks like a disorder of cortical maturation. Imagine if we took
everyone with myocardial infarction and said they had a chest-pain problem.
Yes, these kids do have attention deficit, they do have hyperactivity, that is
part of it, but if you don’t begin to think about ADHD as a disorder of
cortical maturation, you’ll never ask the key questions . . . Maybe we could
use this as the target to develop treatments instead of always thinking about
the observable symptoms.”
The same is true of schizophrenia, Insel
continued, and presumably of other psychiatric disorders. “Behavior is a late
manifestation of brain disorders, so if mental disorders are brain disorders
and we’ve only allowed ourselves to define them based on manifest symptoms and
signs, we’re talking about getting into this game in the ninth inning. And in
medicine we don’t do so well when we get into the game very late.”
Psychiatrists, not to mention their patients, can’t afford to wait until people
actually suffer to intervene—and, if RDoC is successful at laying bare the
neural and genetic substrates of our suffering, they won’t have to. They will
be able to render a diagnosis before there is even trouble, based on what they
can see in the brain.
And since the brain is nothing but
electricity and meat, since, that is, it is real, brain-based diagnosis will
also be real, not reified real but really real, and psychiatric nosology will
finally put paid to the century-old promissory note—not by finally connecting
signs and symptoms to biology and chemistry, but by getting out of the mind
business and placing all the money on the brain. In the system the RDoC
envisions, there will be no more reminders to clinicians not to think of
diagnoses as actual diseases, no more worries that the DSM is taken too
seriously, no more whining about epistemic prisons, no more fights over symptom
counts or disorder names, no more exclusion criteria, no more doomed attempts
to ride the royal road of descriptive psychiatry to the kingdom of anatomical
pathology, no more unworkable definitions of mental illness, and, above all, no
more bullshit.
• • •
On the other hand, maybe not.
In 2020, or whenever RDoC comes to fruition, after the animals have been
startled or frustrated or taught a new maze and had their brains duly mashed
and assayed, after the matrix has been filled in, Insel and Cuthbert or their
successors will still have to name those circuits and then define all those
words. They will have to say exactly what those measurements of neurons in the
stria terminalis or cortisol in the spinal fluid are measuring. And then they
will have to do what Kraepelin and Salmon and Spitzer and Frances and First and
Regier and every other would-be psychiatric nosologist has had to do: figure
out what fear of loss is and where it leaves off and attachment/separation fear sets in, and how much of each is
pathological and when and whether to say that the measured symptoms add up to
an illness. They will once again be faced with the fact that there is very
little that is important about us that can be defined in such a way as to
measure it, and that numbers and words may be incommensurable vocabularies, two
irreconcilable languages in which to understand us.
The mind may well be an illusion,
something the brain does to entertain us while it goes on about its business,
whatever that business is, but it’s a gorgeous illusion and very convincing.
I’ll bet you think you are in there reading this, just as I am sure I am in
here writing it, and when you are doing that, or when you are anxious or
depressed, I’ll bet you are pretty sure it’s because of something other than
some crossed-up brain circuits. The mind is also a resilient illusion. The idea
that we are agents, that our brains serve us just as our other organs do—in
this case providing us with the means to author our lives—and that this is in
some sense what it means to be human, has survived all sorts of assaults, and
it may survive this one as well.
But then again, popes and dictators and
philosopher kings have never had so many drugs at their disposal or a huge
scientific-looking book claiming to list the natural varieties of our
suffering. Nor have they been able to hold out the tantalizing possibility of
elucidating the brain’s role in consciousness, of finding us in its hundred
billion or so neurons, its five hundred trillion synapses, its
ten-to-the-millionth-power possible connections. Neither have they presided
over a populace quite so eager to turn over their (and their children’s)
troubles to their brains and to the doctors who claim to know how to understand
them, or quite so willing to gobble down mind-altering medications whose
mechanisms of action and long-term effects are as unknown as their capacity to
blunt feeling is known. So conditions might be ripe for a
neuroscience-inflected psychiatry to usher in a new understanding of ourselves
as the people of the brain and for us, with the help and encouragement of our
doctors and the drug companies, to become the kind of selves who believe in and
benefit from that understanding, and for whom the RDoC’s matrix is the
troubleshooting manual.
Not that an assault on human agency is
what psychiatrists like Insel are after. Despite the creepy Minority
Report overtones of his idea that we can be mentally ill (and ready for
treatment) before we actually do anything, it’s
impossible to spend an hour or so with him and Cuthbert or, for that matter,
with any of the doctors with whom I have spent so much time over the last
couple of years and think that they are motivated by anything other than a wish
to relieve suffering. Their purpose in cataloging our troubles is surely not to
turn us into Shrink McNuggets. But they are in the grips of forces bigger than
they are, bigger than any of us. It’s not their fault that medicine is a
service industry, that diseases are market opportunities, and that a book of
them is worth its weight in gold.
• • •
After my visit with Frances
in Boston, I e-mailed to ask him to name a diagnostic category that in his view
made the strongest case for psychiatric diagnosis.
“Why do
you hate psychiatrists12 so much? Is it because I pinched
your cheek?” he wrote back.
I persisted. I wanted to hear about a slam
dunk, the psychiatric equivalent of strep or diabetes, a single diagnosis that
indicated a single pathology and a single treatment. But I would have settled
for less, just one solid example of the value of a diagnostic system.
“Really silly questions,” he replied.
“Your bias is showing.”
Frances did offer a defense. Not for the
first time, he told me that “psychiatry done badly can be very harmful,
psychiatry done well within its proper competence can be noble. The trick is to
develop a healing relationship, to care for the person not just the disorder,
to diagnose and treat cautiously, and to see the healthy part of the person not
just the sick.” All of which is inarguable, if a little hazy, but it doesn’t
really answer the question of why pulling off that trick requires a
thousand-page catalog of disorders that are not real—other than to inspire
confidence among bureaucrats, and among people who are comforted when a doctor
names their suffering. Nor does it explain how exactly that book can keep
psychiatry within its “proper competence.” Neither does it acknowledge Freud’s
warning that medical education is the worst possible training for people who
take on the troubles of the psyche, a warning issued long before the
medical-industrial complex turned suffering into a commodity and psychiatry
into a profession in which clinician communication must be efficient and the
“healing relationship” must be established in ten-minute medication management
visits.
“It isn’t bias to be skeptical,” I wrote.
“And it’s not antipsychiatry to question psychiatry. And it’s not silly, in the
context of a book about diagnosis, to ask how nosology relates to the practice
of psychiatry.” I gave Frances a hypothetical case, a psychotic person he has
diagnosed with Bipolar Disorder. “How does that diagnosis help him to proceed?”
I asked. It was the question former APA president Paul Fink once answered by
saying, “I got paid.”
“Like to help,” Frances answered. “But the
question makes no sense to me. Suggest you read a textbook of psychiatry.”
At $80.99, Kaplan &
Sadock’s Concise Textbook of Clinical Psychiatry seems like a real
bargain, compared with the $410.99 Kaplan & Sadock’s
Comprehensive Textbook of Psychiatry. At 700 pages, it
isn’t exactly concise, but it is a lot shorter than the 4,884-page full-size
version, not to mention 200 pages shorter than the DSM-IV. So maybe Benjamin
and Virginia Sadock, authors of the Concise Textbook,
are just trying to save space, but when they tell students that “DSM-IV-TR attempts to describe13
the manifestations of the mental disorders,” they don’t mention that there’s no
reality to those mental disorders or warn students of the dangers of
reification.
They do, however, tell the young doctors
that it is a “major challenge” to separate the bipolars from the depressives,
and they discuss the “difficulty of
distinguishing a manic episode14 from
schizophrenia.” They explain that “depressive
symptoms are present15 in almost all psychiatric
disorders,” that “every sign or symptom seen
in schizophrenia16 occurs in other psychiatric and
neurological disorders,” and that “the distinction between generalized anxiety
disorder and normal anxiety is emphasized by the use of the words ‘excessive’
and ‘difficult to control.’” But, the book reassures the students, these
difficulties can be overcome through careful clinical observation. Even if the
categories don’t exist, in other words, people can nonetheless be sorted into them.
“Once a
diagnosis has been established17,” Sadock and
Sadock write, “a pharmacological treatment strategy can be formulated.” That
may involve psychosocial treatment, but as just about any psychiatrist will tell
you, the days in which psychiatrists underwent psychoanalysis as part of their
training are long gone, as are the days in which psychiatrists routinely
practiced talk therapy, so that treatment is most likely not going to be
provided by them. When it comes to the technique that remains their sole
bailiwick—pharmacotherapy—“no one drug is
predictably effective18.” For bipolar patients, the doctor
has at her disposal lithium, anticonvulsants such as Depakote, tranquilizers
such as Ativan, and antipsychotics such as Haldol and Zyprexa. “Often,” advise Sadock and Sadock, “it is
necessary19 to try several so-called ‘mood
stabilizers’ before an optimal treatment is found.”
Even when the diagnosis is established,
the treatment is still uncertain. And there is a good reason for this.
According to Sadock and Sadock, “the
objective of pharmacologic treatment20 is symptom
remission.” Bipolar isn’t the only case. There is no specific treatment for any
of the disorders Sadock and Sadock present, and many drugs are used for many
conditions: antidepressants to treat obsessions, antipsychotics to treat
depression, mood stabilizers to treat anxiety, and so on. Psychiatrists, in
other words, are not treating the disorders they diagnose. The categories,
after all, aren’t natural formations; symptoms, the scattered particulars, are
all they have to go on and all they can treat.
Which doesn’t mean they shouldn’t treat
them. “Not everyone needs to see21
a psychiatrist for the treatment of a mental disorder,” Frances told me. “But
if the problem is moderate to severe, persistent, and impairing, medication is
likely to be needed. In my view, this should mostly be provided by
psychiatrists, not primary care doctors who are usually out of their depth.” He
is surely right about this. Psychiatrists do indeed have a wealth of experience
in treating people’s distress with drugs. No clinician can deny the value of
that knowledge, the way that people in the throes of a manic episode or a
psychotic break or a disabling depression can be helped by drug therapy. Nor
can anyone deny that this uncertainty about diagnosis and treatment is exactly
what makes the expertise of the psychiatrist essential.
But you don’t have to hate psychiatrists
to point out that their expertise is mostly empirical and their treatments
potentiated at least as much by hope as by chemistry. Or, to put it another
way, that psychiatry, much more than other medical specialties, is still deeply
in the debt of ancient medicine. The Platonic ideal of a world of suffering
carved up into its natural formations remains exactly that—an ideal, one that
psychiatric nosology can’t yet approach. And you also don’t have to hate
psychiatrists to think that this gap, the distance between what the profession
claims and what it actually knows, between its opportunity and its knowledge,
is vast, and that even as the jury remains out on the legitimacy of
psychiatry’s claim to understand mental suffering, more and more people are
taking daily doses of drugs whose mechanisms are poorly understood and whose
long-term consequences, on the body and on the body politic, are uncertain. You
don’t have to hate psychiatrists to think that the ever-expanding DSM is not a
book that can help psychiatrists stay within their competence, that indeed it
encourages them to do the opposite. You don’t have to hate psychiatrists to think
that a book that dresses up symptoms as diseases that are not real and then
claims to have named and described the true varieties of our suffering is all
clothes and no emperor. And you don’t have to hate psychiatrists to think
we—patients, doctors, therapists, all of us—might be better off without it.
• • •
Or maybe the APA was trying to erase history. In early November 2012, the
draft of the DSM-5 disappeared from the DSM-5 website, removed, according to a
note on the home page, “to avoid confusion or use of outdated categories and
definitions.” It wasn’t enough to threaten legal action against people who
might want to use the draft criteria as part of a research project or, I don’t
know, a book about the development of the DSM-5. It is, of course, possible
that the APA really feared that a paper using outdated criteria would slip by a
peer reviewer or that a doctor would render a diagnosis based on discarded
definitions. But it is also possible that the APA hit the delete button for the
same reason Soviet apparatchiks airbrushed old photos: to prevent
embarrassment.
The move was so arrogant, and so
unnecessary, and so heedless of the public trust the APA holds—in short, it was
so incompetent that it made me wonder if Frances had been right all along: that
the trouble with the DSM-5 was purely bureaucratic, that if it turns into the
disaster he has predicted, it will not be because the APA has found itself
perfectly situated to exploit the capitalist imperative to turn all need into
markets and thus to manufacture need by the carload. Neither will it be because
a diagnostic empire built on air must at some point come crashing down, as if
some tragic principle were at work, ensuring that hubris inevitably meets
justice. Nor will it be because the attempt to catalog our suffering is doomed
to be a fool’s errand, that our troubles will always outdistance our attempts
to take their measure. It will be because the Keystone Kops bungled the job.
Only naiveté or animus toward psychiatry or a writer’s fervent wish for drama
could make someone read more into the unfolding events than incompetence, to
see the DSM-5 as anything other than one more step in the long, random walk of
human folly.
But there is a reason insiders trot out
the one-bad-apple defense when disasters occur. It distracts from the more
disturbing truth—in this case, that a profession that has been struggling to
establish its credentials for more than a century, that has lurched from crisis
to crisis, always for the same reason, always because it cannot make good on
its claim to be treating diseases as other doctors do—that such a profession
has something rotten at its foundation: its have-it-both-ways,
real-until-it-isn’t diagnostic manual.
You don’t have to be a hater to think that
the DSM, no matter how often it is revised or how competently, will never
manage to pour the old wine of human suffering into the new skin of scientific
medicine. And you don’t have to resort to biblical analogies to show that the
Bible of psychiatry is failing to do what it is presumably intended to do, and
what would bolster the argument for bringing our mental suffering under the
medical gaze: to improve psychiatric treatment. You don’t even have to be an
upside-down Jesuit or a Leibowitz unwittingly sowing the seeds of destruction.
You could be Tom Insel, who is neither an antipsychiatrist nor a Jesuit of any
spatial orientation, who is, in fact, America’s psychiatrist in chief.
“Whatever
we’ve been doing for five decades22,” he told me,
“it ain’t working. And when I look at the numbers—the number of suicides,
number of disabilities, mortality data—it’s abysmal, and it’s not getting any
better. All of the ways in which we’ve approached these illnesses, and with a
lot of people working very hard, the outcomes we’ve got to point to are pretty
bleak”—especially, he added, compared with the “extraordinary” progress in
other fields, such as the 70 percent drop in mortality from cardiovascular
disease since he went to medical school or the steep reductions in deaths from
auto accidents and homicides. “There are some people for whom some of what we
do is enormously helpful,” he said. But even so, “we don’t know which
treatments are working for which people.” And this litany of failure, he said,
“gets us back to your interest in nosology. Maybe we just need to rethink this
whole approach.”
That’s what Pliny Earle said in 1886, and
what Thomas Salmon said in 1917, and George Raines in 1951, and Robert Spitzer
in 1978, and Steve Hyman in 2000: that without a working nosology, psychiatry
is a failure, that the current nosology (whatever it is) is sadly lacking, that
the profession needs a new paradigm. You don’t have to be an antipsychiatrist
to wonder if incompetence can possibly explain all that futility, or if a
profession that, despite its repeated failures, continues to “cherish
expectations with regard to some mode of infallibly discovering the heart of
man,” as Melville once put it, deserves our confidence. You only have to know
what Tom Insel knows and is honest enough to say out loud.
Insel may be right that a deeper foray
into the thickets of the brain will yield what psychiatry has long sought: a
taxonomy of disorders validated by biochemical findings. And Frances may also
be correct that in the meantime mythical disorders are better than no disorders
at all, that without them patients won’t listen to their doctors or get the
benefits of having a name for their pain. But no one knows what would happen if
psychiatrists simply let themselves out of their epistemic prison by no longer
pretending to know what they can’t know. No one knows what would happen if they
simply told you that they don’t know what illness (if any) is causing your
anxiety or depression or agitation, and then, if they thought it was warranted,
told you there are drugs that might help (although they don’t really know why
or at what cost to the brain, or whether you will be able to stop taking them
if you want to; nor can they guarantee that you—or your child—won’t become
obese or diabetic or die early), and offer you a prescription.
There are undoubtedly patients who would
balk. Depressed people might be less willing to surrender their orgasms to
Prozac if they don’t think they are correcting a biochemical imbalance called
Major Depressive Disorder. Psychotic patients might object to a lifetime of
taking drugs that blunt their emotions, cloud their cognition, make them gain
weight, and shorten their life span if they don’t think they are being treated
for Schizophrenia. Parents might hesitate to ply their kids with stimulants and
antipsychotics if they believe that they are merely calming them down rather
than treating their ADHD or BD (or, once the DSM-5 goes into effect, their
DMDD). After all, this is a country whose pharmacological Calvinism has led to
a four-decade-long war on drugs used merely to change the way we feel, and that
harbors disdain—especially when it comes to our mental lives—for treating
symptoms rather than underlying causes.
But other people would surely be willing
to take the gamble. Indeed, they already are. Seventy-two
percent23 of the prescriptions for
antidepressants in the United States are written for patients who are not given
a psychiatric diagnosis of any kind, who suffer from troubles ranging from
tiredness and headaches to “abnormal
sensations” and “nonspecific pain24.” It’s
impossible to know exactly how the prescribing doctors sold their patients on
the idea of using the drugs, and while it’s likely that at least some doctors
told patients they had depression but then didn’t write that down in the chart,
it’s also easy to imagine a conversation in which the doctor confesses her
uncertainty about diagnosis, but suggests that other patients with similar
symptoms have benefited from the drug and encourages the patient to give it a
try.
Of course, this is exactly the kind of
problem that Frances thinks arises when nonpsychiatric physicians (family
doctors and other primary care providers account for 80 percent of those
prescriptions) go beyond their proper competence. He may be right about this,
but that doesn’t necessarily mean specialists are more restrained in their
prescribing habits, nor is whatever advantage they might have over their
nonpsychiatrist colleagues the result of being better at figuring out which of
the nonreal mental disorders listed in the DSM their patients have. Rather, it
is more likely to come from their greater experience in treating symptoms, in
making the artful judgment of which potion is likely to help which patient. If
this—the ability to match symptom with drug—were the only claim that psychiatry
made, if psychiatrists stopped pretending that they know the proper names for our
suffering, then perhaps the profession could finally free itself from the
prison it has built.
Of course, a psychiatry that gave up a
common scientific language, and the perquisites it garners, might also not have
a DSM, or at least not one that looks anything like the DSM we have now. But by
no longer insisting that it is just like the rest of medicine, and by
renouncing its noble lies about the scientific status of psychiatric diagnosis,
the profession might become a more honest one than it is now. Given that
psychiatrists demand honesty from their patients, honesty is perhaps the least
we should ask of them. It might even build our confidence. (And theirs: with
less to defend itself about, psychiatry, or at least the APA, might have less
need for secrecy and paranoia, and less need to diagnose all its opponents with
Antipsychiatry Disorder.)
But there is no doubt that an honest
psychiatry would be a smaller profession. It would have fewer patients, more
modest claims about what it treats, less clout with insurers, and reduced
authority to turn our troubles into medical problems simply by adding the word disorder to their description. It would, in other words, be
more likely to stay within its proper competence. Its restraint would depend
not on the modesty of aristocrats, who have proven themselves to be unreliable
in that respect, and not on government regulation, which, even if it were
possible, has recently fallen into disrepute, and not on the discovery of the
boundary between mental health and mental illness, which will always prove
elusive, but on that much more modern and effective arbiter, the one master to
whom we all seem to submit: the marketplace.
• • •
Speaking of marketplaces, an
honest psychiatry would not be such a good thing for my profession, at least
not if it meant the end of the DSM as we know it. We talk therapists have
arguably been the book’s prime beneficiaries. While psychiatrists are treating
the floridly psychotic, the raving manic, the suicidal and the catatonic and
the delirious, we, by and large, get to minister to the walking wounded. Thanks
to Bob Spitzer’s expansive approach to the DSM, we can casually jot down
“Generalized Anxiety Disorder” or “Adjustment Disorder” and talk (on the
insurance tab) with our patients about the meaning of life, while right down
the hall psychiatrists are making momentous decisions about whether a man who
thinks his bones have been sucked out of him is bipolar or schizophrenic and
which drugs to prescribe. While they have to take the DSM at least a little
seriously, we can pretend it doesn’t exist, give it the cynical bureaucrat’s
shrug, denounce it even as we cash those insurance company checks. And when it
comes time to revise it or explain it or defend it, and its flaws are once
again open to scrutiny, it’s the psychiatrists who take the heat.
Not that I feel particularly sorry for
them, but it is clear that for us nonpsychiatrist clinicians, the stakes are
purely monetary. Without those codes and the access they give us to insurance
companies’ compensation schemes, the unfettered marketplace will decide how
much we are worth. Weekly visits with me right now cost the equivalent of a
monthly payment on a car. I try to adjust my charges according to what a person
can afford to drive. But while for some people that’s a BMW, for others it
isn’t even a badly used Kia, and I have no doubt that shorn of their
DSM-enabled insurance subsidy, fewer people could pay me anything at all. So I
would make less money. In this, I am like workers everywhere in America,
although at least for now my job can’t be offshored.
• • •
An honest psychiatry might
also lead the way to a new understanding of illness. The idea that disease is
suffering caused by an identifiable pathogen that can be targeted and killed by
medicine’s magic bullets is a historical accident, one that originated at the
height of the Industrial Revolution and that springs as much from commerce as
from science. It has been an extraordinarily beneficial idea, but like all
inventions, it has its drawbacks—notably that it has encouraged us to think
that all our troubles will ultimately yield to the microscope and the pill.
“The
future belongs to illness25,” Peter Sedgwick wrote in the
early 1970s. “We are just going to get more and more diseases, since our
expectations of health are going to become more sophisticated and expansive.”
Thanks to a DSM that has kept pace with those expectations, that future is
here. It has arrived in a capitalist age, which means that we have placed our
well-being in the not-so-invisible hands of a medical-industrial complex whose
proprietors have a stake in reducing suffering to biochemistry. It has spawned
a psychiatry that can’t help giving us more and more diseases, at least not if it
wants to meet the economic, if not the scientific, demands of the day.
Still, the problem with psychiatry may not
be that it lags behind the other medical specialties, with their magic bullets
and the science by which they identify the targets. Rather, it may be a
harbinger of a time when the low-hanging fruit has been picked, when the
inadequacies of modern medicine to the complexity of our suffering—physical and
mental alike—have become manifest, and when the folly of encouraging us to give
up the ghost for the machine is unmistakable.
Because there is one definition of mental
disorder that is not bullshit. Mental disorder, like all disease, is suffering
that a society devotes resources to relieving. The line between sickness and
health, mental and physical, is not biological but social and economic. It is
the line between the distress for which we will provide sympathy and money and
access to treatment, and the distress for which we will not. For the past 150
years, we have relied on doctors to decide who gets those resources, and they
in turn have furnished us with diseases that, they assure us, are not figments
of their imaginations, but real entities that reside in tissues and cells and
molecules, that can be observed and measured, and, if all goes well, treated.
Psychiatry has tried its best to stake its claim to this bonanza, perhaps
nowhere so ardently as in its attempt to fashion its book of woe, but it has
not worked. This may be because the psychiatrists in question, or their
technologies, have not been up to the job. It may be because that line can’t be
drawn without deciding how a human life is supposed to go, how it ought to
feel, and what it is for—questions for which science, no matter how robust, is
no match. It may be because the arc of history bends toward justice, and
biochemistry may not be the fairest basis on which to determine whose suffering
deserves recognition. But it may also be because the human mind, even in its
troubles, perhaps especially in them, has so far resisted this attempt to turn
its discontents into a catalog of suffering. And for this we should be glad.
Afterword
The careful reader will by
now have detected the odor of a certain barnyard effluent suffusing this book.
My opportunity to publish at the same time as the DSM-5 exceeds my knowledge of
what is actually in the new manual. Indeed, it is very likely that you know
more about its specifics as you read this than I do as I write in early January
2013. But I do know a little about the final product.
For this, I can thank the APA. Not that
they decided to talk directly to me, but they did use the trustees’
rubber-stamping of the final draft at the beginning of December 2012 as an occasion to release some details1—among
them, the price of the new book, $199. As expected, Hoarding Disorder and
Disruptive Mood Dysregulation Disorder were in, Asperger’s was out, and
Attenuated Psychosis Symptoms Syndrome was in the Appendix, now officially
renamed Section 3, where it would be joined by all the dimensional measures and
the “trait-specific methodology” proposal for personality disorders. (Those
diagnoses would revert largely to their DSM-IV versions.) Section 3 would also
include “the names of individuals involved in DSM-5’s
development.” I’m looking forward to finding out if my name is among them.
The summary left unanswered some important
questions. For instance, while it said that Asperger’s would be “integrated”
into the autistic spectrum, it did not spell out exactly how, or whether the
APA would retain ownership of the name or relinquish it to all those Aspies in
search of an identity. Neither did it illuminate a persistent rumor: that
currently diagnosed Asperger’s patients would be “grandfathered,” keeping the
diagnosis even if the disorder was eliminated. It mentioned that the
bereavement exclusion had been replaced by “several notes within the text
delineating the differences between grief and depression,” but did not
elaborate except to say that the change “reflects the recognition that
bereavement is a severe psychosocial stressor that can precipitate a major
depressive episode beginning soon after the loss of a loved one.” What a
clinician, astute or otherwise, was supposed to do with that recognition was
not made clear.
The press release did offer some
reassurances to a skeptical public. “We have sought to be very conservative in
our approach to revising DSM-5,” David Kupfer said. “Our work has been aimed at
more accurately defining mental disorders that have a real impact on people’s
lives, not expanding the scope of psychiatry.” And Jay Scully reminded
reporters that the process had been “as open and independent as possible. The
level of transparency we have strived for is not seen in any other area of
medicine.” An e-mail sent by Kupfer and Regier to task force and work group
members in advance of the press release elaborated on just how open and
independent that was. “We do ask that you
focus2 your interviews on the disorder and
refrain from talking about the criteria or text,” it read. They apparently
didn’t want anyone to spoil the surprise.
The trustees’ vote triggered a spate of
news coverage, some of it summarizing the APA’s summary, some of it opining for
or against, and at least one article—in The Washington Post3—repeating charges
of corruption in the process, this time by reporting on the study that Sid
Zisook, architect of the bereavement policy, once ran proving that Wellbutrin
was effective in the bereaved. The APA responded with a press release under
David Kupfer’s byline, reiterating all that the task force had done to
eliminate conflicts of interest and assuring the public that “DSM-5 includes material4
to make sure that it is understood that sadness, grief, and bereavement are not
things that have a time limitation to them or go away within two or three
months.” What it meant that psychiatrists had to be told this, or what they
would do now that they had been informed, Kupfer did not say.
Two weeks after the vote, psychiatric
diagnosis was back on the front pages, this time when a young man armed with a
semiautomatic weapon slaughtered twenty children at an elementary school in
Connecticut. Dilip Jeste, the APA president,
told Congress5 that the tragedy, which occurred
“at the very time [that] federal and state funding for critical mental health
services is under siege,” was a reminder that, because mentally ill people in
treatment are “considerably less likely to commit violent acts” than those who
are untreated, Congress should “act to protect federal funding for mental
health . . . research and services.” Three days later, however, after the
National Rifle Association’s Wayne LaPierre told the nation that no matter how
many rounds they can fire in an instant, guns don’t kill people, “lunatics”
kill people, and suggested that the solution to the problem was a registry of
mentally ill people whose diagnoses would presumably lose them their Second
Amendment rights, Jeste took a different approach. Not only was LaPierre’s language “offensive6,”
he said in a news release, but “only four to five percent of violent crimes are
committed by people with mental illness,” and that “only a small percentage” of
the 25 percent of Americans who will come down with a mental disorder in any
given year “will ever commit violent crimes.” Gun violence, in other words, was
not an indication of mental illness unless there was money to be made.
Al Frances responded to the trustees’ vote
with what he promised would be his last blog on the subject. “The saddest day7
in my 45-year career,” he wrote, and urged clinicians to “ignore its ten worst
changes,” which he enumerated. “Apparently they deleted a few irrelevant things
and approved all the junk that was left,” he e-mailed.
Ten days later, Frances broke his promise,
telling readers that the APA had “one last
act8 to save DSM 5 before the curtain drops,” and warning
that unless the organization used the remaining time to fix the outstanding
problems (and add a black-box warning about the dangers of overdiagnosis), the
new manual would be “a financial as well as a clinical, scientific, and
artistic flop.” He repeated this warning in a series of e-mails to the APA’s
leaders, in which he promised to shut up if they heeded his advice. They did
not take him up on his offer.
The APA wasn’t the only organization
ignoring Frances. In the wake of the trustees’ approval, many proposals to
boycott the DSM-5 sprang up—a dozen, by his account. He urged comity. “Any new boycott must unify the diverse
opposition9,” he wrote, “not further fragment
what is already a very fragmented field.” But the groups did not coalesce into
a single movement, nor did the antipsychiatrists among the dissidents heed his
call to stop using his name (“without permission,” he pointed out) to support
their cause. Frances was left to explain once again that his attack on his
profession’s foundational text was not an attack on the profession itself.
For his part, Michael First was back on
the inside. In late November, I asked him about a rumor I’d been hearing all
fall: that the APA had called him to duty to help finalize the manual. “I can confirm10 it’s true,” he
e-mailed, “but I really cannot say anything else. Sorry.” He wasn’t going to
jeopardize his ability to do once again what he’d been born to do. An insider,
who also wouldn’t go on the record, made it clear that his role was limited:
reviewing criteria for consistency, editing them for clarity, and making sure
the book could be used by clinicians.
First was willing to give me his overall
appraisal of the outcome. “The good news11
about the DSM-5 is also the bad news,” he e-mailed. “While many little things
have changed for the better, and clinicians will find the transition relatively
easy to make, the fundamental problems with the descriptive approach remain.”
It still explains little, offers scant treatment guidelines, and “relies on
categories that facilitate clinician communication but have no firm basis in
reality. So I think it’s an improvement,” he concluded, “but it’s also an
acknowledgment that psychiatry, especially in its understanding of mental
illness, is still in its infancy.” Whether the profession can grow up remains
to be seen.
At Wired,
where this book got its start (and its title): Bill Wasik and Bess Kalb.
At Blue Rider Press: Aileen Boyle, Anna
Jardine, Phoebe Pickering, David Rosenthal, and the inestimable Sarah Hochman.
For crack agentry: Jim Rutman.
For reading and comment on parts of the
manuscript: Barney Carroll, Bill Musgrave, and Stuart Vyse.
For reading and comment on the entire
manuscript: Rand Cooper, Gideon Lewis-Kraus, and Michelle Orange.
For interviews that no doubt turned out to
be more than they bargained for, not to mention all those follow-up e-mails:
Bill Bernet, Michael Carley, Gabrielle Carlson, Will Carpenter, Jane Costello,
Bruce Cuthbert, Max Fink, Paul Fink, Steve Hyman, Tom Insel, Nomi Kaim, Ronald
Kessler, David Kupfer, John Livesley, Catherine Lord, Steve Mirin, Bill Narrow,
Roger Peele, Harold Pincus, Darrel Regier, Jay Scully, David Shaffer, Andrew
Skodol, Bob Spitzer, Fred Volkmar, Jerry Wakefield, Barbara Wiechmann, Tom
Widiger, and Sid Zisook.
For research materials and editorial
assistance: Paula Caplan, Beth Card, Bart Laws, Ned Shorter, Steve Silberman,
Katherine Sticklor, and Ken Kendler.
For careful proofreading: Ruth Greenberg.
For honesty, patience, and generosity:
Michael First.
For honesty, patience, generosity, and
hospitality, sometimes against their better judgment: Allen Frances and Donna
“Peach” Manning.
And, as always, for bringing out my best
and putting up with my worst, and for her blue eyes: Susan Marie Powers.
Chapter 1
1. “In
noticing a disease”: Cartwright, “Diseases and Peculiarities of the
Negro Race,” Part 1, 332.
2. “the disease causing
Negroes”: Ibid., 331.
3. Two classes of persons: Ibid., 332.
4. “whipping the devil”: Ibid.
5. “submissive knee-bender”: Ibid.
6. “northern
hornbooks in Medicine”: Cartwright, “Diseases and Peculiarities of
the Negro Race,” Part 2, 506.
7. “demonstrated, by dissection”: Ibid., 505.
8. “the membranes, tendons,
and aponeuroses”: Ibid., 506.
9. dyaesthesia
aethiopica: Cartwright, “Diseases and Peculiarities,” Part 1, 333.
10. “the learned Dr.
Cartwright”: Olmsted, Journeys and
Explorations, 122.
11. “the
nervous erythism”: S. B. Hunt, “Dr. Cartwright on ‘Drapetomania,’”
441–42.
12. They
underwent countless therapies: For an account of the treatment of
homosexuals, see LeVay, Queer Science, chapter 4.
13. 11
percent of the U.S. adult population: Centers for Disease Control,
“NCHS Data Brief, October 19, 2011,”
http://www.cdc.gov/nchs/data/databriefs/db76.htm.
14. you
got tired of feeling numb: For side effects of antidepressants, see
Glenmullen, Prozac Backlash.
15. placebo effect: Kirsch, The Emperor’s New Drugs.
16. this chemical imbalance
does not, as far as doctors know: Greenberg, Manufacturing Depression.
17. more
than seventy combinations of symptoms: See DSM-IV-TR, 356. There are
nine symptoms of depression, but patients need have only five in any
combination to earn the diagnosis.
18. “another
[of] the ten thousand”: Cartwright, “Diseases and Peculiarities,”
Part 1, 336.
19. “Love is a madness”: Plato, Phaedrus, 265e.
20. Before
John Snow: The best account of this famous story is probably Steven
Johnson’s The Ghost Map.
21. Louis Pasteur and Robert
Koch:
Ullmann, “Pasteur–Koch.”
22. “blessed
rage to order”: Stevens, “The Idea of Order at Key West,” The Palm at the End of the Mind.
23. Adam
and Eve: Genesis 2:19–21.
24. “loose, baggy monster”: Henry James, The Tragic Muse, 4.
25. “insomnia, flushing,
drowsiness”: Beard, American
Nervousness, 7–8.
26. “As long as I live”: Gay, Freud, 491.
27. “It burdens [a doctor]”: Freud, The Question of Lay Analysis, 95.
28. “the mental sciences”: Ibid., 88–90.
29. “the
patient’s ambivalent feeling”: American Psychiatric Association,
DSM-I, 34.
30. a
psychologist showed: Ash, “The Reliability of Psychiatric
Diagnoses.”
31. By
1962, despite various attempts: Summarized in Beck, “Reliability of
Psychiatric Diagnoses.”
32. doctors
in Great Britain: Sandifer et al., “Psychiatric Diagnosis.” See also
Kendell et al., “Diagnostic Criteria of American and British Psychiatrists.”
33. Erving Goffman and
Michel Foucault: See Goffman, Asylums, and Foucault, Madness
and Civilization.
34. The
DSM instructs users: American Psychiatric Association, DSM-IV-TR,
xxxi–xxxii.
35. “perhaps
the most powerful psychiatrist in America”: Daniel Goleman,
“Scientist at Work,” The New York Times, April 19,
1994.
36. “Here’s
the problem”: Allen Frances interview, August 16, 2010.
37. the
lead of the Wired article: Gary
Greenberg, “The Book of Woe: Inside the Battle to Define Mental Illness,” Wired, December 2010, 126–36.
38. “Bullshit is
unavoidable”: Frankfurt, On Bullshit, 63.
39. “neither on the side of
the true”: Ibid., 56.
Chapter 2
1. “The
present classification of mental diseases is chaotic”: Salmon et
al., “Report of the Committee on Statistics,” 256.
2. “It cannot be supposed”: Jarvis, Relation of Education to Insanity, 4–5.
3. “Within the last fifty
years”: Ibid., 6.
4. “In an uneducated
community”: Ibid., 8.
5. “From all this survey”: Ibid., 11.
6. “In
the present state of our knowledge”: Grob, “Origins of DSM-I,” 231.
Emphasis in original.
7. “had become marginal”: Shorter, History of Psychiatry, 144.
8. “Pathological anatomy”: Kraepelin, Lectures, 27.
9. “poetic
interpretation”: Kraepelin, “Manifestations of Insanity,” 512.
10. he
took a Kraepelinian approach: Salmon, “Report of the Committee on
Statistics,” 256–59.
11. the
association issued the Statistical Manual: Grob, “Origins of DSM-I,” 426.
12. its last edition ran to
seventy-one pages: American Psychiatric Association, Statistical Manual for the Use of Hospitals.
13. a membership of only
2,295 doctors: Grob, “Origins of DSM-I,” 427.
14. “Our
experiences with therapy”: Quoted in Grob, “Origins of
DSM-I,” 428.
15. Psychoanalysis
proved easy enough to adapt: For a detailed account of this shift,
see Zaretsky, Secrets of the Soul, especially chapters
10 and 11.
16. only
10 percent of their cases: American Psychiatric Association, DSM-I, vi.
17. “At least three
nomenclatures”: Ibid., vii.
18. “stepchild of [the]
Federal Government”: DSM-I, x.
19. Anxiety Reaction: DSM-I, 32.
20. Depressive Reaction: DSM-I, 33.
21. “disorders of
psychogenic origin”: DSM-I, 24.
22. “Instead of putting so
much emphasis”: Menninger, The Vital Balance, 325.
23. “Man
in transaction with his universe”: Quoted in Wilson, “DSM-III and
the Transformation of American Psychiatry,” 401.
24. it had become a
professional backwater: Wilson, “DSM-III,” 403.
25. “compared to other types
of services”: Quoted ibid.
26. The war over the
homosexuality diagnosis: For a full account, see Bayer, Homosexuality and American Psychiatry.
27. Ego-Dystonic
Homosexuality: DSM-III, 281–82.
28. “If groups of people march”: Bayer, Homosexuality and American Psychiatry, 141.
29. “Referenda on matters of
science”: Ibid., 153.
30. “Psychiatry
was regarded as bogus”: Robert Spitzer interview, August 27, 2010.
31. “I
was uncomfortable with not knowing”: Spiegel, “The Dictionary of
Disorder.”
32. By
1972, the group had described: Feighner et al., “Diagnostic Criteria
for Use in Psychiatric Research.”
33. Research
Diagnostic Criteria: Spitzer et al., “Research Diagnostic Criteria:
Rationale and Reliability.”
34. A. One or more distinct
periods: Ibid., 776.
35. the nosology would
inexorably gain substance: Ibid., 781–82.
36. “The use of operational
criteria”: Ibid., 781.
37. a
conclusion he published in the Archives of Sexual Behavior:
Spitzer, “Can Some Gay Men and Lesbians Change Their Sexual Orientation?”
38. a
letter to the Archives: Spitzer, “Spitzer
Reassesses His 2003 Study of Reparative Therapy.”
Chapter 3
1. “In
the morning, everyone would be screaming ideas”: Allen Frances
telephone interview, November 23, 2011.
2. people
who “employ self-sacrificing and self-defeating behavior”: Siever
and Klar, “A Review of DSM-III Criteria for the Personality Disorders,” 304.
3. “dumb
idea”: Allen Frances e-mail, November 27, 2011.
4. “The fact that we had a
descriptive system only revealed”: Allen Frances interview, August 16, 2010.
5. “loving
the pet, even if it is a mutt”: Allen Frances e-mail, September 3,
2010.
6. “seemed
a bit like stamp collecting”: Hyman, “The Diagnosis of Mental
Disorders: The Problem of Reification,” 157.
7. “The
tendency [is] always strong”: James Mill, Analysis
of the Phenomena of the Human Mind, 5. The quotation is from a footnote
appended to a later edition of Mill’s 1829 book by his son John Stuart Mill.
8. “It became a source of
real worry”: Ibid.
9. “I
realized that it got me nowhere”: Steven Hyman e-mail, October 5,
2012.
10. the Post had twice come out against
parity: “The Mental Health Amendment,” The
Washington Post, April 28, 1996; and “‘Parity’ in Health Insurance,” The Washington Post, December 4, 2001.
11. They
“asked questions”: “Changes Put APA on Right Track to Face Future,” Psychiatric News, October 4, 2002.
12. They’d
asked twenty thousand people: The questionnaire is available in
Robins and Regier, Psychiatric Disorders in America,
401–26.
13. The ECA’s findings: Ibid., 333.
14. And the sick among us
were really sick: Ibid., 357.
15. only 19 percent: Ibid., 361.
16. the
paper came out in favor of parity: “Equity for Mental Illness,” The Washington Post, September 9, 2002.
17. the Midtown Manhattan Study: Srole et al., Mental Health in the Metropolis, vol. 1.
18. “designed for
classifying full-blown pathology”: Ibid., 134.
19. So rather than ask .
. . they asked about: Ibid., 388–91.
20. a six-point
classification: Ibid., 134–38.
21. “mental illness and
mental health [differed]”: Ibid., 135.
22. the actual number is
81.5 percent: Ibid., 138.
23. It was more than double
the rate of mental illness: Ibid., 141–43.
24. he
cited the 23 percent figure accurately: Regier et al., “The De Facto
U.S. Mental Health Services System,” 687.
25. about 15 percent of
Americans were mentally ill: Ibid., 692–93.
Chapter 4
1. “the
mind is a set of operations”: Kandel, “The New Science of Mind,” 69.
2. “all mental disorders”: Ibid., 71.
3. “We
can think of mental disorders”: Insel, “Rethinking Mental
Illness,” 2011 American Psychiatric Association annual meeting, Honolulu, May
14, 2011.
4. “neurologizing
tautologies”: Meyer, “The Aims and Meaning of Psychiatric
Diagnosis,” 165.
5. “driving
the Devil out”: Shorter and Healy, Shock Therapy,
30.
6. it
was hard to argue with the biological psychiatrists: For a history
of these discoveries, see Greenberg, Manufacturing Depression,
chapters 7, 8; Healy, The Creation of Psychopharmacology,
and Shorter, History of Psychiatry.
7. depression,
he announced, must be the result: Schildkraut, “The Catecholamine
Hypothesis of Affective Disorders.”
8. “The gold standard was
the DSM criteria”: Steven Hyman e-mail, October 5, 2012.
9. “to the point that they
are considered”: Kupfer, First, and Regier, Research Agenda for DSM-V, xix.
10. “yet unknown”: Ibid.
11. “In
a way, I was born to do the DSM”: Michael First interview, April 25,
2011.
12. “I
have a patient”: Paul Fink interview, September 2, 2010.
13. “There is no
assumption”: DSM-IV-TR, xxxi.
14. “The purpose of
DSM-III”: DSM-III, 12.
15. “consensus of current
formulations”: DSM-III-R, xxix.
16. black-box
warning:
http://www.fda.gov/downloads/Drugs/DrugSafety/InformationbyDrugClass/UCM161641.pdf.
Chapter 5
1. “When
I heard about them”: Allen Frances interview, July 7, 2011.
2. Biederman
thought he detected in these children: Biederman, “Resolved: Mania
Is Mistaken for ADHD.”
3. a small literature
reporting a few cases of “hyperactive children”: Ibid., 1091.
4. “the essential feature
of Bipolar Disorder”: DSM-IV-TR, 382.
5. “a distinct period of
abnormally and persistently elevated”: DSM-IV-TR, 362.
6. Manic episodes have
seven Criterion B symptoms: Ibid.
7. So
Biederman set out to prove: Wozniak et al., “Mania-Like Symptoms.”
See also Biederman, “Pediatric Bipolar Disorder Coming of Age.”
8. One
in five of those patients: Wozniak et al., “Mania-Like Symptoms,”
873.
9. Biederman’s
announcement provoked: See, for instance, Klein, Pine, and Klein,
“Resolved: Mania Is Mistaken for ADHD,” and McClellan, “Commentary: Treatment
Guidelines for Child and Adolescent Bipolar Disorder.”
10. “smallpox vaccine was
ridiculed”: Biederman, “Resolved,” 1098.
11. “disorders with bipolar
features”: DSM-IV-TR, 400.
12. “thoughtful clinical
investigators”: Papolos and Papolos, The Bipolar Child, 32.
13. “latest research
findings” would recognize the symptoms: Ibid., 55–59.
14. “You have bipolar
disorder”: Anglada, Brandon and the
Bipolar Bear, 16.
15. “can’t do their job
right”: Ibid., 17.
16. Brandon most likely
inherited it: Ibid., 20.
17. “Young
and Bipolar”: “Young and Bipolar,” Time,
August 19, 2002.
18. 6.67
percent of office visits: Moreno et al., “National Trends in the
Outpatient Diagnosis and Treatment of Bipolar Disorder in Youth.”
19. “The
label may or may not reflect reality”: Benedict Carey, “Bipolar
Disorder Cases Rise Sharply in U.S. Children,” The New York
Times, September 3, 2007.
20. there is “some medicine
that could help”: Anglada, Brandon and the Bipolar Bear, 21.
21. rebranding
atypical
antipsychotics:
The APA had a hand in this effort. See Hales et al., What
Your Patients Need to Know About Psychiatric Medications, 183–85.
22. devastating
side effects: See, for example, Üçok and Gaebel, “Side Effects of
Atypical Antipsychotics: A Brief Overview.”
23. twelve-to-twenty-year
decrease in life expectancy: See Whitaker, Anatomy of an Epidemic, 175–77.
24. studies
indicating that children’s symptoms improved: For a summary, see
Kowatch et al., “Treatment Guidelines for Children and Adolescents with Bipolar
Disorder.”
25. prevalence
of BD among children: Moreno et al., “National Trends.”
26. antipsychotic
use in children and adolescents: “Antipsychotic Drug Use Among Kids
Soars,” Associated Press, May 3, 2006.
27. Gardiner
Harris reported: Gardiner Harris, “Proof Is Scant on Psychiatric
Drug Mix for Young,” The New York Times, November 23,
2006.
28. stories
such as that of Rebecca Riley: David Abel, “Hull Parents Arrested in
Girl’s Poisoning Death,” The Boston Globe, February 6,
2007.
29. “In
psychiatry Mr. Grassley has found”:
Benedict Carey and Gardiner Harris, “Psychiatric Group Faces Scrutiny over Drug
Industry Ties,” The New York Times, July 12, 2008.
30. what
Grassley found when he investigated Joseph Biederman: Gardiner
Harris and Benedict Carey, “Researchers Fail to Reveal Full Drug Pay,” The New York Times, June 8, 2008.
31. “move
forward the commercial goals”: Gardiner Harris, “Research Center
Tied to Drug Company,” The New York Times, November
25, 2008.
32. “will
support the safety and effectiveness of risperidone”: Gardiner
Harris, “Drug Maker Told Studies Would Aid It,” The New York
Times, March 20, 2009.
33. this exchange, which
followed his testimony: Ibid.
34. “I
have never seen someone so angry”: Harris, “Research Center Tied to
Drug Company.”
35. “violated
certain requirements”: Liz Kowalczyk, “Harvard Doctors Punished Over
Pay,” The Boston Globe, July 2, 2011.
36. Grassley
wasn’t stopping with Biederman: Gardiner Harris, “Top Psychiatrist
Didn’t Report Drug Makers’ Pay,” The New York Times, October
3, 2008.
37. He
revealed that Frederick Goodwin: Gardiner Harris, “Radio Host Has
Drug Company Ties,” The New York Times, November 21,
2008.
38. a
drug that has been “generic for decades”: Statement of Frederick K.
Goodwin, M.D., http://drgoodwin.com/index.php?page=nyt.
39. Alan Schatzberg owned
nearly $5 million in stock: Harris, “Top Psychiatrist.”
40. “I have come to understand”: Senator Grassley’s letter is
available at
http://www.finance.senate.gov/newsroom/ranking/release/?id=56860a96-5fba-4fb9-9207-849e796998ad.
41. nearly
one-third of the organization’s $62.5 million annual revenue: Carey
and Harris, “Psychiatric Group Faces Scrutiny over Drug Industry Ties.”
42. As
the Times had reported earlier:
Benedict Carey, “Study Finds a Link of Drug Makers to Psychiatrists,” The New York Times, April 20, 2006.
43. the
report of a team led by psychologist Lisa Cosgrove: Cosgrove et al.,
“Financial Ties Between DSM-IV Panel Members and the Pharmaceutical Industry,”
154–60.
44. “Pharmaceutical
companies have a vested interest”: Ibid., 159.
45. Restless
legs syndrome: GlaxoSmithKline, press release, June 10, 2003,
www.gsk.com/press_archive/press2003/press_06102003.htm.
46. “With
every new revelation”: Carey and Harris, “Psychiatric Group Faces
Scrutiny.”
47. the
$4 million or so the industry kicked down every year: See APA
Treasurer’s Report, May 2012. Available at https://docs.google.com/file/d/0BzWdENl1wkVSYk5aXzRZelFYUjA/edit?pli=1.
This report contains APA financial reports from 2005 to 2011.
48. “my
board thought that through”: James Scully interview, September 13,
2010.
49. it took nearly two years: Regier et al., The Conceptual Evolution of DSM-5, xxv.
50. “All
the people at the top”: Michael First interview, April 25, 2011.
51. “a
new diagnostic paradigm must be developed”: Kenneth S. Kendler et
al., “Guidelines for Making Changes to DSM-V,”
http://www.dsm5.org/ProgressReports/Documents/Guidelines-for-Making-Changes-to-DSM_1.pdf.
Chapter 6
1. “I
was bored stiff”: Allen Frances e-mail, October 7, 2011.
2. “Psychiatric
classification”: Allen Frances e-mail, October 11, 2011.
3. “Perhaps not
surprisingly, the diagnosis”: Allen Frances e-mail, October 7, 2011.
4. “confidentiality
in the development”: See Hannah Decker, “A Moment of Crisis in
American Psychiatry,” h-madness (blog), April 27,
2010,
http://historypsychiatry.com/2010/04/27/a-moment-of-crisis-in-the-history-of-american-psychiatry/.
5. the
APA had insisted: On its acceptance form, available at
http://www.dsm5.org/about/Documents/DSM%20Member%20Acceptance%20Form.pdf.
6. “We
are rethinking”: “DSM-V Development Will Be Complex and Open
Process,” Psychiatric News, June 6, 2008.
7. “I
was dumbfounded”: Robert Spitzer e-mail, September 24, 2010.
8. “I
found out how transparent” . . . “I didn’t know
whether”: Robert Spitzer, “DSM-V: Open and Transparent?” Psychiatric News, July 18, 2008.
9. “I
told him I completely agreed”: Allen Frances interview, August 15,
2010.
10. new
diagnosis to be called Psychosis Risk Syndrome: For a full
description, see Carpenter, “Anticipating DSM-V: Should Psychosis Risk Become a
Diagnostic Class?” and Woods et al., “Validity of the Prodromal Risk Syndrome
for First Psychosis.”
11. a
conversion rate of 25 to 30 percent:
See Cornblatt and Correll, “A New Diagnostic Entity in DSM-5?”
12. “I
had not been closely following”: Allen Frances interview, August 16,
2010.
13. Carpenter
explained to Pincus: William Carpenter interview, September 10,
2010.
14. “I
still think it’s a crazy idea”: Harold Pincus interview, December 9,
2011.
15. pseudoneurotic
schizophrenia: Allen Frances telephone interview, November 23, 2011.
16. “more kids getting
unneeded antipsychotics”: Allen Frances interview, August 16, 2010.
Chapter 7
1. “People
are going to write dissertations”: James Scully interview, September
13, 2010.
2. Zucker was known for research: See Zucker and Bradley, Gender Identity Disorder and Psychosexual Problems in Children and
Adolescents.
3. a
fetish Blanchard called autogynephilia: Blanchard, “The
Concept of Autogynephilia and the Typology of Male Gender Dysphoria.”
4. “out
of step”: National Gay and Lesbian Task Force, “Task Force Questions
Critical Appointments to APA’s Committee on Sexual and Gender Identity
Disorders,” news release, May 18, 2008.
http://www.thetaskforce.org/press/releases/PR_052808.
5. “thorough
and balanced”: American Psychiatric Association, “APA Statement on
GID and the DSM-V,” news release, May 23, 2008,
http://www.dsm5.org/Newsroom/Documents/APAStatementonGIDandTheDSMV.pdf.
6. “the DSM is a
diagnostic manual”: Ibid.
7. an
immediate rejoinder: Nada Stotland et al., “DSM-V: Open and
Transparent? A Response,” Psychiatric News, July 18,
2008.
8. Regier
wanted to know: Darrel Regier, William Narrow, and David Kupfer
interview, September 14, 2010.
9. “I’m
not on the task force”: Sidney Zisook interview, September 10, 2010.
10. “We
have enemies”: Stotland, “Presidential Address,” 1102.
11. “psychiatry
is a pseudoscience”: Tom Cruise, interview by Matt Lauer, Today, June 25, 2005,
http://msnbc.msn.com/id/8343367/site/todayshow/ns/today-entertainment/t/im-passionate-about-life/.
12. “Michael
First shamed me into it”: Allen Frances e-mail, December 18, 2011.
13. “Setting
the Record Straight”: Alan Schatzberg et al., “Setting the Record
Straight,” Psychiatric Times, July 1, 2008.
14. “Soaring
ambition is another matter”: William Carpenter, “Criticism vs Fact,”
Psychiatric Times, July 7, 2008.
15. “letting
nostalgia and passion”: Alarcon, “DSM-5—The We Know Better/Holier
Than Thou Crusade,” Psychiatric Times, July 14, 2008.
16. “You
must understand”: Allen Frances, letter to APA board of trustees,
July 6, 2009. http://www.scribd.com/doc/17172432/Letter-to-APA-Board-of-Trustees-July-7-2009-From-Allen-Frances-and-Robert-Spitzer.
17. The
APA’s financial picture: APA’s Treasurer Report, 2012.
18. “In reality, clinicians
in the United States”: Michael First interview, August 24, 2010.
19. the
ICD, created by a public agency, is available for download: You can
browse it yourself at http://apps.who.int/classifications/icd10/browse/2010/en.
20. an
unsettling if unsurprising discovery: Clayton et al., “The
Bereavement of the Widowed.”
21. “a full depressive
syndrome”: DSM-III, 333.
22. The bereavement exclusion:
DSM-III-R, 223.
23. he
tried to define
disease: Spitzer and Endicott, “Medical and
Mental Disorder: Proposed Definition and Criteria,” in Critical
Issues in Psychiatric Diagnosis.
24. “present concepts that
have influenced the decision”: DSM-III, 6.
25. Mental disorder, he argued: Spitzer and Endicott, “Medical and Mental
Disorder,” 30.
26. “These guys have some
chutzpah”: Kirk and Kutchins, The
Selling of DSM, 113.
27. “In DSM-III each of the
mental disorders”: DSM-III, 5–6.
28. “The syndrome or
pattern”: DSM-III-R, xxii.
29. DSM-IV devoted seven of
its 886 pages: DSM-IV, 843–49.
Chapter 8
1. “psychiatric
classification is necessarily”: Frances, “DSM in Philosophyland:
Curiouser and Curiouser.”
2. “recurrent and
persistent thoughts”: DSM-IV-TR, 462–63.
3. “A
diagnosis is a call to action”: Frances, “DSM in Philosophyland.”
4. “I
just wanted them to learn”: Allen Frances
e-mail, January 6, 2012.
5. “One
of the reasons”: Robins and Guze, “Establishment of Diagnostic
Validity in Psychiatric Illness,” 983.
6. They
concluded that T.
pallidum: For a comprehensive history of the discovery of syphilis
and its significance to modern medicine, see Quétel, History
of Syphilis. See also Greenberg, Manufacturing
Depression, 52–60.
7. a
five-step process toward validity: Robins and Guze, “Establishment
of Diagnostic Validity,” 983–84.
8. “validity tests . . .
have not lived up”: “Time for a Change?” Psychiatric News, August 21, 2009.
9. Kenneth
Kendler added another validator: Kendler, “The Nosologic Validity of
Paranoia.”
10. “the
[diagnostic] categories”: Kendler, “An Historical Framework for
Psychiatric Nosology,” 1939.
11. “to consider our major
diagnostic categories”: Ibid.
12. “critics of psychiatric
diagnoses”: Ibid.
13. “A historic and
scientific process”: Ibid.
14. “It
sounded about right”: Kendler et al., “The Development of the
Feighner Criteria,” 136.
15. “wonderful
property of iteration”: Kendler, “An Historical Framework,” 1940.
16. “assure ourselves”: Ibid.
17. “wobbly iterations”: Ibid.
Emphasis in original.
18. “asymptotes to a stable
and accurate”: Ibid., 1939.
19. paleontologist Stephen
Jay Gould: See Gould, Wonderful
Life.
20. “We
follow the tape forward”: Kendler, “An Historical Framework,” 1938.
21. “The
‘disastrous result’”: “APA Disputes Critics of DSM-V,” Psychiatric News, August 21, 2009.
22. “attempt
to address” . . . “The single most important
precondition”: Regier et al., “Conceptual Development of DSM-V,” 649.
23. “establish
better syndrome boundaries”: Darrel Regier e-mail, October 5, 2010.
24. Some diagnoses, such as
depression: DSM-IV-TR, 413.
25. Global Assessment of
Functioning: DSM-IV-TR, 32–34.
26. National Institutes of
Health had created PROMIS: See www.nihpromis.org.
27. “bottoms-up approach”: Regier et al., “Conceptual Development,” 648.
28. “If they really want to
do dimensional assessment”: Michael First interview, September 28, 2010.
29. “We
don’t expect the DSM-5”: Darrel Regier e-mail, October 11, 2010.
30. Diagnostic
criteria “are intended”: Regier et al., “Conceptual Development,”
648–49.
Chapter 9
1. “Advice
to DSM V”: Allen Frances, “Advice to DSM V . . . Change Deadlines
and Text, Keep Criteria Stable,” Psychiatric Times (blog),
August 26, 2009, www.psychiatrictimes.com/display/article/10168/1444663.
2. in the field trials the
new criteria identified 15 percent more: Lahey et al., “DSM-IV Field Trials for
ADHD,” 1682.
3. the
actual increase was 28 percent: Akinbami et al., “Attention Deficit
Hyperactivity Disorder Among Children,” 2.
4. “everything
was on the table”: Allen Frances, “Alert to the Research Community,”
Psychiatric Times, January 7, 2010.
5. “over
the cliff”: Frances, “Advice to DSM-V.”
6. “I
take more blame for DSM-IV”: Allen Frances interview, August 16,
2010.
7. “some
of us have gotten”: Shirley Wang, “Psychiatrists
Bash Back at Critics of Diagnostic Manual Revision,” Wall
Street Journal Health Blog, January 8, 2009,
blogs.wsj.com/health/2009//01/08/psychiatrists-bash-back-at-critics-of-diagnostic-manual-revision.
8. “The
development process has been so public”: Alan Schatzberg, “Some
Thoughts on DSM-V,” Psychiatric News, August 21, 2009.
9. “I’m
too small a fish”: Jane Costello e-mail, August 1, 2010.
10. “I cannot in good conscience”: Jane Costello resignation
letter, available at http://www.scribd.com/doc/17162466/Jane-Costello-Resignation-Letter-from-DSMV-Task-Force-to-Danny-Pine-March-27-2009.
11. the
response came from Darrel Regier: Regier supplied me with the letter
via e-mail, November 11, 2010.
12. “Since
we considered”: Darrel Regier e-mail, November 11, 2010.
13. “When
there is smoke”: Carolyn Robinowitz interview, October 4, 2010.
14. the
APA issued a press release: American Psychiatric Association, “DSM-5
Publication Date Moved to May 2013,” news release, December 10, 2009,
http://www.dsm5.org/Newsroom/Documents/09-65%20DSM%20Timeline.pdf.
15. “long
vetting process”: Beth Casteel e-mail, November 11, 2010.
16. “I’m
going to be quite critical”: Allen Frances, “DSM-V in Severe
Distress: Is a Happy Ending Possible?” January 15, 2010,
http://columbiapsychiatry.org/videos/dsm-v-severe-distress-happy-ending-still-possible.
17. The
APA posted a full draft: Although it has since been taken down, the
draft is available at
http://web.archive.org/web/20100402094501/http://www.dsm5.org/ProposedRevisions/Pages/Default.aspx.
18. “Anything
you put in that book”: Benedict Carey, “Revising Book on Disorders
of the Mind,” The New York Times, February 10, 2010.
19. “The
19 Worst Suggestions for DSM5”: Allen Frances, “Opening Pandora’s
Box: The 19 Worst Suggestions for DSM5,” Psychiatric Times,
February 11, 2010,
www.psychiatrictimes.com/print/article/10168/1522341?printable=true.
Chapter 10
1. another
letter to the trustees: Frances, “To the Membership of the APA,” Psychiatric Times, June 2, 2010,
http://www.psychiatrictimes.com/dsm-5/content/article/10168/1565491.
2. “I
was of age in the ’60s”: Allen Frances e-mail, January 23, 2012.
3. “I never yell”: Ibid.
4. “nice irony”: Ibid.
5. “This
was the stupidest idea in the world”: Allen Frances telephone
interview, November 23, 2011.
6. “After
the third or fourth”: Herb Peyser interview, January 23, 2012.
7. Freud once said: See Freud, The Joke and Its Relation to the Unconscious.
8. “orderly
and democratic process”: David Shaffer interview, December 8, 2011.
9. “David
probably misinterpreted”: Allen Frances e-mail, January 23, 2012.
10. “that
children with the broad phenotype”: Leibenluft et al., “Defining
Clinical Phenotypes of Juvenile Mania,” 436.
11. “claim
to define a new diagnosis”: Leibenluft, “Severe Mood Dysregulation,”
131.
12. “Justification
for Temper Dysregulation Disorder with Dysphoria”: “Justification
for Temper Dysregulation Disorder,” http://www.dsm5.org/Proposed%20Revision%20Attachments/Justification%20for%20Temper%20Dysregulation%20Disorder%20with%20Dysphoria.pdf.
13. it
announced a new “naming convention”: American Psychiatric
Association, “APA Modifies DSM Naming Convention to Reflect Publication
Changes,” news release, March 9, 2010.
14. “distinctly
unmedical”: Schatzberg, “Presidential Address,” 1163.
15. “Some of the attacks”: Ibid.
16. New Orleans had “risen
as the Phoenix”: Ibid., 1162.
17. “the negative attacks
on industry”: Ibid., 1164.
18. “There are a number of
new drugs”: Ibid.
Chapter 11
1. “Turning
bereavement into major depression”: Allen Frances, “Good Grief,” The New York Times, August 14, 2010.
2. “Sure,
there’s a reality out there”: Allen Frances interview, August 16,
2010.
3. “The
full truth”: Allen Frances e-mail, February 2, 2012.
4. “Like
most medical specialties”: Allen Frances interview, July 7, 2011.
5. “stigmatization
[and] inappropriate care”: Wakefield et al., “Extending the
Bereavement Exclusion,” 433.
6. “ignore the many other
kinds”: Ibid., 434.
7. “define every
undesirable consequence”: Horwitz and Wakefield, The Loss of Sadness, 220–21.
8. “Psychiatry has made
immense strides”: Ibid., 225.
9. “There are few signs”: Ibid., 212.
10. “It just doesn’t make
any sense to me whatsoever”: Sidney Zisook interview, September 10, 2010.
11. Zisook
did some data mining of his own: Zisook and Kendler, “Is
Bereavement-Related Depression Different Than Non-Bereavement-Related
Depression?”
12. “provides some
support”: Ibid., 791.
13. “Because
work toward the DSM-V”: Zisook et al., “Validity of the Bereavement
Exclusion,” 102.
14. “validity of the
bereavement exclusion”: Ibid., 104.
15. “Why should bereavement
be singled out”: Ibid., 105.
16. “Idiotic”:
Jerome Wakefield e-mail, January 31, 2012.
17. a
study showing that GSK’s Wellbutrin: Zisook et al., “Buproprion
Sustained Relief for Bereavement.”
18. “The
DSM-IV position is not logically defensible”: Kendler, “Grief
Exclusion,” http://www.dsm5.org/about/Documents/grief%20exclusion_Kendler.pdf.
19. “that
sadness in response to loss”: Wakefield et al., “Extending the
Bereavement Exclusion,” 439.
Chapter 12
1. “the
best we can do”: See Allen Frances, “The Most Important Psychiatrist
of Our Time,” Psychiatric Times, December 22, 2010.
2. “Moving
forward”: Regier, “Diagnostic Threshold Considerations for DSM-5,”
293.
3. “the clinical judgment
of a psychiatrist”: Ibid., 285.
4. the
National Comorbidity Survey: Kessler et al., “Lifetime and 12-Month
Prevalence of DSM-III-R Psychiatric Disorders in the United States.”
5. “We had much greater
confidence”: Ibid., 286.
6. Regier’s
team began to dig them out: Narrow et al., “Revised Prevalence
Estimates of Mental Disorders in the United States.”
7. “To
put it mildly”: Regier, “Diagnostic Threshold Considerations,” 288.
8. Wakefield
and Spitzer pointed out: Wakefield and Spitzer, “Lowered
Estimates—but of What?”
9. “What
is striking about this debate”: Regier, “Diagnostic Threshold
Considerations,” 289.
10. “to
define the problem out of existence”: Kessler et al., “Mild
Disorders Should Not Be Eliminated from the DSM-V,” 1.121.
11. “In
response to this scientific critique”: Regier, “Diagnostic Threshold
Considerations,” 289.
12. “I
wasn’t aware that he had interpreted”: Ronald Kessler e-mail,
February 9, 2012.
13. “Certainly
some of the loudest concerns”: Regier, “Diagnostic Threshold
Considerations,” 290.
14. Just look at the
history of “progress”: Ibid.
15. “It may be of
interest”: Ibid., 292–93.
16. “Since the broad
definition”: Ibid., 293.
17. “DSM-IV has a label for
everyone you might want to treat”: Roger Peele interview, November 4, 2011.
18. his
$600,000-per-year salary: That is as of 2010, according to the APA’s
tax return, available at http://www.guidestar.org/FinDocuments/2010/130/433/2010-130433740-077883c7-9.pdf.
19. “The spirit of
moderation”: Montesquieu, The Spirit
of Laws,
49.
20. “They [the dimensional
measures] will continue to evolve”: Darrel Regier e-mail, September 29, 2010.
Chapter 13
1. more
than eight thousand comments: Joan Arehart-Treichel, “DSM-5 Work
Groups Assess Thousands of Comments,” Psychiatric News,
August 20, 2010.
2. “developed
a strong sense of uniqueness and belonging”: Bernstein, “DSM-5: Year
Ahead and Year in Review,” Psychiatric News, August
20, 2010.
3. “I fought to get myself
comfortable in high school”: Nomi Kaim interview, June 16, 2011.
4. “It
was a total add-on”: Fred Volkmar interview, March 1, 2012.
5. The
disorder was first described by an Austrian pediatrician: See Wing,
“Asperger’s Syndrome: A Clinical Account,” and Lyons and Fitzgerald, “Asperger
and Kanner, the Two Pioneers.”
6. “an especially intimate
relationship”: Wing, “Asperger’s Syndrome,” 117–18.
7. “pervasive lack of
responsiveness”: DSM-III, 89.
8. “the syndromes are more
alike than unalike”: Wing, “Asperger’s Syndrome,” 121.
9. “the term is helpful”: Ibid., 124.
10. Of
the nearly one thousand subjects: Volkmar et al., “Field Trial for
Autistic Disorder in DSM-IV.”
11. “The
Little Professor Syndrome”: Lawrence Osborne, “The Little Professor
Syndrome,” The New York Times Magazine, June 18, 2000.
12. “Some
things made sense”: Michael Carley and CC interview, October 13,
2011.
13. “I . . . have yet to
stand successfully”: Carley, Asperger’s from the Inside Out, 4.
14. “At
GRASP we envision a world”: http://grasp.org/page/mission-statement.
15. She
ballparked it: Wing, “Asperger’s Syndrome,” 119–20.
16. Eric Fombonne, an
epidemiologist working in England, reviewed: Fombonne, “The
Epidemiology of Autism: A Review.”
17. “secular increase”: Ibid., 777.
18. a
rate of 34 per 10,000: Yeargin-Alsopp, “Prevalence of Autism in a
U.S. Metropolitan Area,” 53.
19. these results were “an
underestimate”: Ibid., 81.
20. As
of 2002, the CDC reported: All CDC figures can be found in Autism
and Developmental Disabilities Monitoring Network, “Prevalence of Autism
Spectrum Disorders,” available at
http://www.cdc.gov/ncbddd/autism/documents/ADDM-2012-Community-Report.pdf.
21. “opening
Pandora’s Box”: Wing, “Reflections on Opening Pandora’s Box.”
22. a
prevalence rate in a city in Korea: Kim et al., “Prevalence of
Autism Spectrum Disorders,” 907.
23. blitzed
the media: “New Study Reveals Autism Prevalence in South Korea,”
Autism Speaks, news release, May 9, 2011.
24. “the
need for improved and wider autism screening”: “Top Ten Autism
Research Achievements of 2011,” Autism Speaks, news release, December 20, 2011,
http://www.autismspeaks.org/about-us/press-releases/top-10-autism-research-achievements-2011.
25. “a
stigmatizing hereditary disorder”: Kim et al., “Prevalence of
Autism,” 910.
26. “Lower
rates in 9- and 10-year-olds”: Yeargin-Alsopp, “Prevalence of Autism
in a U.S. Metropolitan Area,” 53.
27. “Diagnosis
of ASDs”: Charman, “The Highs and Lows of Counting Autism,” 874.
28. “canaries [who] sensed
before anyone else”: Lethem, The Ecstasy of Influence, 73.
29. “premature
to add Asperger’s”: Michael First e-mail, March 20, 2012.
30. “We
probably were premature”: Allen Frances e-mail, February 20, 2012.
31. “It
involves a use of treatment resources”: Amy Harmon, “A Specialists’
Debate on Autism Has Many Worried Observers,” The New York
Times, January 20. 2012.
32. “The
goal was not to change prevalence”: Catherine Lord interview, March
29, 2012.
33. most
important factor in determining which diagnosis: Lord et al., “A
Multisite Study of the Clinical Diagnosis of Different Autism Spectrum
Disorders,” 309–11.
Chapter 14
1. “People
say, ‘What’s in a name?’”: Dilip Jeste, “State of Classification of
Neurocognitive Disorders,” American Psychiatric Association annual meeting, May
17, 2011.
2. “Attire
is ‘aloha business/casual’”:
http://web.archive.org/web/20110523195007/http://www.psych.org/annualmeeting.
3. “invent[ing]
out of thin air”: Thomas Widiger, “The DSM-5 Personality Disorder
Dimensional Model,” American Psychiatric Association annual meeting, May 15,
2011.
4. “I
do sense a reactionary element”: David Shaffer, “State of the
Science on Diagnostic Classification: Implications for DSM-5,” American
Psychiatric Association annual meeting, May 17, 2011.
5. “Allen
and I have a big disagreement”: Michael First interview, March 2,
2012.
6. First
stuck to small ball: Michael First, “The Future of Psychiatric
Nosology,” Association for the Advancement of Philosophy and Psychiatry annual
meeting, May 15, 2011.
7. Kupfer
and Regier demonstrate: David J. Kupfer and Darrel A. Regier,
“Diagnostic Assessment in DSM-5: Approaches and Examples,” American Psychiatric
Association annual meeting, May 16, 2011.
8. “That’s
why we are doing a field test”: Darrel Regier interview, September
14, 2010.
9. “two
rigorous study designs”: American Psychiatric Association, “APA
Announces Start of Field Trials for DSM-5,” press release, October 5, 2010.
10. “I’m
surprised”: Darrel Regier e-mail, October 6, 2010.
11. “People’s
expectations of what reliability should be”: Kraemer, “DSM-5 Field
Trials,” American Psychiatric Association annual meeting, May 17, 2011.
12. Spitzer “could have
employed”: Kirk and Kutchins, The
Selling of DSM, 61–62.
13. “We’d
better get smart about measuring”: Lawson Wulsin, “DSM-5 Research
and Development,” American Psychiatric Association annual meeting, May 16,
2011.
Chapter 15
1. “You
have to understand”: Allen Frances interview, July 9, 2011.
2. “If
it seems like this is coming”: Allen Frances interview, August 16,
2010.
3. “My narcissism couldn’t
survive the teenage insight”: Allen Frances e-mail, April 22, 2010.
4. “over a period of at least 6
months” . . . “The fantasies, sexual urges”: DSM-IV, 528.
5. “the
symptom criteria alone”: First and Frances, “Issues for DSM-V,”
1240.
6. “While
we have been preoccupied”: Linda Bowles, “Kinder Gentler
Pedophilia,” WorldNetDaily, http://www.wnd.com/1999/05/228/.
7. “acknowledge
the ‘APA’s clear opposition’”: Linda Bowles, “Pedophilia: Good News
Bad News,” WorldNetDaily, http://www.wnd.com/1999/06/231/.
8. if someone “has acted
on these urges”: DSM-IV-TR, 572.
9. “Fewer
than half of child molesters”: Michael First e-mail, April 22, 2012.
10. “too
polemical”: Kutchins and Kirk, Making Us Crazy,
164–65.
11. “a
tendency to feel inordinately threatened”:
Pantony and Caplan, “Delusional Dominating Personality Disorder,” 127–30.
12. “I
really wasn’t sure”: Kutchins and Kirk, Making Us
Crazy, 171.
13. “It is disruptive to
constantly tinker”: Ibid., 172.
14. Caplan
did give Frances a shout-out: Paula Caplan, “DSM-5 Heads’ Comments
Reveal Lack of Compassion and of Respect for Science,” When
Johnny and Jane Come Marching Home (blog),
http://whenjohnnyandjanecomemarching.weebly.com/1/post/2011/05/dsm-5-heads-new-comments-reveal-lack-of-compassion-and-of-respect-for-science.html.
15. On
the appointed day: This account is from Caplan, “Letter from DSM-5
Task Force Head Leaves Major Concerns Unanswered,” Science
Isn’t Golden (blog),
http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/science-isnt-golden/201106/letter-dsm-5-task-force-head-leaves-major-concerns-unanswered-part-1.
The public relations firm that arranged the conference call declined to
comment.
16. “the
continued and continuous medicalisation”: British Psychological
Society, “Response to the American Psychiatric Association:
DSM-5 Development,” http://apps.bps.org.uk/_publicationfiles/consultation-responses/DSM-5%202011%20-%20BPS%20response.pdf.
17. Regier
made clear in his official response: See “Society’s Critical
Response to DSM-5,” The Psychologist News, July 13,
2011,
http://www.thepsychologist.org.uk/blog/blogpost.cfm?threadid=2102&catid=48.
18. “previous failures”: Melville, The Confidence-Man, 77.
19. “stranger entering”: Ibid.
20. “general
resistance or indifference”: Blanchard et al., “Pedophilia,
Hebephilia, and the DSM-V,” 336.
21. “discriminable erotic
age-preference”: Ibid., 335.
22. “Your
neighbors’ 7-year-old girl”: Blanchard et al., “IQ, Handedness, and
Pedophilia in Adult Male Patients,” 292.
23. “to
minimize his embarrassment”: Blanchard et al., “Pedophilia,
Hebephilia, and the DSM-V,” 339.
24. “hebephilia exists”: Ibid., 347–48.
Chapter 16
1. “We
are . . . test piloting”: APA Research e-mail, July 8, 2011.
2. “The
most common reason”: Now found at
http://www.findthatpdf.com/search-80840213-hPDF/download-documents-ft-20note-20for-20web-20site.pdf.htm.
3. “We
have learned”: Eve Moscicki e-mail, September 9, 2011.
4. “Thanks for your candid
note”:
Ibid.
5. another
note from Kupfer and Regier: APA Research e-mail, September 20,
2011.
6. DSM-5
proposal for Generalized Anxiety Disorder: This once appeared at
www.dsm5.org/ProposedRevisions1.2011/Pages/proposedrevision5478.html?rid=167.
7. the
old one: DSM-IV-TR, 476.
8. “A Personality Disorder
is an enduring pattern”: DSM-IV-TR, 685.
9. “ensures that
consideration will be given”: DSM-IV-TR, 28.
10. “I
think this is the best way”: Allen Frances e-mail, May 1, 2012.
11. “I have never really
been a doctor”: Gay, Freud, 681.
12. “They have the lowest reliability”: Allen Frances e-mail,
May 12, 2012. See Frances, “The DSM-III Personality Disorders Section: A
Commentary.”
13. The
kappas were .56 to .65: Spitzer et al., “DSM-III Field Trials: I.
Initial Interrater Diagnostic Reliability.”
14. “the
personality disorders are not at all clearly distinct”: Frances,
“The DSM-III Personality Disorders Section,” 1050.
15. “Rather than being
diagnosed”: Ibid., 1051.
16. “committed
dimensionalist”: Allen Frances e-mail, May 17, 2012.
17. “I
believe I was chosen”: Thomas Widiger e-mail, May 21, 2012.
18. “under active
investigation”: DSM-IV, 633–34.
19. a
paper, published just before DSM-IV: Frances, “Dimensional Diagnosis
of Personality Disorders—Not Whether but When and Which.”
20. “It
might be more consistent”: First et al., “Personality Disorders and
Relational Disorders,” 130.
21. “uniform classification
of general personality functioning”: Ibid., 131.
22. “That
is why I pushed”: Michael First e-mail, May 15, 2012.
23. Regier,
he said, had asked him: Thomas Widiger e-mail, May 21, 2012.
24. According
to Widiger’s distillation: See Widiger and Simonsen, “Alternative
Dimensional Models of Personality Disorder.”
25. “basic science
research”: Ibid., 123.
26. “The devil, of course”: Ibid., 126.
27. “Nobody
on the work group”: Thomas Widiger e-mail, May 21, 2012.
28. “a
sense of self-identity”: For the original proposal, see
http://web.archive.org/web/20100323205756/http://www.dsm5.org/ProposedRevisions/Pages/PersonalityandPersonalityDisorders.aspx.
29. insufficient
“empirical evidence”: Skodol, “Personality Disorder Types Proposed
for DSM-5,” 138.
30. “We
knew we couldn’t incorporate”: Andrew Skodol interview, May 24,
2012.
31. “embarrassingly
bad”: Thomas Widiger e-mail, September 23, 2010.
32. “lost
opportunity” that “negates years of progress”: Livesley, “Confusion
and Incoherence in the Classification of Personality Disorder,” 307.
33. “cumbersome
hodgepodge”: Frances, “The DSM-5 Personality Disorders,” DSM-5 in Distress (blog), http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/dsm5-in-distress/201004/the-dsm5-personality-disorders-great-intentions-unusable-result.
34. “an
unwieldy conglomeration”: Shedler et al., “Personality Disorders in
DSM-5,” 1027.
Chapter 17
1. “There
has been a continual struggle”: Helena Hansen, e-mail, September 27,
2011.
2. “This
is amazing!”: Helena Hansen e-mail, September 28, 2011.
3. “Approaching
endgame”: Allen Frances e-mail, November 14, 2011.
4. “A
random and geographically diverse”: Allen Frances e-mail, October
31, 2011.
5. “pretty
Spockean”: Allen Frances e-mail, September 21, 2010.
6. an
open letter to the APA: Available at
http://www.ipetitions.com/petition/dsm5/.
7. a
letter on behalf of his 115,000: Available at
http://www.counseling.org/Resources/pdfs/ACA_DSM-5_letter_11-11.pdf.
8. “bring
Darrel to see DSM-5”: Allen Frances e-mail, August 28, 2010.
9. “trying
to negotiate”: Allen Frances e-mail, November 15, 2011.
10. “Cast of fascinating
and colorful characters”: Ibid.
11. “This will likely be
the most important”: Allen Frances e-mail, October 25, 2011.
12. “Don’t waste your best
brains”: Ibid.
13. “I
was in Dubuque”: Allen Frances e-mail, November 4, 2011.
14. “your
brilliant opening”: Allen Frances e-mail, October 16, 2011.
15. “Paula
Caplan in drag”: Allen Frances e-mail, January 5, 2012.
16. “one-time
pillar of the psychiatric establishment”: Rob Waters, “Therapists
Revolt Against Psychiatry’s Bible,”
http://www.salon.com/2011/12/27/therapists_revolt_against_psychiatrys_bible/.
17. “Fate
has an ironic sense of humor”: Allen Frances e-mail, July 14, 2011.
18. “Everything
I say”: Allen Frances e-mail, October 16, 2011.
19. “Where you see intelligent conspiracy”: Allen Frances
e-mail, September 18, 2011.
20. “Dereification
is just as dumb”: Allen Frances e-mail, January 15, 2012.
21. “I
like to think the best of you”: Allen Frances e-mail, January 5,
2012.
22. “What’s
the ending mean?”: Allen Frances telephone interview, November 23,
2011.
23. I
received this message: Eve Herold e-mail, November 7, 2011.
24. “We
realize how challenging it is”: Lisa Countis e-mail, November 7,
2011.
25. “This behavior
pattern”: DSM-I, 35.
26. “The
journey into the future”: The newsletter is available at
http://api.ning.com/files/AbciMXSvxet4NaqPJajU41T2kvOhgvc3JLSZdblrTDlfSyH4b2tKRiorseSDWZFCrifi7jgzHZyn7S5TvwzCpddFjQN—kLt/DSM5.fieldtrials.pdf.
27. the
treasurer delivered grim news: http://www.ncpsychiatry.org/APA/APA%20Assembly%20ReportNov2011.pdf.
28. running
a blog called Dsm5watch: It can now be found at dxrevisionwatch.com.
29. “It
has come to our attention”: Cecilia Stoute e-mail to Suzy Chapman,
December 22, 2011.
30. “I
thought it was a hoax”: Suzy Chapman e-mail, June 11, 2012.
31. “I
could not finance a legal wrangle”: Suzy Chapman e-mail, February
27, 2012.
Chapter 18
1. “The
idea of medicalizing normality”: Elizabeth Lopatto, “Psychiatric
Group Push to Redefine Mental Illness Sparks Revolt,” Bloomberg
Businessweek, January 27, 2012.
2. “I
wasn’t exactly hiding it”: Fred Volkmar e-mail, June 26, 2012.
3. “It
was one thing to make a change”: Michael Carley e-mail, June 28,
2012.
4. “damage
control”:
http://grasp.org/profiles/blogs/very-important-dsm-5-update.
5. “We
have to make sure”: Amy Harmon, “A Specialists’ Debate on Autism Has
Many Worried Observers,” The New York Times, January
20, 2012.
6. “There
has never been an agenda”: Debra Brauser, “Concern over Changes to
Autism Criteria Unfounded,” Medscape Medical News,
January 25, 2012.
7. “10,000
plus e-mails”: This exchange, not reported in the press, is
available at
http://grasp.org/profiles/blogs/dsm-5-update-a-poor-poor-descent-into-pettiness.
8. a
Carey-penned DSM piece: Benedict Carey, “Grief Could Join List of
Disorders,” The New York Times, January 24, 2012.
9. a World Psychiatry article by Jerry Wakefield and
Michael First: Wakefield and First, “Validity of the Bereavement
Exclusion to Major Depression: Does the Empirical Evidence Support the Proposal
to Eliminate the Exclusion in DSM-5?”
10. “set
out realistic expectations”: Kraemer et al., “DSM-5: How Reliable Is
Reliable Enough?,” 13.
11. a
pair of op-ed columns: Paul Steinberg, “Asperger’s History of
Overdiagnosis,” and Benjamin Nugent, “I Had Asperger Syndrome, Briefly,” The New York Times, January 31, 2012.
12. “The
proposals in DSM-5”: See “Psychologists Fear US Manual Will Widen
Mental Illness Diagnosis,” The Guardian, February 9,
2012.
13. The Lancet . . . in a single
issue, a report: See
http://www.thelancet.com/journals/lancet/issue/vol379no9816/PIIS0140-6736%2812%29X6007-0.
14. “I
still feel sadness”: Kleinman, “Culture, Bereavement, and
Psychiatry,” 608.
15. “even
if,” as the Illinois version put it: Public Act 097-0972 available
at http://www.ilga.gov/legislation/publicacts/fulltext.asp?Name=097-0972.
16. “the
door is still very much open”: John Gever, “DSM-5 Critics Pump Up
the Volume,” MedPage Today, February 29, 2012.
17. “You’ve
got to feel sorry”: Gary Greenberg, “Not Diseases, but Categories of
Suffering,” The New York Times, January 29, 2012.
18. “Wonderful
news”: “Wonderful News: DSM 5 Finally Begins Its Belated and
Necessary Retreat,” Psychology Today (blog), May 2,
2012. http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/dsm5-in-distress/201205/wonderful-news-dsm-5-finally-begins-its-belated-and-necessary-retreat.
19. “stain
on psychiatry” . . . “Cassandra”: Allen
Frances e-mail, April 29, 2012.
20. “We
encourage the wide dissemination”: Roger Peele provided the memo via
e-mail, April 29, 2012.
21. “What
possible copyright excuse”: Allen Frances e-mail, April 23, 2012.
22. “It
is just too nutty” . . . “I used to compare”:
Allen Frances e-mail, April 30, 2012.
Chapter 19
1. a
DSM-5-related 60 percent increase: Mewton et al., “An Evaluation of
the Proposed DSM-5 Alcohol Use Disorder Criteria Using Australian National
Data,” 947.
2. “I
wanted to avoid a repeat of Axis V”: Roger Peele interview, August
2, 2012.
3. “Conceptual questions
are not minor ‘side issues’”: Kendler et al., “Issues for DSM-V,” 175.
4. “Yes,” he said, “but I
do like a challenge”: Michael First e-mail, May 12, 2012.
5. “I
felt if I just addressed”: Swedo, “Making National Headlines,”
American Psychiatric Association annual meeting, May 6, 2012.
6. “Newsflash
from APA Meeting”: See
http://www.huffingtonpost.com/allen-frances/dsm-5-reliability-tests_b_1490857.html.
7. “The controversy
stirred by my critique”: Allen Frances e-mail, June 29, 2012.
Chapter 20
1. “Melancholia,”
they wrote: Parker et al., “Issues for DSM-5: Whither Melancholia?,”
745.
2. “distinct,
identifiable, and specifically treatable”: Ibid., 747.
3. “I
believe the inclusion of a biological measure”: William Coryell
e-mail to Max Fink, October 16, 2008.
4. “I
[am] flabbergasted”: Max Fink e-mail to William Coryell, April 9,
2010.
5. “I
believe you and your colleagues”: William Coryell e-mail to Max
Fink, April 12, 2010.
6. “The
APA owns all products”:
http://www.dsm5.org/Pages/PermissionsPolicy.aspx.
7. “arrogance,
secretiveness” . . . “is no longer capable”: Allen Frances, “Diagnosing the DSM,” The
New York Times, May 11, 2012.
8. “Our
resources are more likely”: Thomas Insel e-mail, October 13, 2010.
9. What
Insel heard “over and over again”: Thomas Insel and Bruce Cuthbert
interview, December 12, 2011.
10. “So many of our
disorders”: Ibid.
11. “We
call this attention deficit/hyperactivity disorder”: Thomas Insel,
“Rethinking Mental Illness,” American Psychiatric Association annual meeting,
May 14, 2011.
12. “Why
do you hate psychiatrists”: Allen Frances e-mail, October 20, 2012.
13. “DSM-IV-TR attempts to
describe”: Sadock and Sadock, Kaplan & Sadock’s
Concise Textbook of Clinical Psychiatry, 33.
14. “difficulty of
distinguishing a manic episode”: Ibid., 218.
15. “depressive symptoms
are present”: Ibid.
16. “every sign or symptom
seen in schizophrenia”: Ibid., 167.
17. “Once a diagnosis has
been established”: Ibid., 222.
18. “no one drug is
predictably effective”: Ibid., 224.
19. “Often,” advise Sadock
and Sadock, “it is necessary”: Ibid.
20. “the objective of
pharmacologic treatment”: Ibid.
21. “Not
everyone needs to see”: Allen Frances e-mail, October 20, 2012.
22. “Whatever
we’ve been doing for five decades”: Thomas Insel and Bruce Cuthbert
interview, December 12, 2011.
23. Seventy-two
percent: Mojtabai and Olfson, “Proportion of Antidepressants
Prescribed Without a Psychiatric Diagnosis Is Growing,” 1436.
24. “abnormal sensations”
and “nonspecific pain”: Ibid., 1437.
25. “The future belongs to illness”: Sedgwick,
“Illness—Mental and Otherwise,” 37.
Afterword
1. an
occasion to release some details: “American Psychiatric Association
Board of Trustees Approves DSM-5,” news release,
December 1, 2012.
2. “We
do ask that you focus”: This e-mail was provided to me by Roger
Peele.
3. one
article—in The
Washington Post: Peter Whoriskey,
“Antidepressants to Treat Grief? Psychiatry Panelists with Ties to Drug
Industry Say Yes,” The Washington Post, December 26,
2012.
4. “DSM-5
includes material”: Statement of David Kupfer,
http://www.psychnews.org/files/Response_to_Wash_Post.pdf.
5. Dilip
Jeste, the APA president, told Congress: Letter from Dilip Jeste to
Harry Reid, John Boehner, Mitchell McConnell, and Nancy Pelosi,
http://www.psychiatry.org/advocacy—newsroom/advocacy/apa-sends-letter-to-congress-regarding-recent-shooting-in-newtownct.
6. Not
only was LaPierre’s language “offensive”: “American Psychiatric
Association Responds to NRA Comments,” news release, December 23, 2012,
http://www.psychiatry.org/File%20Library/Advocacy%20and%20Newsroom/Press%20Releases/2012%20Releases/12-45-APA-Response-to-NRA-Comments.pdf.
7. “The
saddest day”: Allen Frances, “DSM 5 Is Guide Not Bible—Ignore Its
Ten Worst Changes,” DSM-5 in Distress (blog),
http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/dsm5-in-distress/201212/dsm-5-is-guide-not-bible-ignore-its-ten-worst-changes.
8. “one
last act”: Allen Frances, “One Last Chance for the APA to Make the
DSM-5 Safer,” The Huffington Post (blog),
http://www.huffingtonpost.com/allen-frances/one-last-chance-for-the-apa-to-make-the-dsm-5-safer_b_2294868.html.
9. “Any
new boycott must unify the diverse opposition”: Allen Frances, “DSM
5 Boycotts and Petitions: Too Many, Too Sectarian,” Saving
Normal: Mental Health and What Is Normal (blog), February 8, 2013,
http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/saving-normal/201302/dsm-5-boycotts-and-petitions.
10. “I
can confirm”: Michael First e-mail, November 27, 2012.
11. “The
good news”: Michael First e-mail January 7, 2013.
Akinbami,
Lara J., Xiang Liu, Patricia M. Pastor, and Cynthia A. Reuben. “Attention
Deficit Hyperactivity Disorder Among Children Aged 5–17 Years in the United
States 1998–2009.” NCHS Data Brief, no. 70 (August
2011).
American
Psychiatric Association. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual,
Mental Disorders (DSM-I). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric
Association, 1952.
American
Psychiatric Association. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of
Mental Disorders: DSM-III. Washington, DC.: American Psychiatric
Association, 1980.
American
Psychiatric Association. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of
Mental Disorders: DSM-III-R. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric
Association, 1987.
American
Psychiatric Association. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of
Mental Disorders: DSM-IV-TR. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric
Association, 2000.
American
Psychiatric Association. Statistical Manual for the Use of
Hospitals for Mental Diseases. Albany, NY: State Hospitals Press, 1942.
Anglada,
Tracy, Toby Ferguson, and Jennifer Taylor. Brandon and the
Bipolar Bear: A Story for Children with Bipolar Disorder. Victoria,
Canada: Trafford, 2004.
Ash,
P. “The Reliability of Psychiatric Diagnosis.” Journal of
Abnormal and Social Psychology 44 (1949): 272–77.
Bayer, Ronald. Homosexuality and American Psychiatry: The Politics of Diagnosis. New York: Basic Books,
1981.
Beard, George Miller. American Nervousness: Its Causes and Consequences; A Supplement to Nervous
Exhaustion (Neurasthenia). New York: G. P. Putnam’s Sons, 1881.
Beck,
Aaron T. “Reliability of Psychiatric Diagnoses: 1. A Critique of Systematic
Studies.” American Journal of Psychiatry 119 (1962):
210–16.
Biederman,
Joseph. “Pediatric Bipolar Disorder Coming of Age.” Biological
Psychiatry 53, no. 11 (2003): 931–34.
Biederman,
Joseph. “Resolved: Mania Is Mistaken for ADHD in Prepubertal Children
(Affirmed).” Journal of the American Academy of Child and
Adolescent Psychiatry 37, no. 10 (October 1998): 1091–93.
Blanchard,
Ray. “The Concept of Autogynephilia and the Typology of Male Gender Dysphoria.”
The Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease 177, no. 10
(1989): 616–23.
Blanchard,
Ray, Amy D. Lykins, Diane Wherrett, et al. “Pedophilia, Hebephilia, and the
DSM-V.” Archives of Sexual Behavior 38, no. 3 (2009):
335–50.
Blanchard,
Ray, Nathan J. Kolla, James M. Cantor, et al. “IQ, Handedness, and Pedophilia
in Adult Male Patients Stratified by Referral Source.” Sexual
Abuse: A Journal of Research and Treatment 19, no. 3 (2007): 285–309.
Carley, Michael John. Asperger’s from the Inside Out: A Supportive and Practical Guide for
Anyone with Asperger’s Syndrome. New York: Perigee, 2008.
Carpenter,
W. T. “Anticipating DSM-V: Should Psychosis Risk Become a Diagnostic Class?” Schizophrenia Bulletin 35, no. 5 (2009): 841–43.
Cartwright,
Samuel. “Diseases and Peculiarities of the Negro Race,” Part 1. In DeBow’s Review, Vol. 11, Series 4 (New Orleans, 1851):
331–36.
Cartwright,
Samuel. “Diseases and Peculiarities of the Negro Race,” Part 2. In DeBow’s Review, Vol. 11, Series 4 (New Orleans, 1851):
504–8.
Charman,
Tony. “The Highs and Lows of Counting Autism.” American
Journal of Psychiatry 168, no. 9 (2011): 873–75.
Clayton,
Paula J., J. A. Halikes, and W. L. Maurice. “The Bereavement of the Widowed.” Diseases of the Nervous System 32, no. 9 (1971): 597–604.
Cornblatt,
Barbara A., and Christoph U. Correll. “A New Diagnostic Entity in DSM-5?” Medscape, September 3, 2010.
Cosgrove,
Lisa, Sheldon Krimsky, Manisha Vijayaraghavan, and Lisa Schneider. “Financial
Ties Between DSM-IV Panel Members and the Pharmaceutical Industry.” Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics 75, no. 3 (2006): 154–60.
Feighner,
John. P., Eli Robins, Samuel B. Guze, George Winokur, Robert A. Woodruff, Jr.,
and Rodrigo Muñoz. “Diagnostic Criteria for Use in Psychiatric Research.” Archives of General Psychiatry 26 (1972): 57–63.
First,
Michael B., Carl C. Bell, Bruce Cuthbert, et al. “Personality Disorders and
Relational Disorders: A Research Agenda for Addressing Crucial Gaps in DSM.” In
A Research Agenda for DSM-V, ed. David J. Kupfer,
Michael B. First, and Darrel A. Regier, 123–200. Washington, DC: American
Psychiatric Association, 2002.
Fombonne,
Eric. “The Epidemiology of Autism: A Review.” Psychological
Medicine 29 (1999): 769–86.
Foucault, Michel. Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason. New York: Pantheon Books,
1965.
Frances,
Allen. “Dimensional Diagnosis of Personality—Not Whether but When and Which.” Psychological Inquiry 4, no. 2 (1993): 110–11.
Frances,
Allen. “DSM in Philosophyland: Curiouser and Curiouser.” AAPP
Bulletin 17, no. 2 (2010), 3–7.
Frances,
Allen. “The DSM-III Personality Disorders Section: A Commentary.” American Journal of Psychiatry 137, no. 9 (1980): 1050–54.
Frankfurt,
Harry G. On Bullshit. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 2005.
Freud,
Sigmund. The Joke and Its Relation to the Unconscious.
New York: Penguin Books, 2003.
Freud, Sigmund. The Question of Lay Analysis: Conversations with an Impartial Person. New York: W. W. Norton,
1989.
Gay,
Peter. Freud: A Life for Our Time. New York: W. W.
Norton, 1988.
Glenmullen, Joseph. Prozac Backlash: Overcoming the Dangers of Prozac, Zoloft, Paxil, and
Other Antidepressants with Safe, Effective Alternatives. New York: Simon &
Schuster, 2000.
Goffman, Erving. Asylums: Essays on the Social Situation of Mental Patients and Other
Inmates.
Garden City, NY: Anchor Books, 1961.
Gould, Stephen Jay. Wonderful Life: The Burgess Shale and the Nature of History. New York: W. W. Norton,
1989.
Greenberg, Gary. Manufacturing Depression: The Secret History of a Modern Disease. New York: Simon &
Schuster, 2010.
Grob,
Gerald N. “Origins of DSM-I: A Study in Appearance and Reality.” American Journal of Psychiatry 148, no. 4 (April 1991):
421–31.
Hales,
Robert E., Stuart C. Yudofsky, and Robert H. Chew. What Your
Patients Need to Know About Psychiatric Medications. Washington, DC:
American Psychiatric Publishing, 2005.
Healy,
David. The Creation of Psychopharmacology. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 2002.
Horwitz,
Allan V., and Jerome C. Wakefield. The Loss of Sadness: How
Psychiatry Transformed Normal Sorrow into Depressive Disorder. Oxford,
England: Oxford University Press, 2007.
Hunt, S. B. “Dr. Cartwright
on ‘Drapetomania.’” Buffalo Medical Journal and
Monthly Review of Medical and Surgical Science 10 (1855): 438–43.
Hyman,
Steven E. “The Diagnosis of Mental Disorders: The Problem of Reification.” Annual Review of Clinical Psychology 6, no. 1 (2010):
155–79.
James,
Henry. Preface. In The Tragic Muse, 3–12.
Digireads.com, 2011.
Jarvis,
Edward. Relation of Education to Insanity. Report.
Washington, DC: Government Printing Office, 1872.
Johnson, Steven. The Ghost Map: The Story of London’s Most Terrifying Epidemic—and How
It Changed Science, Cities, and the Modern World. New York: Riverhead Books, 2006.
Kandel,
Eric R. “The New Science of Mind.” In Best of the Brain from
Scientific American, ed. Floyd E. Bloom, 68–75. New York: Dana Press,
2007.
Kendell,
R. E., J. E. Cooper, A. J. Gourlay, J. R. M. Copeland, L. Sharpe, and B. J.
Gurland. “Diagnostic Criteria of American and British Psychiatrists.” Archives of General Psychiatry 25, no. 2 (1971): 123–30.
Kendler,
Kenneth S. “An Historical Framework for Psychiatric Nosology.” Psychological Medicine 39, no. 12 (December 2009): 1935–41.
Kendler,
Kenneth S: “The Nosologic Validity of Paranoia (Simple Delusional Disorder): A
Review.” Archives of General Psychiatry 37 (1980):
699–706.
Kendler,
Kenneth S., Paul S. Appelbaum, Carl C. Bell, et al. “Issues for DSM-V: DSM-V
Should Include a Conceptual Issues Work Group.” American
Journal of Psychiatry 165, no. 2 (2008): 174–75.
Kendler,
Kenneth S., Rodrigo A. Munoz, and George Murphy. “The Development of the
Feighner Criteria: A Historical Perspective.” American
Journal of Psychiatry 167, no. 2 (2010): 134–42.
Kessler,
Ronald C. “Mild Disorders Should Not Be Eliminated from the DSM-V.” Archives of General Psychiatry 60, no. 11 (2003): 1117–22.
Kessler,
Ronald C., Katherine A. McGonagle, Shanyang Zhao, et al. “Lifetime and 12-Month
Prevalence of DSM-III-R Psychiatric Disorders in the United States: Results
from the National Comorbidity Survey.” Archives of General
Psychiatry, 51, no. 1 (1994), 8–19.
Kim,
Y. S., B. L. Leventhal, Y. J. Koh, et al. “Prevalence of Autism Spectrum
Disorders in a Total Population Sample.” American Journal of
Psychiatry 168, no. 9 (2011): 904–12.
Kirk,
Stuart A., and Herb Kutchins. The Selling of DSM: The
Rhetoric of Science in Psychiatry. New York: A. De Gruyter, 1992.
Kirsch, Irving. The Emperor’s New Drugs: Exploding the Antidepressant Myth. New York: Basic Books,
2010.
Klein,
Rachel G., Daniel S. Pine, and Donald F. Klein. “Resolved: Mania Is Mistaken
for ADHD in Prepubertal Children (Negative).” Journal of the
American Academy of Child & Adolescent Psychiatry 37, no. 10
(October 1998): 1093–95.
Kleinman,
Arthur. “Culture, Bereavement, and Psychiatry.” By Jerry
Wakefield and Michael First 379,
no. 9816 (February 18, 2012): 608–9.
Kowatch,
Robert A., Mary Fristad, Boris Birmaher, Karen Dineen Wagner, Robert L.
Findling, and Martha Hellander. “Treatment Guidelines for Children and
Adolescents with Bipolar Disorder.” Journal of the American
Academy of Child & Adolescent Psychiatry 44, no. 3 (2005): 213–35.
Kraemer,
Helena C., David J. Kupfer, Diana E. Clarke, William E. Narrow, and Darrel A.
Regier. “DSM-5: How Reliable Is Reliable Enough?” American
Journal of Psychiatry 169, no. 1 (2012): 13–15.
Kraepelin,
Emil. Lectures on Clinical Psychiatry. New York:
Hafner, 1968.
Kraepelin,
Emil. “The Manifestations of Insanity.” History of Psychiatry
3, no. 12 (1992): 504–8.
Kupfer,
David J., Michael B. First, and Darrel A. Regier. Introduction. In A Research Agenda for DSM-V, xv–xxiii. Washington, DC:
American Psychiatric Association, 2002.
Kutchins, Herb, and Stuart
A. Kirk. Making Us Crazy: DSM: The Psychiatric
Bible and the Creation of Mental Disorders. New York: Free Press, 1997.
Lahey,
B. B., B. Applegate, K. McBurnett, et al. “DSM-IV Field Trials for Attention
Deficit Hyperactivity Disorder.” American Journal of
Psychiatry 151, no. 11 (1994): 1673–85.
Leibenluft,
Ellen. “Severe Mood Dysregulation, Irritability, and the Diagnostic Boundaries
of Bipolar Disorder in Youths.” American Journal of
Psychiatry 168, no. 2 (February 2011): 129–42.
Leibenluft,
Ellen, Donald S. Charney, Kenneth E. Towbin, Robinder K. Banghoo, and Daniel S.
Pine. “Defining Clinical Phenotypes of Juvenile Mania.” American
Journal of Psychiatry 160, no. 3 (2003): 430–37.
Lethem,
Jonathan. The Ecstasy of Influence: Nonfictions, Etc.
New York: Doubleday, 2011.
LeVay, Simon. Queer Science: The Use and Abuse of Research into Homosexuality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
1996.
Livesley,
W. John. “Confusion and Incoherence in the Classification of Personality
Disorder.” Psychological Injury and Law 3, no. 4
(2010): 304–13.
Lord,
Catherine, Eva Petkova, Vanessa Hus, Weijin Gan, Feihan Lu, and Donna Martin.
“A Multisite Study of the Clinical Diagnosis of Different Autism Spectrum
Disorders.” Archives of General Psychiatry 69, no. 6
(2012): 303–13.
Lyons,
Viktoria, and Michael Fitzgerald. “Asperger (1906–1980) and Kanner (1894–1981),
the Two Pioneers of Autism.” Journal of Autism and
Developmental Disorders 37, no. 10 (2007): 2022–23.
doi:10.1007/s10803-007-0383-3.
McClellan,
Jon. “Commentary: Treatment Guidelines for Child and Adolescent Bipolar
Disorder.” Journal of the American Academy of Child &
Adolescent Psychiatry 44, no. 3 (March 2005): 236–39.
Melville,
Herman. The Confidence-Man: His Masquerade. New York:
New American Library, 1964.
Menninger, Karl A. The Vital Balance: The Life Process in Mental Health and Illness. New York: Viking Press,
1963.
Mewton,
Louise, Tim Slade, Orla McBride, Rachel Grove, and Maree Teesson. “An
Evaluation of the Proposed DSM-5 Alcohol Use Disorder Criteria Using Australian
National Data.” Addiction 106, no. 5 (2011): 941–50.
Meyer,
Adolf. “The Aims and Meaning of Psychiatric Diagnosis.” American
Journal of Psychiatry 74 (1917): 163–68.
Mill,
James. Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind, vol.
2, ed. John Stuart Mill. London: Longmans Green Reader and Dyer, 1869.
Mojtabai,
Ramin, and Mark Olfson. “Proportion of Antidepressants Prescribed Without a
Psychiatric Diagnosis Is Growing.” Health Affairs 30,
no. 8 (August 2011): 1434–42.
Montesquieu,
Baron de (Charles de Secondat). The Spirit of Laws.
Great Books in Philosophy. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 2002.
Moreno,
C., G. Laje, C. Blanco, H. Jiang, A. B. Schmidt, and M. Olfson. “National
Trends in the Outpatient Diagnosis and Treatment of Bipolar Disorder in Youth.”
Archives of General Psychiatry 64, no. 9 (2007):
1032–39.
Narrow,
William E., Donald S. Rae, Lee N. Robins, and Darrel A. Regier. “Revised
Prevalence Estimates of Mental Disorders in the United States.” Archives of General Psychiatry 59, no. 2 (2002): 115–23.
Olmsted,
Frederick Law. Journeys and Explorations in the Cotton
Kingdom, vol. 1. London: Sampson Low and Son, 1861.
Pantony,
Kaye-Lee, and Paula J. Caplan. “Delusional Dominating Personality Disorder: A
Modest Proposal for Identifying Some Consequences of Rigid Masculine
Socialization.” Canadian Psychology 32, no. 2 (1991):
120–35.
Papolos, Demitri F., and
Janice Papolos. The Bipolar Child: The Definitive
and Reassuring Guide to Childhood’s Most Misunderstood Disorder. 3rd ed. New York:
Broadway Books, 2006.
Parker,
Gordon, Max Fink, Edward Shorter, et al. “Issues for DSM-5: Whither
Melancholia? The Case for Its Classification as a Distinct Mood Disorder.” American Journal of Psychiatry 167, no. 7 (2010): 745–47.
Plato.
Phaedrus. Trans. Benjamin Jowett. Teddington, England:
Echo Library, 2006.
Quétel,
Claude. History of Syphilis. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
University Press, 1990.
Regier,
Darrel A. “Diagnostic Threshold Considerations for DSM-5.” In Philosophical Issues in Psychiatry II: Nosology, ed. Kenneth
S. Kendler and Josef Parnas, 285–97. New York: Oxford University Press, 2012.
Regier,
Darrel A., Irving D. Goldberg, and Carl M. Taube. “The De Facto U.S. Mental
Health Services System.” Archives of General Psychiatry
35 (June 1978): 685–93.
Regier,
Darrel A., William E. Narrow, Emily A. Kuhl, and David J. Kupfer. “The
Conceptual Development of DSM-V.” American Journal of
Psychiatry 166 (2009): 645–50.
Robins,
Eli, and Samuel B. Guze. “Establishment of Diagnostic Validity in Psychiatric
Illness.” American Journal of Psychiatry 126, no. 7
(1970): 983–87.
Robins,
Lee N., and Darrel A. Regier. Psychiatric Disorders in
America: The Epidemiologic Catchment Area Study. New York: Free Press,
1991. “Appendix B,” 399–426.
Sadock,
Benjamin J., and Virginia A. Sadock. Kaplan & Sadock’s
Concise Textbook of Clinical Psychiatry. 10th ed. Philadelphia: Wolters
Kluwer/Lippincott Williams & Wilkins, 2008.
Salmon,
Thomas W., Owen Copp, James V. May, E. Stanley Abbot, and Henry A. Cotton.
“Report of the Committee on Statistics of the American Medico-Psychological
Association.” American Journal of Insanity 74 (October
1917): 255–61.
Sandifer,
Myron G., Anthony Hordern, Gerald C. Timbury, and Linda M. Green. “Psychiatric
Diagnosis: A Comparative Study in North Carolina, London and Glasgow.” The British Journal of Psychiatry 114, no. 506 (1968): 1–9.
Schatzberg,
Alan F. “Presidential Address.” American Journal of
Psychiatry 167 (2010): 1161–65.
Schildkraut,
Joseph. “The Catecholamine Hypothesis of Affective Disorders.” American Journal of Psychiatry 122 (1965): 509–22.
Sedgwick,
Peter. “Illness—Mental and Otherwise.” Hastings Center
Studies 1, no. 3 (1973): 19–40.
Shedler,
Jonathan, Aaron Beck, Peter Fonagy, et al. “Personality Disorders in DSM-5.” American Journal of Psychiatry 167, no. 9 (2010): 1026–28.
Shorter, Edward. A History of Psychiatry: From the Era of the Asylum to the Age of
Prozac. New
York: John Wiley & Sons, 1997.
Shorter,
Edward, and David Healy. Shock Therapy: A History of
Electroconvulsive Treatment in Mental Illness. New Brunswick, NJ:
Rutgers University Press, 2007.
Siever,
Larry J., and Howard Klar. “A Review of DSM-III Criteria for the Personality
Disorders.” In Psychiatry Update: American Psychiatric
Association Annual Review, ed. Allen Frances and Robert E. Hales,
279–314. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Press, 1986.
Skodol,
Andrew E., Donna S. Bender, Leslie C. Morey, et al. “Personality Disorder Types
Proposed for DSM-5.” Journal of Personality Disorders
25, no. 2 (2011): 136–69.
Spiegel,
Alix. “The Dictionary of Disorder.” The New Yorker,
January 3, 2005.
“Spitzer
Reassesses His 2003 Study of Reparative Therapy.” Letter from Robert Spitzer.
In Archives of Sexual Behavior. 4th ed. Vol. 41
(2012).
Spitzer,
Robert L. “Can Some Gay Men and Lesbians Change Their Sexual Orientation? 200
Participants Reporting a Change from Homosexual to Heterosexual Orientation.” Archives of Sexual Behavior 32, no. 5 (October 2003):
403–17.
Spitzer,
Robert L., and Jean Endicott. Critical Issues in Psychiatric
Diagnosis. Ed. Robert L. Spitzer and Donald F. Klein, 15–39. New York:
Raven Press, 1978.
Spitzer,
Robert L., Jean Endicott, and Eli Robins. “Research Diagnostic Criteria:
Rationale and Reliability.” Archives of General Psychiatry
35, no. 6 (June 1978): 773–82.
Spitzer,
Robert L., Janet B. W. Forman, and John Nee. “DSM-III Field Trials: I. Initial
Interrater Diagnostic Reliability.” American Journal of
Psychiatry 136, no. 6 (1979): 815–17.
Srole,
Leo, Thomas S. Langner, Stanley T. Michael, Marvin K. Opler, and Thomas A. C.
Rennie. Mental Health in the Metropolis: The Midtown
Manhattan Study. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1962.
Stevens,
Wallace, and Holly Stevens. The Palm at the End of the Mind:
Selected Poems and a Play. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1971.
Stotland,
Nada L. “Presidential Address.” American Journal of
Psychiatry 166 (2009): 1100–04.
Üçok,
Alp, and Wolfgang Gaebel. “Side Effects of Atypical Antipsychotics: A Brief
Overview.” World Psychiatry 7, no. 1 (February 2008):
58–62.
Ullmann,
A. “Pasteur–Koch: Distinctive Ways of Thinking About Infectious Diseases.” Microbe 2, no. 8 (2007): 383–87.
Volkmar,
Fred R., Ami Klin, Bryna Siegel, et al. “Field Trial for Autistic Disorder in
DSM-IV.” American Journal of Psychiatry 151, no. 9
(1994): 1361–67.
Wakefield,
Jerome, and Michael First. “Validity of the Bereavement Exclusion to Major
Depression: Does the Empirical Evidence Support the Proposal to Eliminate the
Exclusion in DSM-5?” World Psychiatry 11 (2012): 3–10.
Wakefield,
Jerome C., Mark F. Schmitz, Michael B. First, and Allan V. Horwitz. “Extending
the Bereavement Exclusion for Major Depression to Other Losses: Evidence from
the National Comorbidity Survey.” Archives of General
Psychiatry 64, no. 4 (2007): 433–40.
Wakefield,
Jerome C., and Robert L. Spitzer. “Lowered Estimates—but of What?” Archives of General Psychiatry 59, no. 2 (2002): 129–30.
Whitaker, Robert. Anatomy of an Epidemic: Magic Bullets, Psychiatric Drugs, and the
Astonishing Rise of Mental Illness in America. New York: Crown, 2010.
Widiger,
Thomas A., and Erik Simonsen. “Alternative Dimensional Models of Personality
Disorder: Finding a Common Ground.” Journal of Personality
Disorders 19, no. 2 (2005): 110–30.
Wilson,
Mitchell. “DSM-III and the Transformation of American Psychiatry.” American Journal of Psychiatry 150, no. 3 (1993): 399–410.
Wing,
Lorna. “Asperger’s Syndrome: A Clinical Account.” Psychological
Medicine 11, no. 1 (1981): 115–29.
Wing,
Lorna. “Reflections on Opening Pandora’s Box.” Journal of
Autism and Developmental Disorders 35, no. 2 (April 2005): 197–203.
Woods,
Scott W., Jean Addington, and Kristin S. Cadenhead. “Validity of the Prodromal
Risk Syndrome for First Psychosis: Findings from the North American Prodrome
Longitudinal Study.” Schizophrenia Bulletin 35, no. 5
(2009): 894–908.
Wozniak,
Janet, Joseph Biederman, Kathleen Kiely, J. Stuart Ablon, Stephen V. Faraone,
Elizabeth Mundy, and Douglas Mennin. “Mania-Like Symptoms Suggestive of
Childhood-Onset Bipolar Disorder in Clinically Referred Children.” Journal of the American Academy of Child & Adolescent
Psychiatry 34, no. 7 (July 1995): 867–76.
Yeargin-Alsopp,
Marshalyn, Catherine Rice, Tanya Karapurkar, Nancy Doernberg, Colleen Boyle,
and Catherine Murphy. “Prevalence of Autism in a U.S. Metropolitan Area.” JAMA: The Journal of the American Medical Association 289,
no. 1 (2003): 49–55.
Zaretsky, Eli. Secrets of the Soul: A Social and Cultural History of Psychoanalysis. New York: Alfred A.
Knopf, 2004.
Zisook,
Sidney, and Kenneth S. Kendler. “Is Bereavement-Related Depression Different
Than Non-Bereavement-Related Depression?” Psychological
Medicine 37, no. 6 (June 2007): 779–94.
Zisook,
Sidney, Steven R. Schuchter, Paola Pedrelli, Jeremy Sable, and Simona C.
Deaciuc. “Bupropion Sustained Release for Bereavement: Results of an Open
Trial.” The Journal of Clinical Psychiatry 62, no. 4
(2001), 227–30.
Zisook,
Sidney, Katherine Shear, and Kenneth S. Kendler. “Validity of the Bereavement
Exclusion Criterion for the Diagnosis of Major Depressive Episode.” World Psychiatry 6, no. 2 (2007): 102–7.
Zucker, Kenneth J., and
Susan J. Bradley. Gender Identity Disorder and
Psychosexual Problems in Children and Adolescents. New York: Guilford Press, 1995.
Leave a Comment